OP THE
Theological Seminary,
PRINCETON, N. J.
sec
^**'*^^> -Dwsion,
f^'»^fJ) Sectior
Bool,
.Mo..,.,.
v/. I
■i^^-C7AHEiVcbi6-
J, .kl. I'lnun^-x^tuT-^C^
THE
COLLECTED WRITINGS
James Henley Thorn well, d.d., ll.d.,
LATE PROFESSOR OF THEOLOGY IN THE THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY
AT COLUMBIA, SOUTH CAROLINA.
EDITED BY
JOHN B. ADGER, D.D.,
PROFESSOR OF ECCLESIASTICAL HISTORY AND POLITY IN THE SAME SEMINARY.
Vol. I.-THEOLOGICAL.
RICHMOND:
PRESBYTERIAN COMMITTEE OF PUBLICATION.
NEW YORK; ROBERT CARTER & BROS. PHILADELPHIA: ALFRED MARTIEN.
LOUISVILLE: DAVIDSON BROS. & CO.
1871.
Entered according to Act of Congress, in the year 1870, by
CHARLES GENNET,
in trust, as
Treasurer of Pcblication of the General Assembly of the Presbyterian
Church in the United States,
in the office of the Librarian of Congress, at 'Washington.
PREFACE BY THE EDITOR.
1. These collected writings of James Henley Thoen-
WELE will probably fill six volumes, of which four will
contain all his Theological works, and be published by the
Presbyterian Cliurch in the United States. The remaining
two will consist of very valuable miscellanea, but it is not
yet determined under whose auspices as publishers they
shall be given to the public. Some of these are metaphys-
ical and some few political ; the major portion are sermons
and sketches of sermons, addresses, etc., etc.
Of the four volumes to be issued by the Presbyterian
Committee of Publication at Richmond, the First may pro-
perly be entitled Theological ; the Second, Theological
AND Ethical; the Third, Theological and Conteo-
VEESiAL ; the Fourth, Ecclesiological.
The present volume contains sixteen Lectures in Theology,
never before printed, besides three separate articles published
during the author's lifetime. All these constitute his dis-
cussion of that portion of Theology which relates to God
and to Moral Government essentially considered, or to the
same as modified by the Covenant of Works. To this vol-
ume, by way of appendix, are added his Inaugural Dis-
course, his Questions on the Lectures to his classes, his
Analysis of Calvin's Institutes and his Examination Ques-
tions thereupon.
The next volume will discuss that portion of Theology
which relates to Moral Government as modified by the
Covenant of Grace. These two volumes are not a treatise
IV EDITOR S PREFACE.
ou Theology written by our distinguished j)rofessor, but
consist of all that he left behind him upon those topics,
gathered together since his decease by the hand of friend-
ship, and systematized as well as possible according to his
conception of the science of Theology. The sixteen Lectures
may be reckoned his very latest productions. Upon some
of the topics in the second volume, what we have to present
the reader will be some of his earlier writings ; there
is not one of them, however, but bears the same impress of
genius — not one of them but is instinct with the same unc-
tion of the Spirit of truth and love.
Accompanying what the second volume will contain upon
the Doctrines of Grace, there will be found a partial discus-
sion of the Morals which necessarily flow out of those doc-
trines. Dr. Thornwell did not write on the other two
departments of Ethics — Justice and Benevolence — but he
wrote and published a separate volume of seven Discourses
on Truth. The place assigned to them in this collection of
all his writings is judged to be logically the most suitable
one.
The third volume will contain an elaborate discussion of
the Canon, the Authority of Scripture, Papal Infallibility,
the Mass, the Validity of Popish Baptism, and the Claims
of the Romish Church to be reckoned any Church at all.
In the discussion of Popish Baptism the author ^^^as led into
a thorough consideration of the Christian doctrine of Justifi-
cation, and hence that whole argument might well have
been placed in the second volume. Connected as it was,
however, by other ties with the Romish controversy, it was
judged best, after mature reflection, to place it in the volume
of the Theological and Polemic writings.
The discussion of the Canon and of Papal Infallibility ap-
peared first in the newspapers, where Dr. Thornwell was
forced to defend himself against Bishop Lynch. His assail-
ant having quit the field, he prosecuted the discussion for a
time, and then published both sides of the controversy in a
volume which is now out of print. These questions have
editor's preface. V
been made to assume in our time a fresh interest, and we
shall hasten to present to the public Dr. Thornwell's very
masterly and learned contributions to their elucidation.
In the fourth volume will be gathered whatever else Dr.
Thorn well has left behind him touching the question of the
Church.
2. The editor is responsible for the correction of numerous
clerical errors in the manuscript lectures and typographical
ones in the printed pieces ; for the arrangement and classifi-
cation of the matter ; for the Table of Contents ; for the In-
dex ; and for the side-headings of the Theological Lectures,
excepting those belonging to Lecture I., which are Dr.
Thornwell's. These side-headings were undertaken in order
to make the remaining lectures correspond in that particular
with the first one. It is hoped they may sometimes assist
beginners in Theology somewhat better to comprehend the
abstruser parts of these Lectures.
3. In the preparation of these volumes the editor has been
indebted for counsel and encouragement to his three col-
leagues, Drs. Howe, Plumer and Woodrow, to Dr. Pal-
mer of New Orleans, and to Stuart Robinson. For im-
portant assistance rendered his thanks are due to Dr. T.
DwiGHT WiTHERSPOON of Memphis. To Dr. J. L. Gi-
rardeau of Charleston he is under special obligations for
the large drafts which he has kindly allowed to be made
continually upon his learning, judgment and taste, and for a
vast amount of actual labour by which he has assisted to
prepare these writings for the press. Dr. Thornwell's
friend, loving and beloved, as well as the editor's, this has
been with him of counse a labour of love ; yet it is proper
here to record this public acknowledgment of the toil he has
without stint bestowed upon these works. There are two
other persons without whose aid this task could never have
been performed. They may not be named here; but the
author, whilst he was with us, was their revered and beloved
friend, and the severest and most protracted literary drudgery
for his sake has been joyfully performed by them. Faith-
vi editor's preface.
fully have they wrought in erecting this monument to our
illustrious dead.
There is still a debt of obligation to be acknowledged.
Soon after the war, informal arrangements with the Messrs.
Carter of New York were entered into for the publication
of these works. It was then expected to collect from the
friends of Dr. Thornwell the means of stereotyping them,
and to present the plates to his widow. Mr. Robert Carter
claimed that he was one of this class, and as a contribution
generously gave his beautiful plates of Thornwell on Truth.
When it was finally concluded, however, to adopt the octavo
form for these collected writings, those plates, being in duo-
decimo, were returned to their liberal donor, and a new edi-
tion has since aj^peared, upon which the customary royalty is
paid to Mrs. Thornwell. Matters stood thus when Dr.
Baird of the Richmond Committee expressed a strong desire
for our Church to own and publish herself the works of her
beloved son, and the idea commended itself so strongly to
the editor's feelings and judgment that he frankly solicited
of the New York publishers a release from his engagements
to them. It was unhesitatingly and very politely granted.
Very recently the same gentlemen were asked to allow the
Discourses on Truth to make part of this collection. The
answer was in these short and pithy terms : " Your letter
was received this morning, and we accede at once and cor-
dially to your request." Not many words are needed to ex-
press a deep sense of so much kindness so kindly done.
It is proper to say that while the stereotype plates of this
collection will belong to our Church, the family of the de-
ceased will receive from the Committee, who bear all the
expenses of printing, binding, etc., a very liberal royalty on
all sales in 'perpetuo.
CONTENTS.
THEOLOGICAL LECTURES.
LECTURE I.
PEELIMINAKY OBSERVATIONS.
Relative importance of the science of Theology. Its Nomenclature
and its Scope.
I. Nomenclature of Theology. Vindication of the term Theology. Its
usage among the ancient Greeks. Patristic usage. Scholastic usage.
Modern usage. Scholastic distinctions of Theology. Komish and Re-
formed Scholasticism.
II. Scope and nature of Theology. 1. Definition of Theology. Is
Theology a science? Its relation to religion. Object of Theology. 2.
Plan of these lectures answering to a threefold division of Theology. 3.
Source of our knowledge of Theology. Principle of Theology according
to Romanists ; according to Rationalists ; according to orthodox Protest-
ants. Respective spheres of Reason and Revelation Page 25
LECTURE II.
THE BEING OP GOD.
The union of all our powers in the recognition of the Being of God.
Religion, or the spiritual knowledge of God, is the highest form of life
and the consummation of our being. The method of proof is to consider
man first as a rational, secondly as a moral, and thirdly as a religious
being.
I. The testimony of speculative reason. The root of this faculty is the
law of causation. This law defined as both a law of thought and a law
of existence. In the Theistic argument the contingency of the world
proves an eternal and necessary cause, and this by immediate inference.
This Cosmological argument vindicated from the charge of soi)histry,
yet defective. The general order and special adaptations in the universe
prove an intelligent cause. This Teleological argument the complement
3
4 CONTENTS.
of the preceding ; and the two comLmed prove the being of an Infinite
Intelligence. The Ontological argument criticised.
II. The testimony of man's moral nature. Personal responsibility in-
fers the Being of God. 1. Commands imply a lawgiver. 2. Duty im-
plies a judge. 3. Sense of good and ill d&sert imjalies moral government.
Hence, Conscience an immediate affirmation of God. It reveals the same
God with reason, but in higher relations.
III. The testimony of man's religious nature. The principle of wor-
ship in man implies the Being of God. Under the Gospel the knowledge
culminates in communion with Him. Thus man finds the complement
of all his powers in a living and personal God. In what sense the know-
ledge of God is innate, li is mediate and representative Page 53
LECTURE III.
man's natural ignokance of god.
Man led to God by the structure of his own being, yet unassisted reason
always ignorant of Him.
I. The nature of this ignorance explained as due to some foreign influ-
ence. Statement and consideration of its two causes : 1, the malignity
of Satan ; and 2, the depravity of our nature. The influence of depravity
(1.) in the sphere of si>eculation — perverting first the reason and then the
imagination ; (2.) in the sphere of morals through a perverted conscience ;
(3,) in the sphere of worship, by means of idolatrous inventions.
II. The profounder ignorance of man's heart even where there is
speculative knowledge. Divine influence the only remedy.
III. The question of the resiionsibility of the heathen for their igno-
rance of God. Heathenism the consummation of depravity in the intel-
lectual, moral and religious nature of man Paye 74
LECTURE lY.
THE NATURE AND LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD.
Two extremes of opinion : that He is perfectly comprehensible and that
He is perfectly incomprehensible. In the middle, betwixt these extremes,
the truth that God is at once known and unknown. As absolute and in-
finite He is unknown, but He is manifested through the finite. As pro-
perties reveal substance, so the finite reveals the infinite. Our concep-
tions of the attributes of God derived from the human soul and embrace
two elements : one positive — the abstract notion of a particular perfection
ascribed to God in the way of analogy and not of similitude ; the other
negative — a protest against ascribing to God the limitations and condi-
tions of man, and a regulative principle at once to warn and to guide.
This relative analogical knowledge of God the catholic doctrine of theo-
logians.
CONTENTS. 5
Tlie objection rebutted tbat this knowledge gives no true representation
of the Divine Being. Equally valid against all knowledge. It is not
only true and trustworthy, but adequate for all the purposes of religion.
Characteristic of man, whether in a state of unmixed probation, of sin, or
of partial recovery. Does not weaken but strengthens the grounds of re-
ligious worship. This relativeness of our knowledge of God in harmony \Jt^ .
with the teachings of Scripture.
It follows that no science of God is possible. The belief of the contrary
is the source of most heresies. Our ignorance of the Infinite solves the
most perplexing problems of Theology., Page, 104
LECTURE V.
THE NAMES OF GOD.
God's nature and perfections disclosed in the use of personal and at-
tributive names. Each one contributes its share to the Ecvelation. They
diminish in number as the Revelation advances. Comparative predomi-
nance of the names Elohim and Jehovah in the Pentateuch. Import of
the name Elohim as indicating the Trinity in Covenant ; — of the name
Jehovah as expressing absolute plenitude of being and His relation to
man as his Redeemer and Saviour ; — of the name Jah as setting forth
God's beauty and glory ; — of the name Adonai as implying dominion
founded in ownership ; — of Shaddai as representing God the Almighty
and Supreme ; — of El as indicating His irresistible power ; — of Elyon as
revealing God as the Most High. The Greek names Kvptoq and feof ex-
plained Page 143
LECTURE VI.
THE NATURE AND ATTKIBUTES OF GOD.
God as He is in Himself cannot be defined. But we may represent our
conceptions of Him in language. He must be conceived of as substance
and attributes. Two definitions of God considered. The best definition
is that of the Shorter Catechism. This, after having a defect supplied,
will best answer the two questions. Quid sit Deus f and, Qualis sit Beus ?
Our notion of the Attributes, whence derived ? These are not separa-
ble from the Essence of God. Said to be all radically one. This is dis-
proved first from the doctrine of the Trinity, and secondly from the law
of our own minds. The distinction of virtual or eminent and real differ-
ence which plays so important a part in theological treatises. Applied
to the question of the oneness of all the Attributes, God is shown to be
eminently all that the universe contains, and accordingly One, but giving
rise to diversity. This is ingenious, but unsatisfactory juggling with scho-
lastic technicalities. We are constrained to make distinctions in the at-
tributes of God, but the whole subject transcends the sphere of our
faculties.
6 CONTENTS.
Since we can know God only as of distinct attributes, some classification
of them is important. Seven schemes of distribution are signalized.
Substantially they are nearly all the same. The fundamental distinction
is between those attributes which refer to God's necessary existence and
those which refer to Him as a Personal Spirit. Classifications of Dr.
Hodge and Dr. Breckinridge considered. The simplest division is
grounded in the distinction between those which pervade the whole
being of God and those which are special and determinative — these latter
being subdivided into intellectual and moral.
It is proposed, accordingly, to treat first of the Nature of God, and then
to unfold the Attributes in the order here set forth Page 158
LECTURE VII.
SPIRITUALITY OP GOD.
This the foundation of all religious worship. Also the foundation of
the Divine attributes. Scripture proof of it. The ancient heathen phi-
losophers concur. Both a negative and a positive truth.
I. It is negative in that it denies to Him the properties of matter.
Ancient and modern Aiithropomorphites. Defence of Tertullian from
this charge. The Anthropomorphism of Scripture explained. The im-
materiality of God implied in the prohibitions to figure Him by images.
II. It is positive in that it affirms Him a person possessed of intelli-
gepce and will. This implies separateness of being in opposition to every
form of Pantheism. The notion of God's spirituality involves — 1. Life in
Himself and necessary activity ; 2. This activity one of thought and will ;
3. The unity and simplicity of His being ; 4. His power of communion
with our spirits ; 5. That He cannot be represented by images. Accord-
ingly, Idolatry is a twofold falsehood Page 173
LECTURE VIII.
THE INCOMJrUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD.
These are universal and all-pervading, characterizing the whole being
and every perfection of God.
I. His Independence. The term used with reference to the grounds
of God's being, and implies that He is uncaused. This mystery not more
incomprehensible than caused being. Both transcend our faculties.
Certain modes of expression regarding this subject criticised. God's in-
dependence involved in every argument for His being. The Scriptures
also presuppose it throughout. It pervades every determinate perfection
of God as well as His being.
II. His Eternity. This term used with reference to the duration of
His being. Vain attempts by the Schoolmen to define it. All our con-
ceptions of it must be purely negative. But these negations cover trans-
cendent excellence.
CONTENTS. 7
III. His Immensity. This term used with reference to tlie extent of
His being. How distinguished from His Omnipresence. Precludes all
mixture with other beings or objects. Not the mere virtual presence of
His power, which is to deny His infinity. The Scriptures full of this
amazing perfection of God, and herein make manifest their own Divine
origin. Special sense in which the Scriptures sometimes speak of God's
presence. His immensity as incomprehensible as His eternity. Practical
uses of the doctrine.
IV. His All-sufBciency. This term used with reference to the contents
of His being. He contains the plenitude of the universe. The sense ex-
plained in which the perfections of all creatures are in Him formally,
eminently or virtually. The value of this truth as a regulative principle
of faith.
V. His Immutability. This applies to the permanence of God's being.
Only another form of asserting the simplicity and oneness of the Infinite.
A self-evident truth, and abundantly proclaimed in Scripture. Appears
to be contradicted by the fact of creation. By reason of our ignorance we
cannot solve the difficulty. The Divine essence not modified by the In-
carnation of the Son, nor by any changes which take place in the universe.
Scriptures which ascribe change to God. Foundation of all our hopes
and fears. It is the immutability of goodness and truth. Disparity be-
twixt God and the creature. Rebuke of arrogance, cavilling and mur-
murs Page 189
LECTURE IX.
CREATION.
Five hypotheses of the relations between the finite and the infinite :
viz. — 1, that of the Atheists ; 2, that of the Eleatics ; 3, that of the Pan-
theists ; 4, that of the Dualists ; 5, that of the Theists. The first two dis-
counted immediately, as having in our times no advocates of considera-
tion. The fourth is also to be discounted at once, as being a disguised
Atheism. The only scheme which remains inconsistent with Creation is
Pantheism, which is the prevailing tendency of modern philosophy.
The fundamental postulate of Pantheism is the impossibility and ab-
surdity of Creation. A fourfold outline of the Pantheistic objections.
All these arguments have the same capital vice of attempting to grasp
what transcends our faculties. The infinite is not to be known, but
believed.
Detailed reply to these objections of Pantheism. The first one shown
to be based on a double misconcej)tion. The second one retorted on the
Pantheists. In the third place, it is shown that Pantheism does not ob-
viate the difficulties which arise from the knowledge and from the will
of God ; that it transcends our power to conceive of the nature of Divine
knowledge or the operation of the Divine will, while yet there are grounds
upon which we can conceive that God might choose to create. Fourthly,
8 CONTENTS.
Pantheism aggravates instead of diminishing the objection to Creation
from the existence of evil by lodging it in God's very nature.
Positive argument for creation from the data of consciousness : 1, The
world has a real, separate existence ; 2, it is finite ; 3, these two imply
that it began ; 4, it had a cause, and that cause the Creator. The inva-
riable tendency of speculation to contradict the most palpable deliver-
ances of consciousness. 5. The Creator must be eternal and necessary.
Only God can create or annihilate. This principle is vital in Theology
and fundamental in the Evidences Page 206
LECTURE X.
Calvin's definition of true wisdom as the knowledge of God and of our-
selves. Man a microcosm. The subject to be considered : I. As to the
distinguishing characteristics of man ; II. As to his condition when he
came from the hands of his Maker ; III. As to the destiny he was to
achieve.
I. Man essentially a person. Keason and Will distinguish humanity
and involve the existence of a soul in man. Vindication of man's im-
mortality upon other than scriptural grounds.
II. The question of man's being created in infancy or with his powers
matured. Pelagian and Popish theories. In puris naturalibus. 1. Adam
not created an infant, either in mind or in body, 2. Not created indif-
ferent to holiness and sin. 3. The indirect testimony of Scri^jture on this
• subject : (1.) Adam had the gift of language in its most difiicult and com-
plicated relations ; (2.) Eve was created a mature woman ; (3.) The pair
received a commission which involved their being mature ; (4.) Adam
was not a rude, warlike, destructive savage. 4. The direct testimony of
Scripture is not definite as to Adam's knowledge of nature, but very ex-
plicit as to his moral condition. A looser and a stricter sense of the ex-
pression, " image of God." The strict and proper sense is holiness mani-
fested in knowledge and righteousness. Adam was endowed with both
the knowledge of God and rectitude of disposition. The Devil has a per-
sonal and spiritual nature, but not the " image of God." In what sense
the holiness of Adam was natural. 5. Adam's holiness was natural, but
not indefectible. The difference between confirmed and untried holiness.
How could the understanding be deceived and the will perverted in the
case of a holy creature ? Several unsatisfactory solutions of this problem
considered : those of Pelagians, of certain Papists and of Bishop Butler.
The Orthodox solution brings in the freedom of man's will. The differ-
ence between freedom not yet deliberately chosen and freedom as a neces-
sity of nature. This is the doctrine of Calvin, of the Confession, of Tiir-
rettin and of Howe, but fundamentally diflerent from the Pelagian.
III. The end of man's creation. Man's relation to God was that of a
servant Page 223
CONTENTS. 9
LECTURE XI.
MORAL GOVERNMENT.
The subject of consideration is — I., the essential principles of moral go-
vernment ; and II., Avhat is implied in the relation of a servant.
I. The essentials of moral government are — first, that the moral law
should be the rule of obedience ; and secondly, that rewards and punish-
ments should be distributed on the principle of justice. The notion of
justice is founded in our moral nature. Analysis of conscience into three
cognitions : 1, the perception of right — an act of the understanding ; 2,
the feeling of obligation — which belongs to the emotions ; 3, the conviction
of merit or demerit — a sentence passed by the mind upon itself. These
are logically distinguishable, but fundamentally the same. The sense of
good and ill desert is a jDrimitive notion. It is an indissoluble moral tie
which binds together merit and right, demerit and wrong. This morail
principle of administration constitutes government moral. Conscience
expresses itself in hopes as well as fears, but obliterates all claims from a
past righteousness. It demands perfect obedience, and counts all other
null. The creature's whole immortal life is one, and at whatever moment
its perfection is lost, all is over. Eepresentation an admissible, yet not
necessary, principle of pure moral government.
II. The relation of servant. Three differences betwixt a servant and a
son : 1, the expectation of a servant is based on his own merit — of a son
on the fullness of Divine benevolence ; 2, the access of a servant to God is
not full and free and close like that of a son ; 3, to a servant the law
si^eaks of obligations, to a son of privileges.
These views of moral government and the relation of a servant are
scriptural. Exposition of Romans ii. 6-11, and of Ezekiel xxxiii. 12, seq.
Moral government to be carefully distinguished from moral discipline.
The law knows no discipline but growth. Discipline provides for the
formation of holy habits and the eradication of propensities to evil. The
law knows how to punish, but not to reform. It knows no repentance ;
once a sinner, always and hopelessly a sinner. Four distinctions between
government and discipline specified. In fine, Discipline is of Grace —
Government, of Nature Page 252
LECTURE XII.
THE COVENANT OF WORKS.
The way is now open to examine the peculiar features of the dispensa-
tion vinder which man was placed immediately after his creation. The
servant was to become a son, and so there was grace in the first covenant
as truly as in the second. Although the adoption was of grace, yet it
must also be a reward of obedience, for man was not to be arbitrarily pro-
moted. An important modification of the general principles of moral
10 CONTENTS.
government is introduced by which probation is limited as to time. This
brings into the Divine economy a new feature, viz. — justification. These
are free acts of God's bounty, and accordingly are matters of pure revela-
tion, as the religion of man must always be. The dispensation under
which these modifications of moral government are introduced is called
the Covenant of Works.
This covenant defined, and the precise sense given in which the term
covenant is applied to this dispensation. The two essential things of the
covenant.
Prior to the discussion of these, another modification of moral govern-
ment is considered, by which the probation is limited as to the persons in-
terested, and Adam becomes the representative of all his race. This is a
provision of pure goodness. Adam, the root, because to be the head.
Kepresentation of grace. Imputation proceeds from the federal tie and
not from the natural.
Thus two principles have entered which pervade every dispensation of
religion to our race — the principles of justification and imputation — key-
notes both of the legal and evangelical covenants.
I. The fii'st essential of the Covenant of Works is its condition. This
was obedience to a positive precept. Bishop Butler on the difference be-
twixt moral and positive precepts criticised. The real difference stated.
Butler criticised again on the ground of preference of the moral to the
positive. Peculiar fitness of the positive to be the condition of the Cove-
nant of Works. Why the tree of the knowledge of good and evil was
called by that name. The explanation overturns various hypotheses — as
that the effects of the fruit of the two trees were physical effects, and that
the tree of the knowledge of good and evil was a sacrament.
The positive, however, cannot supersede the moral law nor repeal it, for
that law was written upon the heart of man. The positive was added to
the moral, and Adam was placed under a twofold law. Through the posi-
tive the issue to he tried might be determined more speedily and more
fully ; yet it was the whole twofold law, both moral and positive, under
which man was placed. This view confirmed by Scripture. Moreover,
the sanction of the positive must have been wholly unintelligible, unless
the moral law had established the conviction of good and ill desert. Tlie
importance of this whole discussion set forth.
II. The second essential is the promise of the covenant. Moses, respect-
ing it, says nothing directly. But the Scriptures must needs arbitrate,
and both indirectly and positively they do teach what was the promise of
the covenant. Under four heads the Scripture doctrine set forth that the
promise was eternal life. The tree of life was a sacramental seal of the
promise. Warburton's view of the covenant criticised.
III. The penalty of disobedience. Warburton's and two otlier theories
discussed. Tlie true view of the penalty. It includes all pain. It is
death, spiritual, temporal and eternal.
IV. The conduct of man under all this display of Divine benevolence.
CONTENTS. 11
The record is a history of facts. An evil spirit is present. The sin of
man was tlie deliberate rejection of God, aggravated by his relations to
God, by the nature of the act, and by its consequences.
V. The relations of man to the covenant since the fall Page 264
LECTURE XIII. V
ORIGINAL, SIN.
The phrase Original Sin as used in a wide sense by the Westminster
Assembly, in a narrower one by Calvin, Turrettin and nearly all the Ee-
formed. The author of the expression was Augustin, who had three uses
for it. In this lecture it is employed in the narrower sense, yet the notion
of guilt is not excluded. For the question how guilt can precede existence
must be met. It is remitted, however, until the second part of the discus-
sion.
I. How all the early confessions, Lutheran and Reformed, held Original
Sin : 1. As being the very mould of man's nature. 2. As negative, the
destitution of all holy principles ; and as positive, an active tendency to
all evil. These but two sides of one and the same thing. 3. As universal
and all-pervading. But they distinguished between loss of faculties and
extinction of spiritual life. Man retained reason, conscience and taste.
Yet these faculties, though not destroyed, were all weakened. Augustin's
language on this point Avas objectionable. The phrase total depravity used
in two senses, and might be used in a third ; but it never was employed to
signify that men are as wicked as they could be. 4. As hereditary.
The doctrine as thus stated, if true, is appalling ; if not true, it ought to
be easily disproved, for the facts of the case are patent, and the reasoning
short and simple.
The doctrine must be true, but as it may be exaggerated, it should be
examined with the utmost candour and solemnity.
In investigating the facts upon which it is grounded, the first fact en-
countered is, that of the universality of sin. Every human being has often
done wrong. The second is, that in all there is a stronger tendency to evil
than to good. The third is, that the best of men complain of its indwelling
power. The fourth is, that it makes its appearance in the youngest chil-
dren. These extraordinary facts can be explained only upon the doctrine
of Original Sin.
But a tendency to sin may be admitted without confessing the total de-
pravity taught by the Reformers, and the question arises : Is there no
middle ground between Pelagians and the Reformed ? The Sensationalists
have their theory and the Semi-Pelagians theirs, which maintain a natural
ability quite different from that of the Arminians. We must consider,
therefore, if there be really anything good in man.
If there be, he must both perceive the excellence of God and desire to
commune with Him, for both these elements belong to holiness. But
Scripture denies to man both of these, and the experience of all the re-
12 CONTENTS.
newed confirms the Scripture. The case of unrenewed men of high prob-
ity does not at all contradict this testimony ; eminent conscientiousness
may be conjoined with eminent ungodliness. The virtue of the Stoics was
pride; that of Christianity is humility. Holiness and morality differ as
the Ptolemaic and Copernican systems. As the one puts the earth in the
centre, the other the sun, so the one makes man supreme, the other God.
A passage of Miiller on Sin is criticised at length, and four distinctions
pointed out between holiness and morality. In what sense man is capable
of redemption. The real tendencies of human nature are exhibited
amongst tlie heathen. The summing up shows that man is totally desti-
■; tute of holiness and dead in trespasses and sins.
II. The question of hereditary guilt now recurs. There are two ques-
tions : First, how sin is propagated ; Second, how that which is inherited
can be sin. The various theories of Stapfer, Pictet, Turrettin and Edwards
are considered, and the whole difficulty is found to lie in Avhat to these
divines presents no difficulty : viz. — in the imputation of guilt. Respect-
ing this second question, the difficulty is stated in its fullness. Then, by
way of approaching a solution, the question is first considered, whether
hereditary depravity can really be sin. The views of Papists and Remon-
strants, as represented by Bellarmin and Limborch, pass mider review ; also
those of Zwingle, and then of the other Reformed divines. Then the tes-
timony of Scripture is taken, and arguments from Scripture definitions of
sin, and from the relation of inward principle to outward action, and from
death behig the penalty of original sin, are combined to prove that the de-
pravity in which we are born constitutes us really guilty before God. Then
the testimony of our conscience concludes the argument.
Touching the way in which we receive this corruption only two suppo-
sitions are possible : One, that the sinful act which produced it was our
own act ; the other, that it was the act of another.
The question of ante-mundane i^robation is introduced, and Pythagoras,
Plato, Origen, Kant, Schelling, Miiller are quoted as holding that theory.
Two insuperable objections are brought against it, and then it is also shown
to be totally inconsistent with Scripture. It is then considered whether
our relation to Adam may not furnish a ground for imi^utation. Adam
was our natural head, and he was also our federal head, and the only point
to be examined is whether this latter is founded in justice. An affirmative
conclusion has been reached on two different grounds : 1, that of generic
unity ; 2, that of a Divine constitution,
1. If there was a fundamental unity between Adam and his race, it is
clear that he could justly be dealt with as their federal head. He was the
race, and could be treated as the race without any fiction of law. Plere we
see the precise relation betwixt the federal and the natural unity — the
former presupposes the latter. Imputation harmonizes the testimony of
conscience. According to the Scriptures it is immediate and not mediate,
as one class of theologians have taught. Two other statements of the case
are considered, and the conclusion is reached tliat a generic unity between
CONTENTS. 13
Adam and his sons is the true basis of the representative economy in the
Covenant of Works.
2. The second theory of an arbitrary Divine constitution is summarily
dismissed.
How the individual is evolved from the genus which contains it is ac-
knowledged to be a mystery.
The theory of representation alone consists with Scripture and with con-
science Page 301
LECTURE XIV.
THE STATE AND NATURE OF SIN.
Theological importance of the doctrine of the Fall. We can know
neither ourselves, nor God, nor the Redeemer, without appreciating the
moral features of our present ruin.
I. The first question is. What is Sin ? And our first determinations of it
must be objective ones. 1. It is the transgression of the moral law, and
this law is concerned not only with action, but also with the will and with
the dispositions which lie back of it ; with the heart as well as with the
life. 2. It is disobedience to God. 3. It is the contradiction of God's
holiness.
Our second determinations of sin are subjective. Man's relation to God
as the expression of His will and the product of His power is the true
ethical ground of right and wrong. The specific shape which obedience
must take is supreme devotion and undeviating conformity. This supreme
devotion is expressed in Love, yet love does not, as Miiller supposes, ex-
haust the whole of duty towards God. It is the motive, but not the whole
object-matter of obedience. Toward the creature Love is also to be
grounded on the common relation to the Creator. Sin, therefore — 1, in-
volves a denial of dependence on God. 2. The next step is positive es-
trangement from God. 3. Then it resolves itself, thirdly, into self-aifirma-
tion. The whole subjective determination of Sin, therefore, may be stated
as self-afiirmation.
An objection maybe made to this analysis from certain affections in )/f.
man which seem to evince disinterested love. And here divines of New
England have erred, who put self-love for the subjective determination of —
sin, and hold to a reflex operation of the mind in the case of all those af-
fections. But the true explanation is that those elementary principles are
a part of our nature itself, and that they exist back of the will.
It is to be noticed that both the objective and the subjective determina-
tions of Sin coincide and harmonize in Selfishness, which is the root of our
disturbed moral life.
II. But there remains the question, What is the formal nature of Sin ?
1. Some have sought to ground moral distinctions in the Will of God, but
this is itself grounded in His Nature, which is their ti-ue ground. Tlius,
they are eternal and immutable, and they make us to be like or unlike
14 CONTENTS.
God. 2. Some ground them in the tendency to make ourselves or others
happy, but this is to ground them in the creature. If grounded in any
tendency at all, it should be in the tendency to promote God's glory.
But we can neither know our own good, nor the good of others, nor the
glory of God, until we know what Good itself is. And the question recurs,
What is the Right? To this question the answer is, that the Eight is an
original intuition which conscience apprehends, as consciousness the ex-
ternal world and ourselves. Conscience does not make, but declares it.
The right is a reality, but under manifold forms, as truth, justice, benevo-
lence, temperance ; and the common relation of all these to conscience is
grounded in their common relation to the holiness of God. 3. The third
step is to investigate the nature of Holiness. It differs from the right as a
faculty from its object. It is a subjective condition. It is not a single at-
tribute, but is an attribute of all God's attributes, and is the fullness and
unity of His nature. In man holiness is not a detached habit, but a na-
ture, and the Scriptures illustrate it by life. It is supreme devotion to
God as the supreme good. It is the notion of the right carried up to the
notion of the good, and the heart must respond to the conscience in choos-
ing it. The right and the good are objectively the same, and the same
subjectively in all holy things ; but not in sinners, for man has lost the
perception of the good. 4. The fourth step is to consider the nature of Sin
from the same qualitative point of view. It is the not-right. The dis-
tinction of privation and simple negation considered. The Augustinian
doctrine of sin as privation. Peter Lombard quoted. The motive of the
doctrine with Augustin was to vindicate God from the authorship of Sin.
Van Mastricht, De Moor and Burmann quoted. The Master of the Sen-
tences quoted again. The distinction by later theologians of Sin in the
concrete and in the abstract. An expression of Augustin explained. The
Vitringas and Wesselius referred to as refuting and defending this theory.
Objections to the theory : (1) founded on a double confusion ; (2) fails of
the purpose for which it was invented ; (3) contradicts consciousness and
requires an extravagant and shameful distinction ; (4) destroys all real
significance in the creature, and abolishes the distinction between the effi-
cient and the permissive decrees. On these grounds the theory must be
rejected. Moral distinctions not exclusively subjective. There is a prin-
ciple of unity in the life of sin as there is in the life of holiness. It is op-
position to God ; it repudiates His authority, and it commits treason against
His sovereignty.
This qualitative consideration of good and evil conducts to tlie same re-
sults in relation to the nature of Sin reached by estimating its objective
and subjective aspects regarding the law ; and the formal i)rinciple of Sin
is seen to be enmity against God.
III. It has been, assumed throughout this discussion that only a rational
being can sin, but the precise conditions of responsibility remain to be
stated. Holiness demands the living unity of all our higher faculties, and
sin is the perversion of them all. In particular, there is no moral worth
CONTENTS. 15
in acts where tlie consent of the heart and will is not found. But the acts
and the habits which are beyond the control of a sinner's will, are they by
his inability stripped of their sinfulness ? A distinction must be made
here between inability original and inability penal. What the advocates
of what is called natural ability really mean by this term. Man's inability
is the result of his own choice, and is therefore penal. He is competent
only for Sin, but is held responsible for the nature God gave to him ; and
the law of God must ever be the standard of his life. To apostate creatures
actual ability, therefore, can never be the measure of obligation. Two ap-
palling facts of every sinner's consciousness Page 352
LECTURE XV.
THE POLIiXJTION AXD GUILT OF SIN.
Two inseparable properties or effects of sin — pollution and guilt.
1. The notion of the macula or stain of sin exhibits the connection of the
beautiful and the good, the deformed and the sinful. Ground of the con-
nection ethical and not aesthetic. Sin is the real and original ugly, and its
power to make us disgusting is its jjolluting power. As the vile and mean
it makes ashamed. Our sensibility to the estimation in which others hold
us is a clear instance of a moral administration carried on in this life, and
the full elucidation of the filthiness of sin demands that it be explained.
Public opinion abashes us only when it accords with our inward senti-
ments, and was designed to have force only as representing the judgment
of truth. But our own moral nature is never alive to the full shame of sin
so long as we can fancy it concealed. At the judgment sin is to be ex-
posed, and a perpetual source of torture for ever to the wicked will be the
everlasting contempt to which they shall awake.
2. Guilt divided into potential and actual; the one is intrinsic ill desert,
the other condemnation. Popularly it is taken in the former, theologi-
cally in the latter sense. The sense of guilt or remorse contains two ingre-
dients— the conviction that sin ought to be punished, and the conviction
that it will be punished. The second conviction involves the other ele-
ment of guilt — that is, actual condemnation ; for guilt in the conscience is a
present sentence of death by God. The punishment of sin is no less neces-
sary than certain. The object of penal justice is not the reformation of the
offender, but the vindication of law. Scruples about capital punishment
always a sign of moral degeneracy. This account of the sense of guilt in-
volves two propositions — first, one sin entails on us a hopeless bondage to
sin ; second, one sin involves endless punishment. The sense of guilt in-
tolerable now, but two circumstances in the future will add inconceivably
to its terrors — first, it will operate more intensely ; second, it will for ever
reproduce the past at every moment. This illustrated in dreams and the
experience of persons drowning. Nothing ever forgotten. How shall the
lost tolerate for ever their own memory ?
The Scriptures sustain these theological determinations of guilt. With
16 CONTENTS.
out this distinction of the stain and the guilt of sin, we could not under-
stand Imputation, nor the diflerence between Justification and Sanctifica-
tion. This distinction pervades Scripture and lies at the foundation of the
whole scheme of Redemption. A distinction of guilt by Papists approved,
but their use of it condemned Page 400
LECTURE XVI.
DEGREES OF GUILT.
Stoical parados. Testimony of Scripture. Jovinian and Pelagius.
Doctrine of the Reformers and of the Westmmster Assembly. Two
grounds of distinction amongst sins : the first is in the object-matter of the
law ; the second in the subjective condition of the agent. Yet some sins
of ignorance reveal greater malignity than some sins against knowledge.
The erring conscience necessitates sin whether resisted or obeyed, and the
only remedy is spiritual light. A precise scale of iniquity, like that of the
Romish confessional, preposterous and delusive. Sins classified as — 1, of
presumption ; 2, of ignorance ; 3, of weakness — but all malignant and
deadly. The Papal distinction of veiiial and mortal sins. Protestants hold
that no sin is venial in its own nature, yet all, save one, may be cancelled
by the blood of Christ. To a very partial extent a modified sense of the
Papal distinction has been adopted amongst Protestants. The unpardon-
able sin is not final impenitency ; nor insult to the Person of the Spirit ;
nor peculiar to the times of the miraculous efiusion ; but is sin agaiiast the
Spirit in His oflicial character Fage 425
THEOLOGY, ITS PROPER METHOD AND CENTRAL PRINCIPLE.
A REVIEW OF BBECKINBIDGE's OBJECTIVE THEOLOGY.
Thought and action neither contradictories nor opposites, and the great
debater was not unlikely to prove a great teacher of Theology.
^yU The argument from final causes for the being of a God as presented in
-I ' modern systems of Theology not only inconclusive, but pernicious. It
— makes Deity but a link in the chain of finite causes, and degrades the
Creator to the huge Mechanic of the world. Dr. Breckinridge gives to
final causes their true place, which is to set forth the nature and the per-
fections of God ; — given a Creator, we can deduce from them that He is
intelligent and spiritual.
The conception of this book is the grandeur and glory of Theology con-
sidered simply as an object of speculation, which leads the author to sepa-
rate the consideration of the Truth from the consideration of its effects,
and also from the consideration of errors. And it is in this form an
original conception. The clue to his plan is the method of the Spirit in
the production of faith.
CONTENTS. 17
Following Foster in part, Dr. Breckinridge argues illogically against
Atheism.
He concentrates liis energies upon the third book, which treats of the
Nature and Attributes of God. Tlie central ideas of his division of these
are three: viz. — Being, Personal Spirit and Absolute Perfection, And
he makes five classes of Attributes, calling them Primary, Essential, Na-
tural, Moral and Consummate. This division and the nomenclature criti-
cised.
In relation to the great problem of modern philosophy concerning the
Infinite and Absolute, this work takes' very definite ground, and that
ground the safe and true middle, that we know the existence of the Infi-
nite as truly as of the finite, but cannot comprehend it. The views of
Cousin, Hamilton and Kant compared. Dr. Breckinridge's views quoted \i
and strongly commended.
Beginning with a survey of man in his individual and social relations,
and demonstrating his universal and irremediable ruin, this treatise pro-
ceeds in a second book to consider the Mediator in His Person, Offices and
Work ; and as in Christ only we know God, the Divine character, perfec-
tions and glory are the culminating points in Book Third. In another
book the sources of our knowledge of God are consecutively considered,
and then the fifth and last book brings us back to Man in his ruin and
misery. Primeval Innocence, the Covenant . of Works, the Entrance of
Sin, the FaU, Election and Eedemption, are all now discussed in sixty
pages, the rigid method of the author requiring that the philosophy of all
these questions be remitted to his third volume, and that now, for the
most part, only the Scripture facts and doctrines be presented.
The wish expressed that Dr. Breckinridge had dwelt more largely on
the Nature of sin, and particularly the First sin. How a holy creature
could sin is a profoundly interesting question, and it is to be regretted that
the author, with his evangelical views, had not grappled with it like
Bishop Butler, and given us more satisfactory results.
The doctrine of the work respecting hereditary depravity and imputed ■
guilt criticised.
Having viewed the whole treatise, the judgment is expressed that the
author has realized his own ideal as far as it could possibly be done. The
unction of the book is beyond all praise, and it pervades the whole.
The peculiarities of Dr. Breckini-idge's teaching are thus seen to be the
separation of dogmatic from polemic Theology, and the concatenation of
the truths of religion upon the principle of ascent and descent, or induc-
tion and deduction. The question is now raised, whether Dr. Breckin-
ridge's peculiarities as a theological teacher should be copied, and it is
answered in the negative.
In conclusion, the attempt is made to find a central principle which
shall reduce to unity all the doctrines of religion, and Justification is set
forth as that central principle Page 445
Vol. I.— 2
_ V
CONTENTS.
THE PERSONALITY OF GOD.
Ancient representations, uninspired and inspired, tliat God cannot be
known, and a modern one that His very essence is compreliensibility. To
explain such contradictory conclusions, we must understand what has ever
been the problem of Philosoi^hy and the methods by which she has in-
vestigated it. That problem is to unfold the mystery of the universe—
whence it came and how it was produced — being in itself and in its laws
— the causes and the principles of all things. In every such inquiry the
answer must be — God. But when the further question is, What is God, and
how do all things centre in Him ? difierent results are reached, according
to the difierent views of the nature of the universe and its relation to its
cause.
Three ancient theories of the universe stated — the third one named
makes God the essence of all things, and they but manifestations of His
substance.
Modern speculation has pursued essentially the same track, but has
taken its departure from a difierent point. The Material was the ancient
point of departure, but the modern is Consciousness. God is made to be
the complement of primitive cognitions. Thus both ancient and modern
speculation reduces everything to a stern necessity. Pantheism and Posi-
tivism, however differing in other respects, unite to deny a Personal God.
I. What is it to be a Person ? A simple and primitive belief is not to
be defined, but we may describe the occasions on which it is elicited in
consciousness, and the conditions on which it is realized.
1. The first circumstance which distinguishes this notion is Individualitij.
Every instance of knowledge is the affirmation of a self and a not-self.
When we assert the Personality of God, we mean to assert that He is dis-
tinct from all other beings and objects.
2. Intelligence and will belong to the idea of Personality.
3. Absolute Simplicity is equally essential to self-hood.
These are the properties which we affirm in maintaining the Personality
of God. He is an absolutely simple Intelligence, having consciousness and
will, who can say " I am," " I will," " I know," and He is not a blind
fatality, nor a mere necessary princii^le or law.
Tliis statement corrects the ignorant misapprehension that person im-
plies bodily figure or material shape. God is a Personal Spirit.
II. The difTerence immense between admitting and rejecting such a
Being.
1. In the field of Speculation. Pantheism in every form of it deduces all
from God with rigorous necessity, and makes all philosophy a priori and
deductive. The belief of God makes the universe to be whatever He may
will, and philosophy becomes an inquiry into His designs, and the method
of induction becomes the true and only method of inquiry. The counsel
of His will then becomes the goal of philosophy. .
CONTENTS. 19
A comparison of what the inductive philosophy has accomplished, with
the results of Pantheism.
2. In the field of Morals. Theism makes God a ruler and man a sub-
ject. Pantheism deprives us of will and puts us under inviolable neces-
sity. It annihilates all moral diflerence of actions and makes Sin a fiction.
It is hostile to every principle which holds society together, which imparts
to states their authority and to the family its sacredness. S]jeculations
which strike at the Personality of God cannot be harmless.
3. In the field of Religion. To make God everything can be no better
than to make Him nothing. Piety is subverted when there is no object
of its regards. Religion consists necessarily in veneration and love, whicli
must presuppose a Person. The highest form of religion is communion
with God. It comes to an end when you remove a Personal God.
4. As to the credibility of Revelation in itself and in its miraculous cre-
dentials. Intelligence and will controlling subordinate intelligences may
well render miracles necessary. And then if God be a Person, He may
be expected to delight in intercourse with His creatures, for Personality
seeks union Pmje 491
NATUEE OF OUR RELATION TO ADAM IN HIS FIRST SIN.
A REVIEW OF BAIRd's ELOHIM REVEALED.
The central topic of this book is the doctrine of Original Sin. It claims
to relieve the question of hereditary sin of most if not all of its difficulties.
Acknowledging its great merits in other respects, it is pronounced in refer-
ence to its main design a failure. The theory is a numerical identity of
nature between Adam and his posterity, so that his sin is not constructively
and legally, but strictly and properly, theirs. Generation communicates
not a like nature, but the very same. The father substantially and essen-
tially, though not personally, is reproduced in his offspring.
Nothing new in all this — as old as the introduction of Realism into
Theology. The book is a reaction against the entire ciu-rent of modern
thought, both in Theology and philosophy — a formal protest against Nom-
inalism and the spirit of the inductive philosophy grounded in Nominalism,
and also against the received system of orthodoxy grounded in the same.
Statement here of the qualified sense in which the author gives his alle-
giance to Realism.
1. The first j^oint considered is Dr. Baird's notion of nature, and it is
concluded to be the bond of unity to the whole race^ sustaining the same
relation to human persons which the substance of the Godhead does to the
inefiable Three. Adam and his posterity are one substance.
2. The next point is the relation between person and nature — it is that
of efiect and cause ; person is a product of the nature. The person is but
an instrument through which the nature works, and it is no great thing to
be able to say " I."
20 CONTENTS.
3. The third point is the law of generation, which, according to the
author, is such that the first man is the efficient cause of the existence of
all other men. The reasonings of Dr. Baird in relation to the nature of
man resemble those of the Pantheists in relation to the nature of God.
Sundry difliculties in the way of his theory of generation suggested.
Upon these grounds the writer explains our interest in Adam's sin ; it
was strictly ours — as strictly as if committed in our own persons. Adam
was every man, and so every man sinned in Adam. But some other con-
clusions will follow as rigidly as this one : namely — first, that every man
is responsible for every sin of Adam, seeing that his nature was implicated
in every sin of his life ; and secondly, that Adam, penitent and believing,
must have begotten penitent and believing children, seeing that the natui'e
always flows from parent to child as it is in the parent.
The consequences of Dr. Baird's theory to our current theology are —
1. There is no imputation of Adam's sin, but his sin is ours, and we are
held to be actually guilty of it.
2. That the twofold relations of Natural and Representative head in
which Adam stood to the species are confounded.
That the Reformers did not hold such a theory is proved not by quota-
tions, which would require too much room, but by several considerations
— among them that they held our sins to be imputed to Christ. Here
Dr. Baird is forced to retract, and does retract altogether, his entire phi-
losophy of guilt and punishment.
Dr. Baird's theory completely solves all difficulties in relation to heredi-
tary sin ; the only difficulty is in that theory itself. Given a numerical
identity of nature transmitted from father to sons, and the moral condition
of it in tlie one is as inexplicable as in the other. But Adam's children
being not Adam, but themselves, two questions arise which have ever been
difficult to solve : one, how that which now and here begins its being can
begin it in a state of sin without an imputation on the character of God ;
the other, how that which is inherent can be our crime. Dr. Baird exults
in the thought that he has demolished the fortress of Edwards and his
disciples, but while their doctrine has difficulties, his is an absurdity.
There are but three hypotheses supposable : 1, That we had an ante-
mundane being and sinned then, which conditions our mundane liistory ;
2, that we had a being in our substance and committed sin in our sub-
stance, though not in our persons ; 3, that we sinned in another standing
in such relations to us as to make us morally one with him. The first two
remove the difficulty, but substitute a greater one. The third is the
scheme of the Bible.
Dr. Baird's account of the Covenant of Works seriously defective.
His representations of the propagative property of man fanciful, and
also degrading to the Divine image in man Page 515
CONTENTS. 21
APPENDIX A.
Discourse delivered by Dr. Thornwell, upon being inaugxj- \/
RATED AS Professor of Theology Page 573
APPENDIX B.
Questions upon the Lectures in Theology., Page 5S3
APPENDIX C.
Analysis of Calvin's Institutes, with Notes and Comments.
Page 597
APPENDIX D.
Questions on Calvin's Institutes Pat/e 642
PREFATORY NOTE.
Sixteen Lectures are here given to the Public : Lecture I. Preliminary
and setting forth the Nomenclature and Scope of Theology ; Lecture II.
On the Being of God ; Lecture III. On Man's Natural Ignorance of God ;
Lecture IV. On the Nature and Limits of ovir Knowledge of God ; Lecture
V. On tlie Names of God ; Lecture VI. On the Nature and Attributes of
God ; Lecture VII. On the Spirituality of God ; Lecture VIII. On the
Incommunicable Attributes ; Lecture IX. On Creation ; Lecture X. On
Man ; Lecture XL On Moral Government ; Lecture XII. On the Covenant
of Works ; Lecture XIII. On Original Sin ; Lecture XIV. On the State
and Nature of Sin ; Lecture XV. On the Pollution and Guilt of Sin ;
Lecture XVI. On Degrees of Guilt.
Tlie Author proposed to divide Theology into three parts : the first
treating of God and of Moral Government in its essential principles ; the
second of Moral Government as modified by the Covenant of Works ; and
the third of the same, as modified by the Covenant of Grace. These Six-
teen Lectures cover with tolerable completeness the ground of the first
two parts. Death cut short the full execution of his plan. In the good
providence of God, hoAvever, it has been so ordered that the writings he
published during his lifetime may be classified so as to constitute, in
connection with these Lectures, in some degree, a full and systematic pre-
sentation of the whole of Theology, as he conceived of that Science.
Dr. Thornwell prepared these Lectures for his classes in Theology, and
he wrote them all twice over, but he did not prepare them for the press.
This will account for the somewhat fragmentary appearance exhibited in
the closing parts of one or two of them. Sundry loose papers in his hand-
writing being found laid away in some of the Lectures, and marked as
Addenda, they have been put into brackets and inserted, in a different
type, in the margin of the pages where they seemed respectively to belong.
At the opening of Lecture VIII. the Author speaks of his intention to
take up the subject of the Trinity immediately after closing that discussion
of the Attributes ; but this promise was evidently forgotten by him, and
he proceeds at once, in the Ninth Lecture, to the subject of Creation.
Instruction to his classes respecting the Trinity was of course given, Cal-
vin's Institutes being his text-book.
23
Lectures in Theology.
LECTURE I.
PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS.
IF the place of a science depends upon the dignity of its
object, the worthiness of its ends, or the intensity and
purity of the intellectual energies it evokes, the science to
which I am now about to introduce you, must confessedly
stand at the head of all human knowledge. It is conversant
about the sublimest object, aims at the noblest ends, and
calls into play the whole spiritual nature of man. Aris-
totle, from the intrinsic excellence of the being whose reality
and nature it is its business to investigate, pronounced it the
first philosophy and the most exalted of sciences ; Locke
places it " incomparably above all the rest," where it is cul-
tivated according to its own liberal and free spirit, and not
degraded " into a trade or faction ;" and both Aristotle and
Locke regard it " as the comprehension of all other know-
ledge," so that without it all other knowledge is fragment-
ary, partial and incomplete. Let us briefly attend first, to
the nomenclature, and then, to the scope of this science.
I. Its common title is Theology ; a word nowhere found
in the Sacred Scriptures, though the simple
Nomenclature. p -..■., . -, „
terms oi which it is composed are of not
unfrequent occurrence. As it was not the office of inspira-
tion to present the truths of salvation in a scientific form,
25
26 PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. [Lect. I.
no more than it is the office of nature to jiresent the facts of
the universe in a scientific form ; as God
Vindication of the „l • /• ii.1'
^, , never makes science tor us, but only gives
term Theology. ' •' o
US the data out of which we must construct
it for ourselves ; it is not to be expected that a word shoukl
be found in the Scriptures designating a science which it
was not their function to realize. The progress of specula-
tion gives rise to technical terms in religion as well as in
philosophy ; and when they have been introduced to relieve
an obvious need, they are not to be rejected because they
are not expressly written in the Scriptures. Many other
words, such as Original Sin, Trinity, Homoouslan, and Pe7'-
son, as applied to the distinctions of the Godliead, which the
necessities of controversy led the Church to adopt for the
2)urpose of fixing scriptural truth and guarding against the
insinuations of error, are not to be met with in so many
syllables in the Sacred Volume. " They are not there," as
Turrettin ^ remarks, " as to sounds and syllables, formally
and in the abstract ; but they are there as to sense, or the
thing signified, materially in the concrete." " AYhere
names," says Calvin,^ " have not been invented rashly, we
must be^vare lest we become chargeable with arrogance and
rashness in rejecting them." And in reply to those who,
like the ancient heretics, insist upon confining us to the
ipsissima verba of Scripture, to the exclusion of all foreign
terms, we may adopt the language of the same illustrious
Reformer in another passage of the same illustrious book : ^
" If they call it a foreign term, because it cannot be pointed
out in Scripture in so many syllables, they certainly impose
an unjust law — a law which would condemn every interpre-
tation of Scripture that is not composed of other words of
Scripture." Equally judicious are the remarks of Owen,
^\\\o, though persuaded that Theology was not precisely the
term by which the Christian Doctrine should be designated,
was yet content to waive his scruples and to merge his diffi-
1 Loc. I., Quest. 1, ? 2. « i^gt. Lib. I., c. xiii., | 5.
^ Lib. I., c. xiii., ? 3.
Lect. I.] PRELIMIXAEY OBSERVATIONS. 27
culties into acquiescence in prevailing usage. " Many/'
says he/ "pertinaciously oppose the use of the words
theology and theologians. Inasmuch as these words have
been imported from the heathen, and have no counterparts
in the Sacred Scriptures, it is useless to debate about them
with any great zeal. When a name is too pompous and
imposing for the thing to which it is applied, its application
is injurious ; and when its use is a question of keen and in-
genious disputation, the uncertainty which attaches to the
name is apt to be transferred to the thing. Moreover, as
these words have been employed to designate an art and a
class of men skilled in it, inconsistent with the simplicity
of the Gospel, they seem, neither in their origin nor use, to
be adapted to express the Christian Doctrine or its teachers.
Still, as in every inquiry, the subject of it must have some
name, let us, with proper precautions, remain content with
that which common consent has introduced. Let us only
be careful to expound with accuracy the thing which the
name is designed to represent."
Among the ancient Greeks, Theology was applied to any
Cage of the term cbsscrtation, whcthcr in prose or poetry, of
Theology among the whicli the gods wcrc the subjcct. It was
ancient Greeks. • ' < n ~ mi • i • i ■ , i
Aoyo:: Tie[)t oeuu. Iheir genealogies, births
and works, their battles, amours and marriages, were all
called Theology; and the writers who treated of these
matters were all called Theologians. Pherecydes of Syros
was the first who received the name. He was the teacher
of Pythagoras, and wrote a book the title of which has been
variously given, kTzzd/iu-j^oc, dsoxpama, deoyovca, dsoXoyia.
He is said to have been the first person who treated of such
subjects in prose. The poets and mythologists, such as
Homer, Hesiod and Orpheus, were all, in the Greek sense
of the term. Theologians. Aristotle was the first to use
Theology in a scientific sense. He distributed speculative
philosophy into three principal branches — Physics, Mathe-
matics, and Theology ; among which he assigned the first
1 Tlieologoum, Lib. I., c. 1, I 3.
28 PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. [Lect. I.
place to Tlieology, by which he intended to denote the
science of pnre existence, or the science of being as being,
abstracted from all consideration of its sensible accidents.^
Theology with him, therefore, was only another name for
ontology or metaphysics.
The Christian fathers used the term to desiji-nate the
general doctrine concerning God, whether
Patristic usage. °
essentially or j^ersonally considered. Any
one who treated of God and the Holy Trinity was said to
theologixe. They applied it siDecially to the doctrine of the
Divine nature of Jesus Christ in contradistinction from
economy, dcxovofiia, the doctrine of His human nature.
Peter Abelard, in the twelfth century, was the first to
employ the term in reference to the scientific
Scholastic usage. j. .' /» , -, „ -,. . xt
treatment of the truths of religion. He
was followed by the schoolmen, and from them, with occa-
sional protests, sometimes against tlie term itself, and some-
times against the latitude of meaning allowed to it, it has
come down to us.
It is now used in a wider or in a narrower sense. In the
wider sense, it embraces not only a particular
Modern usage. Wide discipline, but all the brauches of know-
sense. i '
ledge that are tributary to it. It includes
whatever is necessary to fit the teacher of religion for his
work — apologetics, hermeneutics, the history of the Church
and of doctrines. Even pastoral care and the composition
and delivery of sermons are considered, in the curriculum of
study, as so many departments of Theology.
Narrow sense. . ' . . . ^ "^
In its narrow sense, it is restricted to a par-
ticular science, the science of Religion.
Before proceeding to a more detailed account of its nature,
it may be well to apprise you of some of the divisions and
distinctions which have been accustomed to be made.
The first is that oi Archetypal and Ectypal. Archetypal
theoloffv has been defined the infinite
Ardietypal and Ec- ^''
typai. knowledge which God possesses of Himself.
^ Metaphys., vi. 1.
Lect. I.] PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. 29
But in this sense, it obviously cannot be the standard or
measure of knowledge to us. It cannot be the pattern to
which ours has to be conformed. Omniscience cannot be
separated from the essence of God, and we should have to
be infinite and self-existent ourselves, before we could know
as God knows. The definition has, therefore, been re-
stricted by others^ to the standard existing as an idea in
the Divine mind of the knowledge which God has willed
that we should attain. He has manifested Himself to intel-
ligent creatures, and manifested Himself for the purpose of
being known. The measure of knowledge which He thus
chooses to communicate is before Him as the archetype or
pattern in conformity Avith which ours must be regulated.
When thus conformed to the Divine ideal, our knowledge
becomes Ectypal — the express image or resemblance of that
which God has proposed as a model.
But even in this sense, it is evident that the idea in the
divine mind can never be the immediate standard of truth
to us. We cannot enter into tlie consciousness of God, and
therefore cannot know His thoughts, as they lie in His infi-
nite understanding, without some medium of external reve-
lation. They must, in some way, be manifested or else re-
main for ever a secret with Himself. That revelation or
manifestation becomes, accordingly, our immediate stand-
ard— that is, the archetype of which our knowledge must
be the immediate ectype or expression. " No doubt," says^
Owen,^ " God has in His own mind an eternal idea or con-
cept of that truth which He wills that we shall attain.
And upon this all our theology depends ; not immediately,
indeed, but upon that act of the Divine will by which it has
pleased Him to reveal this knowledge to us. For no one
has seen God at any time ; the only-begotten who is in the
bosom of the Father, He hath revealed Him.^ The revela-
tion, therefore, of the mind and will of God — ^that is, the
Word — is that doctrine concerning which we treat, in con-
1 De Moor, c. T., ? 7. See also Turrett., Loc. I., Quest. 2, | 7.
* Theologoum, Lib. I., c. iii., § 2. ^ John i. 18.
30 PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. [Lect. I.
forinity with which all our concepts of God, of His worship,
and of the obedience due to Him, must be framed." In other
words, the true archetypal theology is not the idea, as a
thought or concept in the mind of the Eternal, but that idea
as revealed and expressed in the Sacred Scriptures. Hence
archetypal theology resolves itself into what is called the
theologic principle.
Theology has again been divided, according to the condi-
union, Vision, sta- ^^o^ ^^^ wliicli the possessors of it are con-
'^'"°i- templated, into the Theology of Union, the
Theology of Vision, and the Theology of the Stadium.
The Theology of Union is the knowledge of God and of
His will which pertains to the human nature of the Lord
Jesus Christ by virtue of its personal union with the eternal
Word. This knowledge, though finite, is far more perfect
in degree than that which any of the saints can acquire.
He was anointed with the Spirit above measure. Hence,
as implying the unction of the Spirit, it has also been called
the Theology of Unction. The unction of the Spirit, how-
ever, is common with Christ to all believers, and though He
possesses it in a larger measure, it is yet not a term which
designates what exclusively belongs to Him. The Theology
of Union is, therefore, the more distinctive phrase.^
The Theology of Vision, called also the Theology of the
Country, from heaven the dwelling-place of the saints, and
the region in which this theology is enjoyed, is, first, the
knowledge which angels possess who stand in the presence
of God ; and next, the knowledge which the spirits of just
men made perfect possess when translated to their heav-
enly home.^
The Theology of the Stadium is that which pertains to men
while strangers and pilgrims in this mundane state. They
are regarded as running a race ; the goal and the ]irize are
still before them. It is also called the Theology of Travel-
lers, Viatorum, in contrast with the theology of the country,
because its possessors are contemplated as engaged in a jour-
1 De Moor, c. L, § 8. ^ De Moor, c. i., § 9.
Lect. I.] PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIOXS. 31
ney to the eternal world. They seek a city which hath
foundations. From the circumstance, too, that it is depend-
ent upon study as the ordinary means of acquiring and aug-
menting it, it has received the name of the Theology of
Study} This, of course, is the only theology with which
we have to do, and when the term is used without a quali-
fying epithet, it is this alone which is meant. " The term,"
says Turi'ettin, " is equivocally and abusively employed
when it is applied to the false theology of Gentiles and
heretics ; less properly when predicated of the original and
infinite wisdom by which we conceive God as knowing
Himself in an ineffable and most perfect manner (for the
word theology is not competent to exjjress the dignity of
this knowledge), or when applied to the theology of Christ
[that of union], or the theology of angels ; it is properly em-
ployed when applied to the theology of men as travellers."^
Theology has further been distinguished as Natural and
Revealed; these epithets indicating the
Natural and Revealed. i • i i
sources irom which the knowledo-e is de-
rived. In this sense, natural theology is that knowledge
of God and of human duty which is acquired from the
light of nature, or from the principles of human reason,
unassisted by a supernatural revelation. Revealed theol-
ogy, on the other hand, is that which rests on Divine reve-
lation. This distinction is real, but it is useless. There
are truths which reason is competent to discover, as there
are other truths which can only be known by a special com-
munication from God. But tlie religion of man has never
been conditioned exclusively by natural truth. In his un-
fallen condition he was placed under a dispensation which
involved a supernatural revelation. He has never been
left to the sole guidance of his reason, and therefore a mere
natural theology, in the sense indicated, has never been the
sufficient explanation of his state.
Natural Theology has been otherwise defined in con-
tradistinction from Supernatural, as the science of Natural
1 De Moor, c. i., I 10. 2 Lo^. I., Ques. 1, I 9.
32 PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. [Lect. I.
Religion, or the knowledge of that religion which springs
from the relations, whether essential or
natural™^ ''"'^ ^^^^^' instituted, wliicli subsist between God and
the rational creature. It was the theol-
ogy of Adam before the fall— the theology of the covenant
of M'orks ; and though remnants of it still linger in the
human mind, the perfect knowledge of it can only be ob-
tained from the Christian Scrij^tures. Supernatural theol-
ogy is the science of salvation — the doctrines of man's
religion considered as a sinner and as redeemed by the
mediation of Christ. The true contrast, therefore, is not
that of natural and revealed, but that of natural and super-
natural— ^the natural indicating the religion of man in one
aspect ; the supernatural, his religion in another. Both are
equally revealed. The only difference is, that we could
know absolutely nothing of the supernatural without reve-
lation, while we can know something of the natural by the
unassisted light of reason.
The distinction of theology into True and False is sim-
ply, as Turrettin remarks, an abusive ap-
Trne and False. i- x- J? i X^ 1 ^^ J
plication 01 terms, jbrror can be called
science only by catachresis. True Theology is the only
theology, and the doctrines of Pagans, Mohammedans and
Heretics receive the appellation in consequence of their rela-
tion to. the same general subjects.
Theology has been divided, according to its matter, into
TJieoretioal and Practical, or Dogmatic and
Theoretical and -,^71 • i i •
Practical; Dogmatic Moral — the tcrius 111 cach coutrast being
and Moral. vlQq^ syiionymoiisly. The theoretical or
dogmatic treats of the doctrines of religion ; the practical
or moral, of the graces and duties.
According to the manner of treatment, theology has again
Thetic and Antithe- ^ccn divided iuto Thctic aud Antithetic; or
tic; or Didactic and Didactic aud Polcmic ; or Dogmatic and
Polemic ; or Dogmatic , r^ • • i 7-17 1 • rm
aud Polemic, or criti- Fokmic, OY Critical, or ±jlenctic. Ine
cal.orElcnctic. ^^^^ ^^^^ J^^ ^^^.^^ ^f ^.J^ggg COUtrastS, tlictic,
didactic, dogmatic, implies that the doctrines are discussed
Lect. I.] PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. 33
without reference to the controversies to which they have
given rise. The design is simply to state, to prove and to
ilhistrate the truth. The second term, antithetic, j^olemic,
critical, elenetic, implies that the errors of heretics are dis-
tinctly refuted. The mode of treatment is controversial.
The two methods are often combined, and the theology is
then called didactico-polemical, or dogmatico-polemical, or
elenetic. It may be well to remark that the phrase dog-
matic theology does not always bear the sense assigned to it
above. The word oojua may signify either an opinion con-
cerning a doctrine or the doctrine itself. In the former
sense, dogmatic theology is the history of opinions concern-
ing the doctrines of religion. In the latter sense, it is the
scientific statement of the doctrines themselves. In the
former sense, it is principally used in the Church of Rome,
and was so employed by Protestant writers until the com-
mencement of the eighteenth century.^
Theology may be considered as a habit of knowledge
resident in the mind, or as a body of truth
Sulijective and Ob- , j.'ll l Txi^f
. ^jj^.p systematically arranged. in tiie lormer
aspect it is called Habitual, Subjective,
Concrete and Utens ; in the latter it is Objective, Abstract,
Systematic and Docens.
Theology has again been distinguished with reference to
the order and arrangement of its contents.
Scholastic and Posi- l j.i i j. i j? t • ' i
ti^g and the general style ot discussion, into
Scholastic and Positive. "The positive,"
says Marck,^ " is not rigidly restricted to logical rules. The
scholastic proceeds in a method more truly disciplinary, a
most useful and ancient institution." " Positive and scho-
lastic are not to l)e distinguished from each other," says De
Moor,^ " as if the one were conversant about the exposition
of Scripture, and the other a treatise of doctrines and com-
monplaces. For doctrines are obviously to be treated in
the exposition of Scripture, and commonplaces and doc-
trines must depend upon the genuine sense and authority
^ Knapp, vol. i., p. 28, 29. ^ Medull. I., xxv. ^ Comment., c. i., xxv.
Vol. I.— 3
34 PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. [Lect. I.
of Scripture. The true distinction is that Positive Theology
is not strictly confined to logical rules ; it gives itself more
oratorical freedom of style. Scholastic Theology proceeds
in a method more disciplinary [more strictly adapted to
teaching] and reduces Divine truths to certain heads accord-
ing to the rules of logic for the use of Christian schools."
It must be remembered that Marck and De Moor were
both advocates of the Scholastic Theology, and have conse-
quently failed to j3oint out its most objectionable feature.
Its great defect was not its logical method, nor its contempt
of the embellishments of rhetoric, but the manner in which
it used its method. It gave no scope to the play of Chris-
tian feeling ; it never turned aside to reverence, to worship
or adore. It exhibited truth, nakedly and baldly, in its ob-
jective reality, without any reference to the subjective con-
ditions which, under the influence of the Spirit, that truth
was calculated to produce. It was a dry digest of theses
and propositions — perfect in form, but as cold and lifeless as
a skeleton. What it aimed at was mere knowledge, and its
arrangements were designed to aid intelligence and memory.
A science of religion it could not be called.
The most perfect examples of this method — those who, in
the Reformed Church, have been called, by way of emi-
-mence, Scholastics — are the divines of the Dutch school. It
reached its culmination in Gisbert Voetius.^
There arose in the same school in the time of Voetius
another class of divines who, from their method of treating
the truths of religion, were distinguished as Federalists.^
The celebrated Cocceius was the founder
Federalists. /. i . ^ . i • t • i
01 this class. Among his disciples are
ra*iked Burmann, Braun and Witsius. The regulative
principle of their method was the doctrine of the Cove-
nants. They consequently treated religion according to the
historical develoj)raent of the covenants, and infused into
their works a decidedly subjective, experimental s])irit.
The true method of Theology is, no doubt, a combination
1 Ebrards' Cliristl. Dogmat. Abs., ii., ^ 39. ^ Id., ^ 40.
Lect. I.] PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. 35
of the Scholastic and Positive. Truth must be exhibited
warm and glowing from the fullness of the Christian heart.
It must be not nakedly truth, but truth according to god-
liness. The writer must know it, because he has been
taught by the Spirit and feels its power. This living con-
sciousness of its preciousness and sweetness and glory is
absolutely essential to save a system from the imputation of
a frozen formalism. There must be method, but method
without life is a skeleton. Infuse life, and you have a noble
organism.
It may be well to guard you against confounding the
Reformed Scholastics with those of the
Romish Scholasticism. /« t-> mi
Church of Rome. They had this in com-
mon, that they were slaves to a logical method. But they
differed widely in the source from wdiich they derived their
materials, and, of course, in the nature of the materials
themselves. The Reformed Scholastics acknowledged Scrip-
ture as the only infallible rule of faith and practice. Their
problem was to digest, under fit and concatenated heads, the
doctrines and nothing but the doctrines of Scri^iture, with
the inferences that lawfully follow from them. The Scho-
lastic Theology of Rome, on the other hand, received as
authoritative, in addition to Scripture, the opinions of the
Fathers, the Decrees of Councils, the Bulls of Popes, and
even the philosophy of Aristotle. It is commonly divided
into three periods: 1. The period of its rise. It began in
the twelfth century with Peter Lombard's Four Books of
Sentences, in which he compendiously arranges the Theologv
of his time under Distinctions and Sentences, taken for the
most part from Hilary, Ambrose and Augustin. The First
book treats of God, His Unity and Trinity; the Second
treats of Creation, particularly the creation of angels and
men, of Free Will, Divine Grace, and of Sin, both native
and actual ; the Third treats of the Incarnation, of Redemp-
tion, of Faith, Hope, Charity, and of the Ten Command-
ments ; the Fourth treats of the Sacraments and of Escha-
tology. 2. The second period is signalized by the writings
36 PRELIMIxNARY OBSERVATIONS. [Lect. I.
of Albertus Magnus, wlio introduced the philosophy of
Aristotle as a principle or source of authoritative truth in
questions of Tlieology. He flourished in the thirteenth
century, and such was his industry that his published works
fill twent}^-one folio volumes. To the same period belongs
Thomas Aquinas, the celebrated pupil of Albert, who, in his
great work, the Summa Theologice, brought the Scholastic
Theology to perfection. 3. The third period begins in the
fourteenth century, and may be characterized as the period
of frivolous discussions. This was the age of Durandus, the
Doctor Resolutissimus, and of the still more celebrated Duns
Scotus, the Doctor Subtilissimus.
II. Having adverted to these preliminary distinctions in
order that you may be at no loss to under-
Scope of the Scieuce. • i i
stand them whenever you meet with them
in your reading, I now proceed — 1, to define the science ac-
cording to my own conception of its nature ; 2, to develoj)
the plan upon which these Lectures shall be prosecuted ; and
3, to indicate the source from which our knowledge must be
authoritatively derived.
1. I accept the definition, now generally given, that
Theology is the science of religion ; that is.
Definition of Theology. ,.■,'" (, -, ...■,,■•
it IS the system ot doctrine m its logical
connection and dependence, which, when spiritually dis-
cerned, produces true piety. There is a twofold cognition
of Divine truth — one natural, resulting from the ordinary
exercise of our faculties of knowledge, and the other super-
natural or spiritual, resulting from the gracious illumination
of the Holy Ghost. The habit which corresponds to the
first, like every other habit of science, is mere speculative
knowledge. The habit which corresponds to the other i.s
true religion. The doctrine, to use the expressive analogy
of St. Paul,^ is the mould, and religion the image that it
leaves upon the heart, which the Spirit has softened to re-
ceive the impression. There is, first, the truth, and that is
theology ; there is next the cordial and spiritual apprehen-
1 Eom. vi. 17.
Lect. I.] PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. 37
sion of it, and that is the obedience of faith, which is synon-
ymous with true religion. In other words, the truth object-
ively considered is Theology ; subjectively received, under
Divine illumination, it is religion. In relation to religion,
therefore, Theology is a science only in the objective sense.
It denotes the system of doctrine, but not the mode of ap-
})rehension. The cognition which produces the subjective
habit to which Theology corresponds is not knowledge, but
faith ; and depends, not upon speculation, but upon the Word
and the Spirit of God. It knows, not for the purpose of
knowing, but for the purpose of loving.
Some have been unwilling to concede to Theology the
title of Science, partly on the ground above
Objections to calling -Tiijiiii ii-j t j -i
it a Science. indicated, that the habit corresponding to it
is not natural, but supernatural ; and partly
on the ground that it does not spring from principles
of reason, nor proceed by logical deductions. It does not,
in other words, find a place under the Aristotelic definition
of science. These objections are easily discharged. The
first is obviated at once by the simple consideration that
science is used only in an objective sense. And surely no
one will deny that revealed truths constitute a logical and
coherent system. They are mutually dependent and con-
nected, and capable of being digested under concatenated
heads. They form a true theory of religion. In the next
place, it is not to be overlooked that there is a natural
knowledge of theology which is pure science ; which rests in
speculation ; which knows, according to the familiar adage,
only that it may know. This natural knowledge is the in-
strument of spiritual cognition. It is the seed which the
Holy Spirit quickens into vital godliness. We must first
know as men before we can know as renewed men. Theol-
ogy, as thus ending in speculation or in theory, can be
taught, but religion must be implanted.
As to the other objection, it may be replied that science
should not be arbitrarily restricted to systems excogitated
by the wit of man. As one science may begin from prin-
38 PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. [Lect. I.
ciples demonstrated in another, so there is no reason why
that shoukl not be denominated a science which is logically
constructed from the data of faith. We may as readily
accept from revelation as from the intuitions of reason our
first principles. In each case we begin with the indemon-
strable and the given.^
AVith these explanations and distinctions, it is easy to
solve the difficulty which has been raised as to the question
whether theology is a speculative or practical science — whe-
ther its end, in other words, is knowing or doing. Emi-
nent divines have pronounced it to be practical, on the
ground that truth is in order to godliness, or that the end of
the doctrine is the sanctification of the heart. But it must
be recollected that it is not as science that the truth sancti-
fies. It is not the doctrine which transforms by its own
inherent and native energies, but the Spirit by a power
beyond the truth, and of which the truth is only the instru-
ment. If the question be, however, whe-
Nature of Religion. -,,.-, ■, ■, >
ther religion, the supernatural product of
the truth, is speculative or practical, the answer is, that it is
exclusively neither. It is not cognition alone, neither is it
action alone, nor feeling alone. It pertains exclusively
neither to intelligence, emotions nor will, but it is a pecu-
liar state, a condition of life in which all are blended in in-
dissoluble unity. It is at once love, obedience and know-
ledge. Spiritual cognition is not bare knowledge, but it is a
state of the soul which involves all the energies of our be-
ing. It knows by loving and loves by knowing. It dis-
cerns and feels by the same operation. It is a form of
spiritual life which includes and fuses the intellectual, the
active and the emotional elements of our nature. It is the
health of the wdiole soul, the consummation and perfection of
our being ; or, as Solomon expresses it,^ " the whole of man."
Here our faculties all centre and rest with the fullness and
satisfaction of unimpeded exercise. To know is not relig-
1 Thos. Aquin., Sum. Pars Prima, Quest. 1, Art. 2.
2 Eccles. xii. 13.
Lect. I.] PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. 39
ion, to feel is not religion, to do is not religion ; bnt to know
by a light which at once warms and enlightens, which makes
us, at the same time and in the same energy, know and feel
and do — that is eternal life — the life of God in the soul of
man. Logically, we can discriminate the elements which
enter into this unity, but really, they can never be divided or
separated in the exercises of true religion. We can distin-
guish, but we cannot disjoin.
As religion involves in unity, cognition, emotion and will,
there must be some object in which the
qualities adapted to these functions and
energies are indissolubly united. There must be some object
which at once presents truth to the understanding, beauty
and grandeur to the emotions, and rectitude to the will.
There must be some object in which they become one, as
religion is a subjective unity in which they are inseparably
blended. There must be an outward corresponding to the
inward. That object is God.' He is at once the true, the
beautiful, the good. As the true. He addresses Himself to
the intelligence, as the beautiful to the emotions, as the good
to the will. He must be known, and known by spiritual cog-
nition, or there is no religion. " This is life eternal," said
the Divine Teacher,^ " that they might know Thee, the only
true God, and Jesus Christ whom Thou hast sent." He, in
what we are able to know of His character, perfections and
works, is the object of all religion. His will, in its purity
and holiness, is the measure of all duty, and His glory the
standard of all beauty. He is absolutely one ; and truth,
beauty and holiness are one in Him, and therefore one in
the spiritual energies which they evoke in us. It is of the
highest importance to understand that religion is not wholly
subjective and one-sided. It is not a vague sense of depend-
ence, nor a blind craving, nor an indefinite feeling of emp-
tiness and want. It consists of determinate states of con-
sciousness, which can be logically discriminated as those of
intelligence, emotion and will ; and these states are condi-
^ Aquin., Sum. Pars Prima, Quest. 1, Art. 7. ^ John xvii. 3.
40 PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. [Lect. I.
tioiied by conscious relations to an outward object. There
can be no religion without truth ; there can be no religion
without love; there can be no religion without the spirit
of obedience. There must, therefore, be something known ;
something perceived as beautiful ; something acknowledged
as supreme. There must be a determinate object or quality
for each department of our nature. If religion did not de-
mand determinate cognitions, emotions and volitions, dis-
tinct exercises of the spiritual nature conditioned by an
object suited to elicit them, a man might be justly called
religious whatever he believed, however in other respects he
felt, or however he acted, if inwardly he cherished the sen-
timent of vague dependence and want into which the advo-
cates of exclusive subjectivism resolve the essence of j)iety.
It would signify nothing wdiether he believed in one God
or a thousand, whether he worshipped stocks or stones, or
the figments of his own mind; as long as he possessed
a certain indescribable subjective state, he could be called
truly religious.
In our notion of religion, therefore, there are two errors
which we must seek to avoid. The first is, that it is a com-
bination of separable habits ; that the knowledge, love and
obedience involved in it are successive states, which may be
disjoined from each other, but which in their coexistence
constitute piety. This is a mistake. Spiritual cognition
includes the perception of the beautiful and the good. The
same energy wdiich knows God unto salvation knows Him
in the unity of His being as the perfection of truth, beauty
and holiness. The perception of His glory is the effulgence
of this unity.
The second error is, that religion can be understood apart
from its object. It must be distinctly recognized as condi-
tioned and determined by the object. It is the nature and
relations of the object which make it what it is. The know-
ledge of God, therefore, as a manifested object, is the indis-
pensable condition of all true religion. The subjective
states, as conditioned by this object, differ from analogous
Lect. I.] PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. 41
subjective states, as conditioned by other objects, in the cir-
cumstance that in the one case they are or ought to be in-
dulged without measure ; in the other, under limitations
and restrictions. An infinite being demands the homage of
the whole soul ; a finite being, a homage graduated accord-
ing to the degree of its excellence. We must love a creature,
and trust a creature, with a moderated confidence and love.
We must love God and trust God with the whole soul,
strength, and heart. Religion, in other words, contemplates
its object as the infinite and the absolutely perfect. It is
this quality of the object which determines the peculiar
character of our religious energies.
2. Man being the subject and God the object of religion,
it is evident that we can never hope to un-
The Plan of these ^lerstaud itS doctriuCS without kuowiug
Lectures. o
something of both terms of this relation.
Calvin was right in resolving true wisdom into the know-
ledge of God and of ourselves. It' is the relations betwixt
us on which religion hinges. God must be given, man
given, and the relations between them given, in order to
construct a solid science of Theology. It is further evident
that these relations are either such as spring from the very
nature of the beings, giving rise to duties and obligations,
on man's part, that are essential and unalterable ; or such
as have been instituted by the positive will of the Creator.
Given God as Creator and Moral Ruler, and there necessa-
rily emerges a moral government, or a government adminis-
tered on the principle of distributive justice. Rectitude to
a moral creature becomes the natural and unchanging law
of its being. God, however, in His goodness, may transcend,
though He can never contradict, the principle of justice.
He may do more, though He can never do less, than simple
equity demands. If He should choose to institute a dispen-
sation under which a greater good than we had any right
or reason to expect is held out to us, the nature of this dis-
pensation would have to be considered in treating of the
doctrines of religion ; and if more than one such disjiensation
42 PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. [Lect. I.
^ were established, each would have to be considered, and con-
sidered in its historical development, in determining the re-
lations which condition religion. Religion never contem-
plates its object absolutely, but in relation to us ; and insti-
tuted relations are as real, and give rise to as real duties, as
natural.
The Scriptures assure us that two such dispensations ha\'e
been instituted, aiming at the same general end, but contem-
plating man in different states or conditions, and therefore
accomplishing the result by different means. One, called
the Covenant of Works, contemplates man as a moral being,
able to obey and fulfil the will of the Creator ; the other,
called the Covenant of Grace, contemplates man as a fallen
being, a sinner, incapable of propitiating the favour of God.
Both contemplate the exaltation of man to a higher condition
of being, to the adoption of sons into God's family.
A complete Treatise of Theology, according to these state-
Answering to a ments, must fall into three parts: (1.) The
Thieefoui Division of dcvclopment of tliosc csscutial rclations
TllCOlOfiTV,
betwixt God and man out of which arises
a moral government, together with an exposition of the fun-
damental principles of such a government. This part,
embracing the being and character of God, the original state
of man, and his natural duties and obligations, might be
called Preliminary, or Introductory. (2.) The development
of the modification of moral government in its principle and
application, as realized in the Covenant of Works. This
part might be called Natural Religion, as it treats of the
form in Avhich man became related to God immediately
upon his creation. (3.) The development of the Covenant
of Grace or the scheme of Redemption. This part may be
called Supernatural Religion, or the Religion of Grace, and
embraces all that is peculiar to Christianity. To state the
same thing in another form : the first part treats of God and
of moral government in its essential principles ; the second
part treats of moral government as modified by the Covenant
of Works ; the third part treats of moral government as
Lect. I.] PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. 43
modified by the Covenant of Grace. The point of unity
between the two covenants is their concurrence in a common
end ; the point of divergence, the different states in which
man is contemplated. Both are answers to the question,
How shall man be adopted into the family of God ? But
the Covenant of Works answers it with reference to man as
a moral creature, in a state of integrity ; the Covenant of
Grace answers it with reference to man as a sinner, under
the condemnation of the law. These three divisions seem
to me to exhaust the whole subject of Theology.
3. We come now to the question, Whence are we to de-
rive the truths of Theology, and how are
ledgTrTheZgy"" ^c to kuow that they are truths? that is,
What are their sources, and what is their
measure ? It is the question concerning what is called the
Principle of Theology. Three answers have been given —
that of the Romanist, that of the Rationalist, and that of the
orthodox Protestant.
The principle of the Romanist is the authority of the
Church. Nothing, in the sphere of religion,
mruis"^'*^ °^ ^'"^ ^" ^^ ^^ ^® accepted as true or received as an
article of faith, which has not been proposed
and defined by the Church. She still retains the Apostolic
commission, and is the onlv accredited orran of God's
Spirit for the instruction of mankind in all that pertains to
life and godliness. Her voice is heard, first, in the Scrip-
tures, which are not only received upon her testimony, but
are dependent upon her authority for their right to regulate
the faith and practice of mankind. They are absolutely
nothing except as she endorses them and interprets them.
She speaks, in the next place, through the tradition of the
Fathers ; and, finally, through the writings of Doctors, the
decrees of Councils, and the bulls of Popes. The Church,
in this view, is the Supreme Oracle of God. She is the final
depository and infallible teacher of all the truth that pertains
to the salvation of a sinner. She occupies precisely the place
which the apostles occupied in the first age of Christianity.
44 PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. [Lect. I.
It is needless to say that the Theology which thus emerges
is a stiff and lifeless body. Its members are mechanically
joined without the organic unity of life. It is a digest of
aphorisms and dicta, dry as a skeleton and cold as an iceberg.
The whole theory misconceives the office and functions of
the Church. She is the product and not the principle of
truth, and her own claims must be vindicated on the same
grounds on Avhich every other article of faith ultimately
rests. The thcologic principle must lie back of her, or she
could never be recognized as the institute of God. The
truth has made her, she has not made the truth. She is a
teacher, it is true, but she teaches only as she has been
taught ; and the principle of Theology must be sought in
the principle upon which she proposes the doctrines that she
teaches. While, however, the Church is not to be accepted
as an arbiter of faith, Ave must avoid the opposite extreme
of treating her instructions with levity and indifference, as
if she were entitled to no more respect than a private
teacher. Her testimony is a venerable presumption in
favour of the Divine authority of all that she proposes.
As an organic body, having an historical existence grounded
in great truths, having an historic life implicated in these
truths — as she has grown out of them and sprung from
them — it is obvious that they must have pervaded the con-
sciousness of her children, and that her testimony to them
is entitled to a respect analogous to that Avhich attaches to
states and empires concerning their origin, their constitu-
tion and their government. The Church is not an accidental
society that owes its existence to the voluntary compact of
its members. It is not a mere political or moral organiza-
tion. It is a society Avhich has grown out of the facts of
redemption. It is the body of Christ ; and as appointed to
teach, the presumption is that it teaches in His name, and
by His authority, the very truths which lie at the basis of
its own existence. Its own authority is nothing ; it claims
to be only a witness, and its testimony is entitled to pro-
found respect until it has been sJKnvn that it is not sup-
Lect. I.] PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. 45
ported by the Word. It is important that we learn to
venerate the Church. The unhappy division into sects, and
the perverse abuse of the principle of private judgment, have
had a tendency to degrade the Church, in the eyes of many
Protestants, to the level of a mere voluntary society. They
look upon it as an association for religious purposes, analo-
gous to societies for the promotion of temperance or any
other moral end. They overlook its Divine constitution, its
historic connection with the facts of redemption, and its
organic unity as the supernatural product of the Holy
Spirit. They forget that, in its origin and idea, it is the
embodiment of the Gospel. INIelancthon ^ has, in a few preg-
nant W'Ords, happily defined its sphere and jurisdiction :
" As the gospel commands us to hear the Church, so I say
that the assembly in which is the Word of God, and which
is called the Church, must be heard, even as we are also
commanded to hear our pastors. Let us therefore hear the
Church teaching and admonishing, but let us not regulate
our faith by the authority of the Church. The Church has
no right to make articles of faith; she can only teach and
admonish." So also in the Loci Communes, under the
head De Ecclesia : " The Church is, indeed, to be heard as
a teacher, but faith and invocation depend upon the Word
of God, not on human authority. Let us not despise the
Church as teaching, but let us know that the only judge or
arbiter of truth is the Word itself." ^ This testimonial and
teaching function of the Church is a safeguard against rash
innovations, presumptuous speculations and fantastic crudi-
ties, and in this light the Reformers steadily maintained it.
It is a check upon bold and audacious spirits, who, if they
did not hear the Church, might be tempted to indulge in
the most absurd and extravagant excesses of doctrine.'
The principle of the Rationalist is that human reason is
Principle of the Ka- the sourcc aud mcasurc of all religious
*'°"'^"^'^- as of all natural truth. Religion is con-
* De Ecclesia et Auctoritate Verbi Dei. Opera Omnia, Pars Secunda, p. 124.
* Opera Omnia, Pars Prima, p. 129. ^ Loci Com., Ibid.
46 PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. [Lect. I.
sidered simply as a department of philosophy, and noth-
ing is to be accepted in it, any more than in any other
sphere of philosophical inquiry, which does not authenti-
cate itself to intelligence as the explicit evolution of what
is implicitly contained in the human consciousness. Man,
according to this theory, is the measure of the universe.
The difference betwixt the Rationalist and the Romanist
reminds one of the difference noted by Bacon betwixt the
empirical and rationalist philosojDhers. " The empirical
philosophers," says he, " are like pismires ; they only lay up
and use their store. The rationalists are like the spiders ;
they spin all out of their own bowels. But give me," he
adds — and this, as we shall afterward see, illustrates the
Protestant principle — " give me a philosopher who, like
the bee, hath a middle faculty, gathering from abroad, but
digesting that which is gathered by his own virtue."^
The defectiveness of this principle is seen, first, in the
fact that it precludes the supposition of any supernatural
revelation. It construes the human mind into an absolute
standard of the possibility of truth. It authoritatively
pronounces that there can be no intelligible reality beyond
the domain of human consciousness. Theology, according
to this view, can embrace nothing but what we liave called
the introductory or preliminary portion of it. This is the
only field in which mere reflection and analysis can find
materials for working on — the only field in which the data
of science can be extracted from ourselves. If there are
dispensations superinduced by the voluntary goodness of
God, which are solely the offspring of will, and not the
evolutions of eternal principles of rectitude, they can, of
course, only be known by express and positive revelation.
Rationalism undertakes to say that no such dispensations
can exist — that there can be no such transactions betwixt
God and the creature as those implied in the Covenants of
Works and of Grace. The only jjrinciple upon which such
a doctrine can be maintained is the impersonality of God,
^ Apophthegms.
Lect. I.] PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. 47
and the consequent reduction of all the forces in the uni-
verse to a law of blind, immanent necessity. Kationalism,
in other words, if maintained as a logical necessity, subverts
the first principles of Theism.
In the next place, even in the sphere to which it restricts
religious truth, it leaves the theologic development in a very
precarious and unsatisfactory state. If religion is not a habit
of science, but a new and Divine life — if it is not a mode
of speculation, but a new mode of being — the analysis of
our spiritual phenomena, considered as so many manifesta-
tions in consciousness, cannot be expected to give us the key
to that Divine life, that work of the Spirit, which underlies
all these appearances. Indeed, we should have, consist-
ently with Rationalism, to deny the facts of any such life.
The work of the Spirit is as completely subverted as the
gracious dispensations of the Father. But should we ad-
mit that there is nothing in Christian experience transcend-
ing our natural consciousness, still the difficulty of repro-
ducing its phenomena accurately in reflection, and generaliz-
ing the laws upon which they are dej^endent (a difficulty
common to all moral and intellectual speculations), is greatly
enhanced by the mixture of good and evil, the confusion
of holy impulses and remaining depravity, the oscillations
of our hopes and fears, which would render it next to im-
possible to separate the precious from the vile, and to exhibit
in scientific form the real principles which constitute piety.
Hence, unless we are prepared to restrict the possibility of
religious truth to the low sphere of mere natural relations ;
unless we are prepared to limit the condescension and good-
ness of God, and to deny to Him any exercise of free-will
in His dealings w^ith His creatures ; unless we are prepared
to change the very nature of religion, and to make it simply
a development in the sphere of morality and law, — we are
compelled to renounce the principle of the Rationalist as an
inadequate source of theologic truth. There are more things
in heaven and earth than are dreamed of in a narrow philos-
ophy. Given dispensations above nature as conditioning
48 PRELIMIXARY OBSERVATIONS. [Lect. I.
religion, and a revelation express and positive must inter-
vene. Instituted by the voluntary goodness of God, they
can only be known by a communication from Him. Pro-
ducts of free-"\vill, and not the result of thejjature of things,
they can be known only as they are reveal^. Here reason,
however it may authenticate, can discover nothing by its
own light. The relations being given, it can see the duties
and obligations thence arising ; but the facts which consti-
tute the relations, being deductions from no necessary prin-
ciples, have to be accepted as matters of faith. To the extent,
then, that religion involves anything more than the funda-
mental and essential elements of moral government, it in-
volves the necessity of Divine Revelation. God alone is
competent to testify to His own free acts and determinations.
Hence, we are driven to the Protestant doctrine, that the
true principle, the only infallible source
Principle. "^ ^^ ^" ^"^^ mcasure of religious truth, is the Word
of God — such a revelation being neces-
sary to a full and perfect development of the laws which
determine all our spiritual exercises, and absolutely indis-
pensable to furnish the objects out of which most of them
spring. AVhen we speak of Revelation as the final and
ultimate authority in theology, we mean the Sacred Scrip-
tures. JSTothing else can present the credentials without
which the claim to inspiration must be dismissed as uncer-
tified. Tradition can hardly preserve the simplest narrative
from exaggeration or perversion for a single month, and to
suppose that it has transmitted, unimpaired, Christian doc-
trines for eighteen centuries is to suppose a miracle which
we have no right to expect. Writings are the only perma-
nent records of truth, and God has illustrated His infinite
goodness in giving us a perfect and infallible rule of relig-
ious truth in the Scriptures of the Old and New Testaments,
which are His Word. The Bible, therefore, is the Religion
of Protestants — the supreme standard of faith and duty.
The authority of the Bible depends upon the question of its
inspiration, and the final and conclusive proof of that elicits
Lect. L] preliminary observations. 49
a princii^le in Protestantism which exempts its theology
from the dead, traditional formalism of the theology of
Home. That principle is, that the truths of the Bible
authenticate themselves as Divine by their own light.
Faith is an intuition awakened by the Holy Ghost, and the
truth is neither known nor believed until it is consciously
realized by the illuminated mind as the truth of God. In-
tuition does not generate, but it perceives the truth. Rea-
son, under the guidance of the Spirit, appropriates and
digests it. The knowledge is immediate and infallible.
The Bible becomes no longer a letter, but a spirit, and
religion is not a tradition, but a life. Hence, Protestantism
has all the warmth and vigour and spirituality of Ration-
alism, without its dangers of confounding fancies with facts,
dreams with inspiration. The Word supplies an external
test, Avhich protects from imposture and deceit. The Spirit
educates and unfolds a Divine life under the regulative
guidance of the Word. The Bible and the Spirit are there-
fore equally essential to a Protestant theology. Theolo-
gia (says Thomas Aquinas) a Deo docetur, Deum docet, et ad
Deum dudt. It springs from God as the source, treats of
God as its subject, and tends to God as its end.
The respective spheres of Reason and Revelation, accord-
ing to the foregoing views, are very dis-
Reason and Revela- .'.i ii tji i , ■/>
tion, tmctly marked. In the department of
necessary moral truth — that is, of essen-
tial rectitude — reason is a source of knowledo-e ; but as it is
darkened and obscured by sin, its princij)les and deductions
are not infallible. Revelation presents these data, as the
reason would have presented them, in its normal state, free
from uncertainty and error. When so presented, even the
fallen reason accepts them, perceives their autopistic charac-
ter, and rectifies its own aberrations and mistakes. Here
revelation brings out into the clear light of reflection what
before was involved in spontaneous consciousness, but not
distinctly eliminated, or, if eliminated, mixed witli false-
hood. The primitive intuitions of reason are always cer-
VoL. I.— 4
60 PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. [Lect. I.
tain, but it is one tiling to feel their power and quite an-
other to reduce them to formal and precise propositions.
No revelation can contradict them, but it may elicit them
as distinct and manifest phenomena of consciousness.
In the next place, in reference to supernatural dispensa-
tions, reason, though wholly incapable of discovering the
data in the free acts of the Divine Will, yet when these are
once given by revelation as matters of fact, can discern the
obligations which naturally arise from them. It can dis-
cern the fit and becoming, the pulchrum et honestum in the
new circumstances in which we are placed, and it can col-
lect, compare and elaborate into scientific unity the truths
which are brought within its reach. But in no case is rea-
son the ultimate rule of faith. No authority can be higher
than the direct testimony of God, and no certainty can be
greater than that imparted by the Spirit shining on the
Word. An accredited revelation, like an oath among men,
should put an end to controversy.
But the question may arise. Can that be an accredited
revelation which contains things that are contradictory to
reason ? If by reason we are here to understand the com-
plement of those primitive truths and cognitions, with the
legitimate deductions from them, which enter into the uni-
versal consciousness of the race, spontaneously considered,
there is and can be but one answer. These fundamental
facts of consciousness cannot be set aside without annihilat-
ing all intelligence. To deny them, or to question them, is
to reduce all knowledge to zero, or to skepticism. No reve-
lation, therefore, can contradict them without committing an
act of suicide ; it would destroy the very condition under
which alone it can be known and received as a revelation.
But suppose that the laws of intelligence and the jn-imitive
intuitions of the soul are not violated by what jirofesses to
be a Divine revelation, is reason competent to judge, upon
internal grounds, of the truth or falsehood of its contents ?
Here we must make a distinction. The contents of revela-
tion may embrace things that are strictly natural, that fall
Lect. I.] PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. 51
within the sphere of human experience and observation.
There may be alhisions to geography and history, to civil
and political institutions, to the manners, customs and con-
dition of different countries and people. Surely, in relation
to these the human understanding, when furnished with the
proper sources of knowledge, is competent to judge. It de-
serves to be remarked, however, that truth in these respects
is only a presumption but not a proof, of truth in others.
A book may contain no blunders in the sphere of the natural,
and yet not be from God. Neither, on the other hand,
would error in these respects convict a professed revelation
of imposture, unless it claimed to be infallible in all matters.
It is conceivable that God might leave men to themselves
Avhen touching upon subjects within the compass of their
natural powers, and yet supernaturally guard them from
error in all that transcends the sphere of experience. The
contents of a revelation may — indeed to justify its name it
must, contain things that are strictly supernatural — things
"which eye hath not seen, ear hath not heard, neither have
entered into the heart of man to conceive. In relation to
this class of contents, reason has no standard of judgment.
It cannot say beforehand what a revelation ought to contain ;
it cannot even prescribe the form in which it should be
given ; and therefore cannot object to it for containing
things contrary to an arbitrary opinion. The objects of
cognition, both in the natural and supernatural world", must
alike be given. As it is the office of intelligence to study
nature as it is, and not to deny its existence because it hap-
pens not to be what our vain fancies imagine it ought to be,
so it is the office of reason to study the facts of revelation as
they are given, and not to indulge in chimerical speculations
as to what oua-ht or ousjlit not to have been communicated.
The attitude of reason here is simply that of a recipient. It
listens and accepts the Word. As the outer world manifests
itself, and is not created by reason, so the supernatural
world is manifested through revelation, and is not the pro-
duct of speculation. As we depend absolutely upon our
52 PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS. [Lect. I.
senses and faculties for the knowledge of material phe-
nomena, so we must depend absolutely uj)on Divine revela-
tion for all supernatural phenomena. They may be mys-
terious ; that is to be expected. They may be incompre-
hensible; that naturally results from their transcendent
character. But we have mysteries in nature, and we carry
in our OAvn bosoms proofs of a substance whose reality can-
not be doubted, but whose being cannot be fathomed by the
line of human intelligence. The soul and self are as inex-
plicable as the sublime mysteries of Scripture.
But while reason cannot judge of the truth or falsehood
of supernatural data upon any internal grounds, there is an
important function which she may perform. She may illus-
trate the harmony of Divine truth, not only with itself, but
with all other truth. She may show that the same eternal
principles which are exemplified in ISTature are exemplified
also in Grace, and that the same objections which an arro-
gant philosophy arrays against the one press with equal
force against the other. God is one, and however manifold
His works, they must all bear the marks of the same hand.
They are all really, though in different degrees, impressions
of Himself. They are all, in a certain sense. His word.
Reason may also derive an internal proof of the authen-
ticity of Revelation from the beauty, symmetry and glory
of the dispensation it makes known. The supernatural
world is not a chaos. Redemption is not an arbitrary
series of events. A glorious plan pervades it, and the
whole scheme from its beginning to its consummation is a
marvellous exhibition of the manifold wisdom of God.
Unassisted reason, when it inquires in a candid spirit, can
partially discern the traces of Divine intelligence and glory,
but when illuminated by the Spirit it wants no other evi-
dence of Divine interposition. The truth overpowers it
with a sense of ineffable glory, and it falls down to worship
and adore ; for faith is only reason enlightened and recti-
fied by grace.
LECTURE II.
THE BEING OF OOD.^
THERE arethree questions in relation to God which a com-
petent theology must undertake to solve : the first con-
cerns His existence, the second His nature,
the third His perfections, — An sit Deusf
Quid sit Deus f Qualis sit Deus ? We begin with the first.
Religion, which is the spiritual knowledge of God, we
have seen, is not a single energy, intellect-
Religion, the high- i i j.' i j. j. i?
est unfty of our being, ^al, moral or cmotional ; nor a state of
mind in which each energy succeeds the
other so rapidly as to make the impression that it is com-
^ [1. If the amount of speculation which a subject has elicited is any in-
dication of the difficulties which surround it, the question of the Being
of God must be the most difficult within the compass of human inquiry.
It would seem to be the universal sentiment of philosophers, the answer
of SImonides the poet to Hiero the king. But in this case, it is not so
much the difficulty as the transcendent importance of the subject that
has provoked such a mass of discussion. The number of books upon the
elementary question of Theology is perhaps greater than upon any other
topic within the whole sphere of speculation. The controversy with
Atheists has perhaps exceeded in the mass of its contributions the contro-
versy with Deists. The confessed importance of the two inquiries, Is
there a God ? and. Are the Scriptures a revelation from God ? is the secret
of the interest they have elicited.
2. In this case, as in many others, it has happened that the very sim-
plicity of the truth has been an occasion of perplexity. Many have
sought for erudite proofs of what God meant should be plain and ad-
dressed to every understanding. Self-evident truths require no proof;
all that speculation can do is to distinguish them and to indicate the cha-
racteristics which define them. The attempt to i^rove the existence of
matter, of an outward world, of our own souls, is simply absurd. They
authenticate themselves. All that philosophy should undertake is to
53
54 THE BEING OF GOD. [Lect. II.
posed of them all as separate and separable elements. It is
the whole energy of our being carried up to the highest unity.
It is the concentration of our entire spiritual nature into one
show that these are primitive cognitions, and to be received upon their
self-manifestation with an absolute faith. The Being of God is so nearly
a self-evident truth that if we look abroad for deep and profound argu-
ments, or expect to find it at the end of a lengthened chain of demonstra-
tion, we shaU only confuse what is plain, and mystify ourselves with
vain deceit.
3. If the end of our being is religion, if we are made to glorify God
and to enjoy Him for ever, there must obviously be a special adaptation
of our nature to the knowledge of God. If religion is not wholly a de-
lusion, the evidence of the Being of God must lie very close to us. This
was the confession of the ancient philosophers, of Socrates and Plato.
4. Hence, we find that the belief of a Deity has been coextensive with
the race. It is as natural to man to be religious as to be social or politi-
cal. His mind craves a God even more intensely than his heart craves
society. There must, therefore, be something in man which recognizes
the existence of God, without the necessity of laboured and formal dem-
onstrations. It must be an obvious and a palpable truth. The diflicul-
ties which have emerged in speculation have been the result of trying
to be deep where the subject was plain and patent.
5. This is confirmed by the fact that the very same process of specula-
tion which has superinduced doubt in relation to the Being of God, has
also superinduced doubt as to the existence of an outer world and the
existence of our own souls. The arguments which have led men to say
that there is no God, have also led them to deny the reality of any sub-
stance, whether material or spiritual.
6. The result of these skeptical speculations has been not the proof of
the non-existence of God, but the impossibility of proving that He does
exist. There is and can be no demonstration of Atheism. The utmost
that can be done is to affirm that if a God exists we cannot certify the
fact to our own consciousness.
7. There is no doubt that there is an antecedent credibility in favour of
the existence of God, from the fact that this hypothesis is a satisfactory
solution of all the phenomena of the universe. It gives one mystery, the
Divine Being Himself, and solves every other mystery. It pours a flood
of light upon all else besides. It begins with the incomprehensible, but
it ends in the comprehensible. Every other system begins and ends in
the incomprehensible. If the question of God had none but a specula-
tive interest connected with it, this presumption would perhaps be more
readily acknowledged.
8. Revelation is as really a proof of the existence of God as nature.
It is not exclusively a question of natural theology, in the sense of that
theology which depends upon the unassisted light of reason.]
Lect. II.] THE BEING OF GOD. 55
form of life. It is a condition in which intellect, conscience
and heart are blended into perfect union. One exercise
cannot be separated from the others. It is hence neither
speculative nor practical — it is a state in which speculation
and practice completely coincide. If this view of the na-
ture of religion be correct, the cognition of God, who is the
, , , object matter of religion, must be the con-
The knowledge of J .
God, the contiibntion tributiou of all our facultics, and not the
result of any single department of our
nature. Give man mere intellect without conscience, will
or heart, and he could never attain to any just conception
of his Maker. He might comprehend a single relation of
God — that of cause ; but apart from the power necessary to
produce the given effect and the intelligence necessary to
explain the order of the world, he would know nothing of
what his philosophy compelled him to postulate as the first
cause. A God who is merely intelligence and power is no
God at all. He might be sufficient to satisfy the needs of
speculation in the sphere of ontology — a substance among
substances, a cause among causes — but there Avould be no
more impulse to worship Him than there is to worship
the secondary causes which emerge in the same region of
thought. The other faculties necessarily imply intelligence.
There can be no conscience without knowledge — it is a pecu-
liar form of cognition. There can be no emotion without
knowledge — that also is a special form of cognition.
In appreciating the argument for the Being of God it is
important to recollect that each higher de-
esfformTf ufl, ^'^'" g^^^ ^f life cmbraccs all the others. The
animal has all that belongs to the vege-
table, and something more ; the rational has all that belongs
to the animal, and something more ; the moral has all that
belongs to the rational, and something more ; and the re-
ligious has all that belongs to the moral, and something
more. The addition in each case is not something capable
of being detached — it is fused into the other. The two
make a new form of life as simple and as indivisible as each
56 THE BEING OF GOD. [Lect. II.
element separately. The animal is not the vegetable, plus
a something which you can separate from it, but the vege-
table in perfect fusion with the something that modifies it.
In the same way, the rational and the animal are not two
factors which make up a compound in which you can dis-
criminate the precise posture of each, but a whole, as single
and indivisible as each of the factors it combines. But
while every higher includes every lower form of life, and
reduces it to the unity of its own being, yet what is really
inseparable may be considered as logically distinct, and we
may approximate a just view of the higher by apjjrehending
the nature of all the lower it absorbs. Religion, accordingly,
being the highest form of life, constituting
and the consiimniatiou ,i p i^' d ••jII*
ofouriieiucr. ^^^^ '^'^ry periectiou ot our spu-itual bemg,
and fulfilling all the functions ascribed by
the Greek philosophers to their Wisdom, though possessing
a strict and perfect unity, may be considered in reference to
the lower forms of life it includes, and in this way a clearer
notion conveyed than could be attained without this logical
resolution. The best way to authenticate our knowledge of
God is to show that it is the consummation of our beina; —
that without God. man is left a maimed and imperfect crea-
ture. Each element of his spiritual being points to God,
and when all are combined they give, in their normal condi-
tion, the true and living God of Revelation. This method
of presenting the subject is simple and progressive, and the
result when attained is seen to be exactly the being that we
seek. It is felt to be the same God whom every part of our
nature proclaims, since the voice of every j)firt is finally
taken up in the voice of the whole.
In conformity with this method we may look upon man
successivelv as a rational beino;, as a moral
Threefold constitu- ^^j^^^^ ^ ^ rcligious bciug ; and wc shall
see that speculation in its fundamental law
reveals a God; moral distinctions are grounded in His
nature and government ; and religion contemplates Him as
a being of ineffable beauty and glory.
Lect. II.] THE BEING OF GOD. 57
I. Let us consider, first, the testimony of speculative
reason. By speculative reason we mean
The testimony of ^j^^^ principle in man which prompts him
speculative reason. ■•• -i J- a
to account for existing phenomena. His
apprehensive faculties furnish him with the materials of
knowledge ; reason digests these materials into science by
generalizing the facts and ascertaining the causes upon which
they depend. It answers the question, Why things are as
we see them to be ? The root of this faculty is the law of
causation. This law is not, as some philosophers have rep-
resented it, a deduction from experience ; nor is it, as Ham-
ilton imagines, a confession of our impotence to conceive an
absolute commencement. It is a fundamental law of belief
The law of causa- ^7 ^hich the ordcr of existence is made
tion, a fundamental Capable of detcction by human intelligence.
This law is not, as Kant would have us
believe, a merely regulative principle, which adjusted the
relations of our thoughts without any objective validity or
any power to certify that things really were as we thought
them. On the other hand, every law of thought is, at the
same time, a law of existence. If oiu* thoughts represent
real beings, the connections of our thoughts will answer to
the connections of the things. If they represent imaginary
beings, then the connections are connections that would ob-
tain if the things were real. The truth is, intelligence
would be a mere delusion if the fundamental law of reason
were shut up within the limits of a rigorous subjectivity.
It would be impossible to extend our knowledge beyond the
circle of actual experience. Even the testimony of others as
a source of knowledge would have to be excluded, since the
ground upon which we ultimately credit the reports of others
is this same law of cavise and effect. Taking, then, the law
This law is a law ^^ causatiou as at once a law of thought
of existenco, as well and a law of cxistcncc, whenever it sets out
as of thought. o ^ i • mitt
from the real it must necessarily lead to the
real. If we have effects that are real, we must find causes
that are real. In the theistic argument we begin, in the
58 THE BEING OF GOD. [Lect. II.
first place, with beings that are real. We set out from facts
which fall w^ithin the sphere of our experience. We start
from the Avorld around us. Here is being, and being in a
constant state of flux and change. It is being that began.
If it were necessary, it would be immutable. Whatever
necessarily is, necessarily is just as it is and just what it is.
f The contingency of the world is as obvioxis
The contingency of O J
the world proves a ne- as its existcuce. An infinite succession
cessary, eternal cause. ^ ^ . -, ^ i i i •
ot finite and changeable objects is a contra-
diction. If the world began, it must have had a Maker.
The conclusion is as certain as the law of causation. The
conclusion is not that we must think it as having had a
Maker — that to us it is incogitable in any other relation,
though in truth it might have had an absolute beginning —
but that it exists under this condition of having been caused.
To put the argument in another form : If there is any being
at all, there must be eternal, unchangeable, necessary being.
If there is any existence, there must be self-existence to ex-
j)lain it. Either the beings that we see are self-existent, or
they have been made. If they have been made, there must
be a Maker — and as there cannot be an infinite regression
of causes, the Maker must be absolutely underived and self-
sufiicient. This is the argument in a brief compass which
results from the law of causation as applied to the contin-
gency of the world. It is simple, conclusive, unanswerable.
You will perceive that it consists of two elements : one, a
'posteriori, given in experience — the contingency of the world ;
the other, a priori, contained in the constitution of our nature.^
^ [The existence of God is really a cognition of the human soul, like
the cognition of matter or of ourselves. It is so inseparable from the de-
velopment of reason that wherever we find a man, we find one who is not
a stranger to the existence of God, The real problem of Theology is not
to prove that a God exists, as if she were instructing the ignorant or im-
parting a new truth to the mind, but to show the grounds upon which we
are already in possession of the truth. It is to vindicate an existing
faith, and not to create a new one. The belief itself is universal — as uni-
versal as the belief in the soul. However men may differ on other points,
they agree in this. Religion is prior to civilization, and has been justly
represented as the first teacher of the race. The question is : How this
Lect. II.] THE BEING OF GOD. 69
The a jrnori element is a guarantee for the objective validity
of all that the reason in obedience to it deduces from the
other. You can state the argument in the form of a syllo-
gism, but you are not to suppose that the conclusion flows
from the major premise as something contained in it.^ On
the other hand it is simply legitimated by it, and the real
„, , . , ^ ^ . character of the ratiocination is that of im-
The beiug of God is
proved by an immedi- mediate inference. By the very nature of
the reason, in apprehending the world as
contingent we apprehend it as having been originated. We
are not conscious of any succession of ideas at all. It seems
to be an intuition of God, which is awakened in the soul
upon the occasion of its coming into contact with the world.
But God is not an object of intuition. If He were, we
would know Him by some faculty of immediate perception.
We know Him only mediately through a law of reason
which gives His being as an immediate inference from the
facts of experience.
The argument from the contingency of the world ^ is what
, . , Kant has called the cosmological proof.
This cosmological o ^
argument not sophis- Like all tlic othcr proofs from pure reason,
he has pronounced it to be a specious
sophism ; and yet he admits again and again that it is the
necessary progress of our reason. It is certainly remark-
able that our reason should be so constituted as necessarily
to seduce us into error; that in obeying its most urgent and
belief arose, and upon what grounds it may be authenticated ? We shall
attempt to show that it is the necessary oflspring of reason — that it springs
from the very constitution of the soul.]
^ [The argument is not a syllogism, it is not a demonstration ; and God
is not the object of an intuition, but it is an immediate inference, like the
connection between thought and existence. One truth necessarily implies
another, and this necessary connection is intuitively perceived, lleason
is so constructed that as soon as it cognizes any being, it must cognize
God. The inference from one to the other is immediate, intuitive, neces-
sary.]
^ [The argument from the contingency of the world is also developed
by Des Cartes, in another form, as an argument from the imperfection of
the world. It is beautifully expanded by Cousin, p. 127, seq.J
60 THE BEING OF GOD. [Lect. II.
imperative impulses we should only entangle ourselves in
the mazes of delusion, instead of being conducted into the
clear light of truth. If reason in such inquiries were pre-
sumptuous or perverted, if she were acting in contradiction
to her own laws, the fallacious result could be easily ex-
plained. But when it is confessed that she is pursuing the
tendencies of her own nature, that she is imjjelled by the
very nature of her constitution not only to engage in these
speculations, but to draw these very conclusions, the infer-
ence would seem to be that reason was given, not as an
organ of truth, but as a faculty of deceit. The manner in
which Kant undertakes to convict reason of sophistry in the
conduct of the cosmological argument will have no weight
with those who are not imbued with the principles of the
Critical philosophy as to the nature of human knowledge.
He takes for granted that the laws of thought have only a
subjective validity, and that the matter of our knowledge is
only a series of subjective phenomena. Of course the argu-
ment must be deceitful according to a philosophy like this.
It must be admitted, however, that this cosmological ar-
gument fails to give us any other concep-
yet it is defective. , r»/^iii i*
tion of God that that of necessary being.
It stops at His absoluteness. From His necessity and eter-
nity you can infer nothing as to His nature and attributes.
He is the first substance, the cause of all things, while un-
conditioned Himself.
Reason, in obedience to the same law of causation, takes
another step in which she equally sets out
The teleological ar- /> lA e i. c • t^ • •
gy^jpjjj from the lacts ot experience. It is impos-
ble to contemplate the universe, as far as it
falls under our observation, without perceiving that it is
really a kosmos, a scene of order and of law. The most
untutored peasant, as well as the profoundest philosopher,
is alike capable of apprehending the general fact. The
motions of the heavenly bodies, the succession of the sea-
sons, the alternation of day and night, the exquisite organi-
zation of plants and animals, and especially the structure
Lect. II.] THE BEING OF GOD. 61
of the human frame, are such conspicuous manifestations
of order that the most careless observer
General order, , , . , , ,^,
cannot fail to be impressed with it. The
perception of this order does not require a knowledge of
the ends to be answered by it. We may be satisfied that
it exists where we do not understand its ultimate pur-
pose or design. A man ignorant of machinery may feel
that there is a plan in the structure of a watch, or of
a ship, or of a cotton-mill, though he does not compre-
hend the subordination of the parts, nor how the end they
aim at is answered. He may see some ancient monument
of art, and be struck with the order that reigns in it, though
he has no idea of the purpose for which it was intended.
General order is one thing, special adapt-
timis ^^'^ "^ atapta- ^tions are auotlicr. In special adaptations
we know the end and understand the means
by which it is accomplished. The eye as adapted to vision is
an instance of special adaptation ; the stomach as adapted to
the functions of digestion is another. Science is constantly
enlarging our knowledge in the wonderful adaptations of
nature, and science is daily deepening the impression of
general order. Indeed, the tendency of physical science is
to make a god of the law of order — to resolve it into a
primordial necessity which precludes the possibility of any
breach upon its course. Now here is an effect, a phenome-
non, to be accounted for. There must be a cause of this
order, and reason intuitively perceives that
prove an intelligent •j.ii- • J.^ i 1 j_- /> •j_
^g^^gg intelligence is the only explanation oi it,
as necessary being is the only explanation
of contingent being. Order implies thought, purpose, de-
sign. It is the prerogative of mind alone to plan and to
arrange. The adjustment of means to ends is a combina-
tion of reason, and reason knows her own footprints. This
is what Kant calls the physico-theological argument. It is
commonly called the argument from final causes, or the
teleological proof. Kant^ admits that it deserves to be
1 Crit. Pure Keason, p. 383. Bolin's Trans.
62 THE BEING OF GOD. [Lect. II.
mentioned with respect. " It is," he says, " the oldest, the
clearest, and that most in conformity with the common rea-
son of humanity. It animates the study of nature, as it
itself derives its existence and draws ever new strength
from that source. It introduces aims and ends into a sphere
in which our observation could not of itself have discov-
ered them, and extends our knowledge of nature by direct-
ing our attention to a unity, the principle of A^hich lies
beyond nature. This knowledge of nature again reacts
upon this idea — its cause — and thus our belief in a Divine
Author of the universe rises to the power of an irresistible
conviction. For these reasons it would be utterly hope-
less," he adds, " to attempt to rob this argument of the
authority it has always enjoyed. The mind, unceasingly
elevated by these considerations, which, although empirical,
are so remarkably powerful and continually adding to their
force, will not suffer itself to be depressed by the doubts
suggested by subtle speculations ; it tears itself out of this
state of uncertainty the moment it casts a look upon the
wondrous forms of nature and the majesty of the universe,
and rises from height to height, from condition to condi-
tion, till it has elevated itself to the supreme and uncondi-
tioned Author of all."
It must be confessed, however, that this argument, if
taken alone, fails to demonstrate the exist-
snffioienrofTe'Jn "" ^^^^ of au Infinite Author of the universe.
It proves intelligence, but it does not prove
that that intelligence may not be derived. It exhibits God
as arranging the order which prevails. He is only, in the
light of it, the Architect of nature. For all that appears,
matter may have existed independently of His will ; and His
knowledge of it may have been derived from observation
and experience analogous to our own. He may have
studied the jjroperties and laws of the materials He has
used in the structure of the universe, and His power may,
like ours, consist in obedience to the laws of the substances
with which He had to deal. The argument, in other words,
Lect. II.] THE BEING OF GOD. 63
does not conduct us beyond a subtle anthropomorphism.
In itself, therefore, it is incomplete, but when added to the
cosmological which gives us a Creator —
but it complements . „ , ■. T> •
the preceding one, and au luiinite, eternal, necessary Jieing — we
together they demon- perceivc that this Being is intelligent, that
Btrate God. ^ _ °, ^ i i i
He is an almighty Spirit, and that the
thoughts of His understanding have been from everlasting.
Here, too, as in the other case, the argument is an imme-
diate inference from a determinate form of experience, that
of order and beauty, to a designing mind — the inference
being guarantied by a law of thought which is, at the same
time, a condition of existence.
These two arguments exhibit the steps by which, in the
Reason in its nor- sphcrc of specuktiou, the rcasou ascends to
mai use, ascends to ail intellio;ent Autlior of the Universe.
They are steps which, in the normal de-
velopment of reason, would seem to be inevitable. It is
prompted, by its very nature, to inquire into the causes of
things. This is the foundation of all philosophy. Take
away the notion and the belief of cause, and the idea of a
Kosmos becomes absurd, and that of philosophy a palpable
contradiction. Unless, therefore, our reason is a lie, there is
a God who made us and ordained the order which constitutes
the beauty and the glory of the Universe.^ These heavens
and this earth, this wondrous frame of ours and that more
wondrous spirit within, are the products of His power and
the contrivances of His infinite wisdom. External nature,
to reason in her normal state, becomes an august temple of
the Most High, in which He resides in the ftdlness of His
being, and manifests His goodness to all the works of His
hands. I^othing is insignificant, nothing is dumb. The
heavens declare His glory. The firmament showeth His
^ [We must study God in His works, as children who cannot look the
sun in the face behold its image in the limpid stream. Simon., p. 25.
One mav almost define philosophy in all its branches as a method of
reaching the infinite through the finite. Simon., p. 29.
He adds, " all philosophy is full of God, and all the sciences are full of
philosophy."]
64 THE BEING OF GOD. [Lect. II.
handiwork. The day elicits from the countless multitude
of beings revealed by its light a tribute to His praise ; and
the night, with its array of planets, suns, and adamantine
spheres wheeling unshaken through the void immense, utters
a sound which is audible to every ear and intelligible to
every heart. Science, when it has con-
and adores Ilim. /-nt
ducted us to God, ceases to speculate and
begins to adore. All the illustrations which it has gathered
in the fields it has explored are converted into hymns, and
the climax of its inquiries is a sublime doxology.
Among the arguments of speculative reason, it has been
usual to class what has been called the
The ontological i i • i r ^^■^ • j. J j. l,
proof criticised. ontoiogiccd proot. Ihispreteuds to be an
a iwiori demonstration of the existence of
God. It is found, in its germ, in the philosophy of Plato,
and under different forms of development it has been trans-
mitted, through the Schoolmen, to Des Cartes and Leibnitz,
The German philosopher put the last touch to it. Indeed
he has so modified it that it requires careful attention to
recognize, in its new form, the speculations of Anselm, and
even of Plato before him. The new form, as given by
Kant,^ is substantially this : " Perfect being contains all
reality, and it is admitted that such a being is possible ; that
is to say, that its existence implies no contradiction. Now,
all reality supposes existence. There is, therefore, a thing
possible in the concept of which is comprised existence. If
this thing be denied, the possibility of its existence is also
denied, which is contradictory to the preceding." The ar-
gument is thus expressed by Leibnitz himself: " Uns, ex
cujus essentia sequitur existentia, si est jyossibile, id est. Est
axioma identicum demonstratione non indigens. Atqui Deus
est ens ex cvjus essentia sequitur ipsius existentia. Est de-
jinitio. Ergo Deus, si est possible, existet per ipsius conceptus
neGessitatem." This means that God is, if He is possible,
because His possibility — that is to say. His essence itself —
carries with it His existence, and because it would be a
1 Cousin, Pliilos. Kant, pp. 120, seq.
Lect. II.] THE BEING OF GOD. 65
contradiction to recognize this essence and refuse to it
existence.^
To me, the objections of the German critic to the conclu-
siveness of this argument are perfectly insuperable. A sub-
jective necessity of thought implies an objective necessity
of existence only when the thought is a real thing. We
may imagine a being, and attribute to it attributes which
necessarily imply other attributes ; but these attributes can-
not be inferred to have a real existence unless the subject to
which they are ascribed is first postulated as real. We may
conceive a being in which necessity of existence is posited as
an attribute ; but if the subject is only a conception of the
mind, the necessity of being is equally subjective. We can-
not pass from thought to existence unless the thought begins
in existence. " Existence," as Kant has justly remarked,^
" is not an attribute, a predicate which determines tlie idea
of the subject. When I say that God is all-powerful, the
attribute all-poioerful determines the idea of God ; but when
I conceive God as simply possible or real, the idea of Him
rests the same in both cases ; here it is certain the real in-
volves nothing more than the possible. If it were otherwise,
the idea which we have of any thing would not be complete
until we had conceived it as possible. It follows that if I
conceive a being as perfect, I may perplex myself as much
as I please by trying to evolve from the idea the real exist-
ence. The question of existence always remains, and it is
not from the conception of the object conceived as possible
that we can draw the concept of its reality. We are there-
fore obliged to quit the concept of an object if we would
accord to it real existence."
Whatever charm this species of reasoning has for spec-
ulative minds, it is certain that it can ter-
It terminates in « , i • j. l, j. x' mi
empty abstractions. mmatc ouly m empty abstractions. The
truth is, the secret of its influence is the
firm conception and belief of a necessary being as actually
existing which we derive from the cosmological proof.
1 Cousin, Phil. Kant, p. 123. ^ Cousin, ibid., p. 122.
Vol. .1—5
66 THE BEING OF GOD. [Lect. II.
There we start out from the real and are conducted to the
real in this most sublime and overpowering of all concep-
tions. The idea of necessary being never emerges until the
fact of contingent being is given/ and then in this fact the
reason perceives by immediate intuition that the eternal and
independent is given too. Having thus reached the concept
of necessary existence, we proceed to draw inferences from
it as a real characteristic of God.
From the nature of the case, the being of God never can
be demonstrated in the strict and proper sense of the term.
He is contained in nothing. It may be manifested, but not
deduced.
Consigning, therefore, this argument to the tender mer-
cies of the metaphysicians, let us see the
esn owiic \\e pesult to wliicli wc arc conducted bv the
have been conducted. "
other two. If the conclusion which they
yield is an immediate inference guarantied by the funda-
mental law of intelligence, the conclusion inevitably fol-
lows that we can know nothing aright without knowing of
God. He becomes the principmm cognosccnd'i , as well as
the principium cssendi. He is the fountain to which all the
streams of speculation converge. Truth is never reached —
the why is never adequately given until you ascend to Him.
Intelligence finds its consummation in the knowledge of
His name.
II. We come now to a higher spiritual energy or a higher
form of spiritual life. We are to contem-
Conscience in man ^
demands the existence platc man as a moral bciug, and we shall
find that his conscience, still more imper-
[1 We may observe, further, that we do not positively think necessary
being ; we only believe it as the indispensable condition or cause of the
contingent. It does not lie in the consciousness as an absolute dictum —
" There is necessary being ;" but only as a hypothetical consequent — " There
must be if there is contingent being." The whole force of the belief
turns upon this if. Take away contingent being, and consciousness knows
nothing of the necessary. We deny, therefore, the Cartesian assumption
that we have the idea of a necessary being as an original and absolute
datum of consciousness. To admit its hypotlietical character is to resolve
the argument into the cosmological.]
Lect. II.] THE BEING OF GOD. 67
atively than speculative reason, demands the existence of
God. Our moral cognitions are wholly unintelligible upon
any other scheme than that of a personal God. The pecu-
liarity of these cognitions is that they involve the sense of
personal responsibility. The right comes to us in the form
of commands and not of simple propositions ; it is known
as duty ; it is felt to involve the distinction of merit and
demerit, or of rewards and punishments administered upon
the principle of distributive iustice. Now
Three aspects m ^ -"^ ^ •'^
which our moral cog- there are three aspects in which these cog-
nitions lead to the im- j^- . ^^^j. ^^^ immediate inference of a
mediate inference of J J
this just and right- jnst aud rightcous God : 1. Considered as
commands they imply an Author who has
a right to prescribe laws — an Author wdiom we are bound
to obey. A law without a lawgiver is unmeaning jargon.
Conscience appears in us as the organ of an authority not
its own. It is in its normal state the voice of God in the
soul of man. 2. Consider these commands as giving rise to
a sense of duty, and there emerges the idea of a judge to
whom we are responsible. Obligation and superior will are
correlative terms ; where there is no superior will there may
be rectitude, but there cannot be duty. God is in no sense
the subject of obligation. Conscience, then, in proclaiming
a duty proclaims a supreme will. 3. Consider conscience
as giving rise to the conviction of good and ill desert, of
rewards and punishments justly and righteously distributed
in contradistinction from mere pleasures and pains, and you
have first a moral government directly affirmed, and then the
prospect of perfect happiness to the righteous uncondition-
ally held out. This connection betwixt happiness and vir-
tue must be a sheer delusion unless He who promises is
able also to perform ; but He cannot be able to perform un-
less He possesses unlimited dominion over all beings, states
and conditions. Hence emerges the notion of an infinite
and all-powerful Euler, with a will morally determined, as
well as with intelligence and mere benevolence of character.
This is an outline of the argument from our moral
68 THE BEING OF GOD. [Lect. II.
cognitions -which might be impressively expanded. It is
enough to put you in possession of the steps of the reason-
ing. This argument, it is conceded by
Kant and Hamilton rr x i O" •xtt-it tt 'Ij.
upon this argument. ^aut and feir W iHiam Hamilton, is con-
clusive and irresistible. In conscience
they recognize an immediate affirmation of God. How
upon the principles of the Kantian philosophy it is any
more valid than the arguments from speculative reason, I
am unable to comprehend. If intelligence is false in its
fundamental utterances, it is difficult to see upon what
ground the veracity of conscience can be consistently main-
tained. If man's nature is a lie in one respect, it may be a
lie ill the other. Falsus in uno, falsus in omnibus.
But Avhat I wish particularly to impress upon you is,
that as man rises to a higher sphere of
In the higher sphere ^ ^ • -i
of life man rises to Spiritual lifc, lic nscs to more precise and
uons of God Tnd To clefinitc couccptious of the character and
the sense of responsi- attributes of God, and lias the highest
evidence that the subject which he cog-
nizes in the sphere of speculation is precisely the same
subject that meets him in the sphere of duty. To the
notions of intelligence and goodness are now added the
notions of rectitude, of justice, of will. To the relations
of a Creator and great First Cause are now added the rela-
tions of law, of responsibility, of moral government, of
rewards and punishments. Every element of personality
is now secured. We have a Being tliat knows, that wills,
that judges. Then, as in the notion of the ultimate felicity
of virtue there is implied an absolute dominion over all
things that exist, the God whose law is virtue is seen to be
the same as He who created the heavens and the earth, and
gave to them their exquisite beauty and order. There is
no pretext for saying that intelligence reveals one God and
conscience another. In the notion of responsibility, they
both meet, and are found to be one and the same.
The sense of responsibility, or the authority of conscience,
is perhaps the argument most efficacious of all in keeping
Lect. II.] THE BEING OF GOD. 69
alive the sense of God. As long as it is implicated in
the conviction of duty, men must obliterate
Conscience an argu- J '
ment for God in our from their miuds all moral distinctions
homes and bosoms. i/> ,i , •, p,i iTf«r»
belore they can get quit ot tlie beliei oi
a God. It is an argument which we carry with us. It is
in our homes and our bosoms. We need not ascend into
heaven to seek the Author of the moral law, nor descend
into the deep to learn the mystery of His being. The
Word is nigh us, in our hearts and in our mouths.
If this reasoning be just, we perceive that all moral
philosophy must find its ultimate ground
God the ground of -^^ q^^_ rpj^^ distiuctiouS of mOral gOOd
all moral distinctions, o
and the soul of every aucl cvil arc a riddlc, au enigma, an in-
social and political in- tit -pi • r^ -\
etitution. explicable mystery, it there is no God.
The entire system of social order, the fab-
ric of government, the criminal jurisprudence of states be-
comes unmeaning, or is reduced to a mere system of pru-
dential and precautionary measures to prevent j)hysical
hurt. Take away God, and, considered in his ethical con-
stitution, man becomes the sport and the scandal of the
universe. He is au enormous lie, and those very elements
of his being in which he exults that he is superior to the
brutes, — those grand conceptions of the true, the good, the
just — are mere chimeras, which foster a pride that in the
eyes of those who know his real condition makes him
ridiculous, and cheats him of pleasures that he might enjoy,
by .empty phantoms. But if the law of causation in the
world of speculation and the law of duty in the moral
world are true and faithful witnesses — and these are the
principles which guarantee the argument in their respective
spheres — then as certainly as man has a reasonable soul, so
certainly there is a God. He cannot explain himself with-
out God. He perceives »s clearly as the light of the sun that
either he himself is a mere bundle of contradictions, or he
was made in the image of a supreme Creator, who is holy
and wise and good. Speculative reason might perplex
itself about the first substance, but when conscience speaks
70 THE BEING OF GOD. [Lect. II.
the personality of God is as plain as the law of duty. He
is felt to be no primordial necessity, no self-developing life
of nature, no soul of the world ; but He is Jehovah, dis-
tinct from all and yet pervading all — the everlasting God
who speaks and it is done, who commands and it stands fast.
III. There is still a higher form of life than that of in-
. tellio-ence or duty. There is a state of
The testimony of o J
man's highest form of tlic soul wliicli calls out cvcry Spiritual
energy in delighted and unimpeded exer-
cise. It transfers to the elements of intelligence and obli-
gation an element borrowed from the heart. It is the ele-
ment of love — an element involving not only tlie cognition
of the true, the just, the right, but the cognition of the
beautiful and glorious. Rectitude is no longer appre-
hended as a duty, and clothed in the cold garb of author-
ity ; it comes to us in the freshness and sweetness of life,
and we delight in it as the highest and purest energy of the
soul.^ This new form of life is religion. To know that
there is a God is not to be religious ; to know that virtue is
our law is not to be religious ; even to practise from the
sense of obligation is not to be religious. You must con-
template God under the forms of beauty — the beauty of
holiness — and imitate His life of spontaneous and blessed
rectitude before you become truly religious. Hence, in
religion every department of our nature is called into play,
and called into play under the law of love, or worship, or
adoration. Now when our nature reaches this stage, the
knowledge of God as existing becomes a fixed element of
our consciousness. We have the witness in ourselves. But
this stage is never perfectly reached in this life, and no-
, where reached at all, except among those
Tlie principle of / x o
worship universal in who arc illuminated by the grace of the
gospel. But in all men there exist traces
1 [The religious nature manifests the identity of the object of its wor-
ship with the God revealed in conscience, tlirough the medium of the
notion of rectitude, which is the measure of holiness objectively consid-
ered. The moral ruler of conscience is the God of beauty and glory of
the heart.]
Lect. II.] THE BEING OF GOD. 71
of the principle of worship — there exist sentiments of
pious veneration which show what man's nature normally
is, and which serve to complete the argument from the
human soul for the being of God. Men everywhere
must worship. They feel that their being is not complete
without an object of worship. Hence the schemes of
superstition, of idolatry; hence the temples, the altars,
the sacrifices which exist among all people. Hence,
too, the systems of Divination, of Sorcery, of Magic.
There is a tie which binds man to the spiritual world.
He craves communion with it and resorts to vain eiforts to
penetrate its mysteries. As the religious principle exists
in the form of a blind craving where it has any develop-
ment in the life, we can conclude nothing from it as to the
character of the beino; it seeks. Having lost the element
of a genuine adoration, grounded in the ineifable holiness
of God, it creates objects for itself that are but the reflec-
tion of the moral state of the worshipper's own soul. But
the reliy-ious sentiment does certainly prove
If man s nature is ~ •' J-
to worship, there must that tlicrc uiust be au objcct corrcspoudiug
to it. If it is the nature of man to wor-
ship, there must be a being to be worshipped, or that nature
is again a lie. But when this law of worship is developed
under the gospel, it becomes not merely the knowledge of
God, but it becomes communion with God. It reveals His
personality in the most convincing light, because we know
that He speaks to us and we speak to Him. It reveals
His glory. Here our knowledge reaches its culmination.
We find the true centre and rest of our being — to glorify
God and to enjoy Him for ever.
I have now given you an outline of the arguments by
_ .,, . ,, , . which man fortifies his faith in the being
Faith in the being O
of God springs out of of God. I havc taken the human soul in
man's nature. i-i /. /••, ••, it/.
tlie higher forms ot its spiritual hie — as
rational, as moral, as religious, and I have shown that the
laws, under which these departments of his being operate
and act, lead necessarily to the immediate inference of a
72 THE BEING OF GOD. [Lect. II.
God, infinite, eternal, necessary, intelligent, moral, volun-
tary, free — a personal Being ineifably glorious in the light
of His holiness. I have pictured the normal progress of
reason, or rather of the whole spiritual man, and I have
shown that man finds the complement of his intelligence,
his conscience and his propensity to worship only in such a
living and personal Jehovah. The argument lies close to him
— so close, that if he can know any thing he can know God.
You can now understand the sense in which the doctrine
In what sense the should bc undcrstood that the knowledge
knowledge of God is of God is inuatc. Thc thcory of innate
ideas in the sense of formed and developed
propositions has been long since exploded. So far as any
objective reality is concerned, the child is born Avith a mind
perfectly blank. Consciousness is dormant until experience
awakens it by the presentation of an object. But though
destitute of formed knowledges, the mind has capacities
which are governed by laws that constitute the conditions
of intelligence. Under the guidance of these laws it comes
to know, and whatever knowledge it obtains in obedience to
them is natural. Now, as the knowledge of God necessarily
emerges from the operation of these laws as soon as our
faculties are sufficiently matured, that knowledge is natural
— as natural as that of the material world or of the existence
of our own souls. We cannot think rightly without think-
ing God. In the laws of intelligence, of duty and of wor-
ship He has given us the guides to His OAvn sanctuary, and
if we fail to know Him, it is because we have first failed to
knoAV ourselves. This is the conclusion to which we are
legitimately conducted.
This view of the subject dispenses with the necessity of
postulating a presentative knowledge of
ness, and"' our know- God, through a faculty of apprchensiou
ledge of God mediate adapted to thc coguitlon of the Divine
and representative. i ~
Being, as perception is adapted to the cog-
nition of external objects. God is not given to us as a phe-
nomenon of experience. There is no God-consciousness apart
Lect. II.] THE BEING OF GOD, 73
from the necessary inferences of reason. All our knowledge
of Him is mediate and representative. He is what intelli-
gence finds in the inquiries which it raises upon the phe-
nomena of experience. But the fact that philosophers have
The conviction of Tesortcd to sucli thcorics as those of the in-
God lies close to our tuitioual thcologj is a proof of how closely
the conviction of a God lies to our nature.
INIen have felt, wdth irresistible certainty, that He exists.
The fact being indisputable, when they have been driven by
sophistical objections from one method of certifying it, they
have immediately resorted to another. When they have
been unable to vindicate it as an inference, they have re-
solved it into immediate perception ; when they could not
ground it in discursive reason, they have grounded it in
faith, and made faith a faculty instead of a mental function.
The import of all is, that the notion of God cannot be ex-
pelled from the human soul. He is, and our nature pro-
claims that He is, however we may explain the manner of
the fact.
LECTUKE III.
3IAN'S NATURAL IGNORANCE OF GOD.
WE have seen that the human mind has been constituted
with a special reference to the knowledge of God. It
was made to know Him. It contains elements of faith, or
laws of intelligence, which, when normally
Man made for the t i , j i i i*
knowledge of God, applied to the phenomena of experience,
necessitate the inference that there is a
God, and, apart from all disturbing influences, would con-
duct to a just apprehension and a true worship of His name.
The very principles by which man is capable of knowing
any thing have their proper termination in God. Indeed,
he cannot justly be said to know at all without the recogni-
tion of the First Cause. This knowledge, we have seen, is
not a remote deduction, but an immediate inference. The
finite and contingent give the infinite and eternal upon the
same principle on which thought gives existence. The ar-
gument, The world exists, therefore God is, is of the same
kind with the celebrated enthymeme of Des Cartes : Cogifo
ergo sum. But while the grounds of the knowledge of God
are thus laid in the very structure of the mind, while its
primitive and indestructible faiths find their natural ter-
mination in Him, it is yet matter of experience that no one
has ever, in point of fact, attained to right
yo^^.oes no a ain ^^^ worthy conccptioiis of the nature and
character of God by the unassisted light of
reason. The world by wisdom knew not God. Here, then,
is a singular phenomenon. Reason, under sound and
healthful culture, must, from its very laws, reflect the image
74
Lect. III.] man's natueal ignorance of god. 75
of God. INIatured by a normal growth, it could not fail to
find in Him the source of knowledge as well as the fountain
of being. Man has implicitly, therefore, what he never
realizes explicitly — a germ which never expands and ma-
tures— a seed which never springs up into a vigorous plant
nor bears healthful fruit. This is the positive testimony of
Scripture, as well as the dictate of observation and experi-
ence : " Because that which may be known of God is mani-
fest in them ; for God hath showed it unto them. For the
invisible things of Him from the creation of the world are
clearly seen, being understood by the things that are made,
even His eternal power and Godhead ; so that they are with-
out excuse. Because that when they knew God, they glori-
fied Him not as God, neither were thankful, but became
vain in their imaginations, and their foolish heart was dark-
ened. Professing Uiemselves to be wise, they became fools,
and changed the glory of the uncorruptible God into an
image made like to corruptible man, and to birds and four-
footed beasts, and creeping things." ^
The question now arises, How is this singular anomaly to
be explained? How is it that while all
A siugular anomaly. i i i • />
may know, and ought to know, none in fact
do know? To answer this question is the design of the
present lecture.
But let us settle, in the first place, precisely the nature of
that ignorance with which we have to deal. If it were ab-
solute and entire, if the reigning doctrine of the human race
were the hypothesis of Atheism, it would be impossible to
vindicate Theism upon any grounds of reason. Were there
no sense of God and no sense of religion, it would be as idle
to speculate upon theology, as to speculate upon morals
where no sense of obligation and of rectitude obtains. The
argument of our last lecture sliows conclusively that a vague
sentiment of religion, of dependence, responsibility and wor-
ship, and a corresponding conviction of the existence and
moral government of a supreme intelligence, are coextensive
' Rom. i. 19-24.
76 man's natural ignorance of god. [Lect. hi.
■with the race. What we affirm is, that while the existence
A more precise state- o^ ^ocl and a general sense of onr relations
ment of man's natural to Him are SO groundcd in the soul as to
ignorance of God. , , i • f» i t •
make man, wherever he is found, a religious
creature, no just and consistent notions of His nature, His
character and His attributes are anywhere compassed by
natural light ; and that wherever apprehended at all. He is
apjjrehended in no such light as to generate the dispositions
and emotions which constitute true piety. In other words,
apart from revelation. He is nowhere rightly represented in
thought, and even with revelation He is nowhere truly
loved and worshipped without special grace. The speculative
knowledge of the heathen is not only defective, but grossly
erroneous ; and spiritual cognition is the product of the Holy
Ghost alone by the Gospel. That this is the truth, the re-
ligious history of mankind abundantly demonstrates. What
Paul wrote centuries ago has always been true of those who
are destitute of the light of revelation — there is none that
understandeth, there is none that seeketh after God. Amid
all the temples and altars and sacrifices and costly oblations
which figure in heathen and superstitious worship, there is
nowhere an offering to the true, except as to the unknown
God. Throughout the earth there is not a heart which
beats in love at the mention of His name or is touched with
a sentiment of pure devotion to His service, except where
the Word and the Spirit of Christ have taken their lodg-
ment. The whole world lieth in wicked-
Explanation demanded. in i • i •
ness. How shall we explain this mourn-
ful phenomenon ?
I. It is clear that this state of things is most unnatural in
the strict and proper sense of the term ; that is, it contradicts
the ideal of humanity. It is equally clear that a force
originally foreign must have entered as a
A foreign disturbing ^lig^urbing clemeut into the development
element; twofold. ^ '-' e> i
of reason, and turned it aside from the line
of its right direction. There must be a steady and perma-
nent cause, where the effects are so uniform and constant.
Lect. III.] man's natural ignorance op god. 77
We are justified by Scripture, and warranted by observation
and analogy, in asserting that this foreign, disturbing force
is twofold : the power of sin as a principle of evil within us,
a law of death continually counter-working the law of the
Spirit of life ; and the power of Satan, the evil one himself,
whose influence upon the human race has only been increased
by the success of his first experiment. These two powers,
in their joint operation, are sufficient to explain the aston-
ishing anomalies of the religious history of the species. To
these two causes, the depravity of man and the malignity of
Satan, we owe it, that while there is a general, if not an
universal, conviction of the existence of a Supreme Being,
when men undertake to frame a just and consistent concep-
tion of His character, relations and works they pass through
every conceivable shade of error, from the disgusting
grossness of Fetichism to the deceitful refinements of Pan-
theism. The God they represent in thought is often a mon-
ster, sometimes a beast, but never the living and true Jeho-
vah. Let us advert in the first place to the power of Satan.
1. Since the fall this malignant spirit has entered into
, , . , , human nature in a manner somewhat anal-
The kind and ex-
tent of Satan's power ogous to that in wliich tlic Spirit of God
in and over men. i -n . ,1 -1 . />it tt ^
dwells m the hearts or believers. He has
an intimate access to our faculties, and though he cannot,
like the Holy Ghost, work at their roots so as to change
and transform their tendencies, he can yet ply them with
representations and delusions wliich shall effectually incline
them to will and to do according to his pleasure. He can
cheat the understanding with appearances of truth, fascinate
the fancy with pictures of beauty, and mock the. heart with
semblances of good. By a whisper, a touch, a secret sug-
gestion, he can give an impulse to our thoughts, and turn
them into channels which shall exactly subserve the pur-
poses of his malice. In all this he does no violence to the
laws of our nature. He insinuates himself into our facul-
ties, and works by them and through them according to
their own constitution. He disturbs neither the spontaneity
(8 man's natural ignorance of god. [Lect. III.
of the understanding nor the freedom of the will. As the
work of the Holy Ghost in the saints is by no means incon-
sistent with their full responsibility and their entire moral
agency, so the work of the devil in the rcin'obate makes it
none the less their work, and leaves these dupes of his malig-
nity and craft without excuse for their sin. Unlike the
Holy Ghost, he has no creative power. He can impart no
new nature. He can only avail himself of what already
exists to his hand. His power, like that of every other
finite being, consists in obedience to the laws of the subject
upon which he operates. Its secret lies in his knowledge
and his skill. In our fallen condition he has no need to
change our nature ; it is already adapted to his purposes.
It is a fit instrument for executing his fell designs against
the kingdom and the glory of God upon earth. These
representations of the indwelling of Satan in the human
soul, and of his consequent power and influence for evil,
are the uniform teachings of Scripture. He is there de-
scribed as the prince of the power of the air ; the sjiirit
that now worketh in the children of disobedience ; the god
of this world, who blinds the minds and hardens the heart
of the impenitent and reprobate and seals them up in final
unbelief; the strong man armed, who holds undisturbed
possession of the palace of the human soul, until a stronger
than he invades and casts him out. Men, on the other
hand, are represented as his servants, his children, his cap-
tives, his dupes, and the obedient subjects of his will. His
dwelling in them as a spiritual fact was authenticated be-
yond the possibility of doubt by its extraordinary manifes-
tations in the case of the demoniacs of the New Testament.
To all this must be added that, in that pregnant passage
which spans the history of time, the contest betwixt light
and darkness — betwixt the children of God and the im^ieni-
tent — is described as a contest betwixt two opposing armies,
the heads and leaders of which are the Seed of the woman
and the Scrjient. This passage teaches us, too, that the
kingdom of darkness is not a series of occasional insurrec-
Lect. III.] man's natural ignorance of god. 79
tions, but an organized conspiracy of evil. Its deeds of
wickedness are not sudden, spasmodic, extemporaneous
eifusions of desperate and impotent malice ; they are parts
of a plan, a great, comprehensive scheme, conceived by a
master mind and adjusted with exquisite skill, for extin-
guishing the glory of God. The consolidated empire for so
many centuries of Paganism, the persecuting edicts of im-
. , perial Rome, the rise and brilliant suc-
An organized sys- a '
tern of evil in the ccss of Mohanimedauism, the corruptions
of the Papacy, and the widespread deso-
lations of modern infidelity, can never be adequately under-
stood without contemplating them as parts of an organized
system of evil, of which the gigantic intellect of the devil
is the author, while men have been the guilty and unwit-
ting instruments. They have answered his ends and played
obsequiously into his hands, while they vainly supposed
that they were accomplishing purposes of their own. He
has, in his sphere, a providence in imitation of that of God,
and to this providence his children and subjects are adroitly
moulded. They take their place and act their part under
his superintending eye.
The ultimate design of Satan in all his machinations is to
-,, ^ . , „ , insult the majesty of God. A liar from
The design of Satan J *'
as to God, and as to the beginning, his first lie was a blasphemy,
and every other has been like unto it.
His great aim, in reference to man, is to transfuse into the
human soul his own views of the Divine character, works
and government. His ready access to our faculties, his in-
timate union with us by virtue of our native depravity,
his familiar acquaintance with the laws of our being, his
long experience and his angelic skill, render it easy for him
to insinuate his own thoughts and impart his own spirit to
the minds of those whom grace has not rescued from his
hands. Where he cannot destroy he perverts and cor-
rupts. As he cannot extinguish reason, and therefore can-
not utterly eiface the general sense of a superior power, he
exerts his ingenuity to distort all the elements of reason,
80 man's natural ignorance of god. [Lect. III.
understanding, conscience and religion into vehicles of slan-
derous impressions of God. As we must have a God and
a religion, he will take care that the God whom we acknow-
ledge shall be unworthy of respect, and the religion which
we j)rofcss a disgrace to our nature. AVith such a teacher,
and with such hearts as ours have been rendered liy the
fall, it is no wonder that men have everywhere come short
of the glory of God and changed it into an image made
like to corruptible man, and to birds and four-footed beasts
and creeping things.
It is a fearful truth that our nature is in such intimate
alliance with the Devil. But there is
Nothing incredible j^^thing incrcdiblc in it. If there be a
in all this. o
spiritual world and we are spiritual be-
ings, that world must touch us in some points. God's works
are not disjointed and isolated. All is dependent upon each,
and each is dependent upon all. The eternal throne is the
only independent thing in the universe. That spirit can be
present to spirit is manifest from the daily intercourse of
life, from the power of friendship, and especially from the
ties of the family. That spirit can enter into actual union
with spirit is apparent from the fundamental facts of re-
demption. Christ is in us aiid we in Him, and God in
both. Believers, too, are one with each other. The union
of Satan with the world is not the same in kind with the
union of Christ and His people ; it is only analogous to it.
He is not our sin in the full sense that Christ is our life.
He has no creative power, but he is our tempter, our
seducer, an ever-present prompter of evil to our thoughts
and hearts, an ever-present sophist to disarm truth of its
point and to commend falsehood to our embrace. To say
that all this is mysterious is to say nothing to the point.
The soul is a mystery, thought itself is a mystery, all know-
ledge begins and ends in mystery. The moral history of
man, whether with respect to the fall or redemption, loses
itself in clouds of mystery which no understanding can
penetrate but the infinite understanding of God. It is for
Lect. III.] man's natural ignorance of god. 81
us to accept the facts, however their explanations transcend
our faculties.
2. While, however, man's ignorance of God is to be
largely attributed to the craft and sophistry of the Devil,
we are not to forget the human side of the phenomenon, and
construe ourselves into innocent victims and dupes. We
have already said that Satan does no violence to the liberty
or faculties of man. He avails himself of the constitution
of our own nature, and especially of our depravity as fallen
beings. He gives an impetus and direction to our own
spontaneous tendencies. His power is purely moral. Apart
from our corruption he can only annoy ; he cannot deceive.
To understand, therefore, the immediate cause of man's mis-
representations of God, we must consider the power of de-
pravity as a law of abnormal develop-
^^^in, a iseasem e j-^g^^ -^ ^j^g goul. As a pcrvadiug State
it has a necessary tendency to distort the
faculties from their legitimate bent and expression. It is to
the mind what disease is to the body. Holiness, on the
other hand, is health, and communion with God, life and
power. We might as reasonably expect that the secretions
of the animal system should go on comfortably and smoothly
amidst the heat and agony of a fever, as expect sound con-
clusions in relation to Divine subjects from a reason to which
Gocl is not present as the Father of lights. Sin is as really
blindness to the mind as it is hardness to the heart, and the
soul under the dominion of sin must be turned aside from
the normal evolution of its real and original tendencies.
Its activities, however intense and vigorous, must be set in
the wrong direction. It is a great error to imagine that
depravity confines its mischief to the heart, or to those fac-
ulties which are immediately conversant about the distinc-
tions of right and wrong. Its seat is the
It extends to all our i jj. ' ^ i i_ i c
p^^^j,,.g soul, and not any smgle department of our
spiritual nature, and as disease extends its
influence to all the functions of the body, so sin extends to
all the powers and faculties of our being. In sin, therefore.
Vol. L— 6
82 man's natural ignorance of god. [Lect. III.
as the disturbance of the normal exercise of our faculties, as
distorting and perverting our energies, as a law of abnormal
development, we see a cause that is adequate to explain
the phenomenon in question. But this general view is
not sufficient to content our thoughts. We look abroad
upon the world, and as we contemplate
A more partinilar .■> •pi-ir> n t • ,i
statement neoUfui. ^he manitold lorms 01 religious error, the
various superstitions, the disgusting rites
of worship, the monstrous and hideous symbols of the
Godhead, and the cruel penances and gross immoralities
which prevail in heathen lands — when we consider all the
abominations which have long passed and still pass under
the sacred name of worship — we wish to see how these errors
have been engendered, and how they have been propagated
and spread. It does not satisfy us to trace them to sin in
the general. That does not explain how these errors rather
than others have arisen. We want to know tlie causes
which have set the human mind in these particular direc-
tions. We desire to see the forms which sin has assumed in
producing these disastrous effects. The general notion of
depravity already contains in it the notion that man must
be ignorant of God, but there must be special influences
of depravity to account for the enormous lies which have
taken the nartie of truth, and the awful blasphemies which
have taken the name of worship.
We do not pretend to be able to indicate the immediate
origin of all the errors that prevail. That would require an
amount of learning, an amount of philosophy and an amount
of historical detail altogether unsuited, even if we possessed
them, to lectures like these. Our task is humbler and more
limited. We propose to illustrate how" de-
dcpnivuy!' ^^^^"^^ °^ pravity enters as a disturbing and pervert-
ing element into the sphere of speculation,
and gives rise to false gods ; how it enters into the sphere
of morality, and corrupts the first principles of duty ; and
how it enters into the sphere of worship, and converts the
temple of God into the abode of monsters. Man never
Lect. III.] man's natural IGNORANCE OF GOD. 83
degrades God until he has first degraded himself, and the
degradation of God keeps pace with the degradation of him-
self. He must become unnatural before he can have an un-
natural religion.
(1.) Let us examine, first, the influence of depravity upon
the speculative knowledge of God. This
Its influence on the • ^ ^ • -t n ^ ^ t lj.j'
speculative knowledge IS the kiud 01 kuowlcdgc Contemplated m a
of God through the gyg^gj^ ^f gound philosophv or metaphvsics.
reason. •' i i ^ i ^
It is the knowledg-e which results from the
application of the law of causation to the phenomena of ex-
perience. This species of knowledge, one would think,
being so accessible, lying so near to our faculties, ought to
be sound and true ; and yet it is always erroneous, defective
and debasing when not corrected by Divine revelation.
]N'ow, in this sphere, sin first appears in the form of vain
speculations. Those speculations are vain
Tanity of mind. i • i i • i i i
which relate to questions that transcend the
scope of our faculties — which undertake to comprehend the
incomprehensible and to carry knowledge beyond its first
principles. The creature, as dependent and finite, can never
hope to compass an absolute knowledge of any thing. In-
telligence begins with principles that must be accepted and
not explained ; and in applying these principles to the phe-
nomena of experience, apparent contradictions constantly
emerge that require patience and further knowledge to re-
solve them. But the mind, anxious to know all and restless
under doubt and uncertainty, is tempted to renounce the first
principles of reason and to contradict the facts which it daily
observes. It seeks consistency of thought, and rather than
any gaps shall be left unfilled, it plunges every thing into
hopeless confusion. Instead of accepting the laws of intelli-
gence, and patiently following the light of reason, and sub-
mitting to ignorance where ignorance is the lot of his nature,
as limited and finite, and joyfully receiving the partial
knowledge which is his earthly inheritance, man, under the
impulse of curiosity, had rather make a world that he does
understand than admit one which he cannot comprehend.
84 man's natural ignorance of god. [Lect. Ill,
When he cannot stretch himself to the infinite dimensions
of truth, he contracts truth to his own little measure. This
is what the Apostle means by vanity of mind. To illustrate
it by an example : Reason asks, and asks
Example. it-)
very properly, vV hence came the world '.
The law of causation, an original and therefore an incompre-
hensible faith — a principle to be accepted, not proved —
answers that it was created. Curiosity asks : How is it pos-
sible that a thing can be created out of nothing ? and because
it cannot comprehend the mystery of the commencement of
being, it fancies a contradiction in the notion of creation, and
then denies the original principle of faith, which positively
affirms that God is a Creator. It must know all, or it will
know nothing. Apparent contradictions, accepted as real,
force it upon hypotheses which the primitive data of intelli-
gence do not justify, and which, therefore, must be false.
So with the immortality of the soul. It is an elementary
principle of reason, a spontaneous and
Another example. n • ^ o i ^ t\
necessary faith oi the human race. But
instead of accepting it as a fact as certain as our conscious-
ness, and waiting for further light to solve the mysteries
which comj)ass it, .vain speculation undertakes to reconcile it
with the double fact of the unity of man as compounded of
soul and body, and the dissolution of the body ; and because
it fails to make thought consistent with itself, denies what
its own nature intuitively affirms. It pronounces immor-
tality to be impossible, because the identity of man depends
upon the coexistence of soul and body, and the body un-
questionably perishes. The problem in all speculation is
harmony of view ; thought must be consistent with itself.
Aiming at this ideal, a creature of imperfect knowledge
must often be tempted to deny the plainest truths, because
it cannot see how they are to be made to correspond with
other truths which are equally indisputable. Difficulties
appear as contradictions, and as the mind cannot think at
all but in obedience to the laws of identity and contradiction,
these difficulties must lead it into serious and fatal error.
Lect. III.] man's natural ignorance of god. 85
But were the reason sound and healthful, it would perceive
at once that there could be no contradiction in the case —
that things equally proved to be true must be harmonious ;
and it would instantly resolve all further perplexity into its
ignorance, and wait patiently for more light. In this im-
patience to compass consistency of thought,
This vanity of mind, ^ • j j coufusiou aS tO the boUudaricS
proof of tlie disturbing
power of Bin, and the of faith and spcculatiou, there is proof of
fruitful source of error .it.i- /»• -r, • i •,
in relation to God, the disturbing power 01 sm. it IS depravity
which so perverts the soul as to make it
violate the laws of its own constitution and the essential
conditions of knowledge. In its normal state it would see
at once that none of its original beliefs could be questioned,
and that any speculation which leads to such a result must
be suicidal. This vanity of mind is a fruitful source of error
in relation to God. It may not only deny Him as Creator,
but it may deny the very law upon which His existence, as
a first cause, is demonstrated. It may find contradictions in
the law, if extended beyond the world of phenomena, and
conclude that there is no bridge between the visible and the
invisible. It may find in finite and contingent being the
grounds of its own phenomena, and thus preclude the neces-
sity of going beyond the world for the solution of its mys-
teries. For examples of this vanity we need not go back to
the ancient philosophers. We have them in our own age
and at our own doors. The very same
in our own age as well ,iir> i,- ^ • ^ • ' i
as of old. method oi speculation which m ancient
times made matter eternal and reduced
God to the level of the finite and conditioned, has, in modern
times, denied with equal confidence the possibility of creation,
and reduced God to a substance without attributes or a being
without determinations. He has been degraded to a level
with nothing, or treated as merely the infinite possibility of
things.
The root of this vanity is most certainly pride. Man is
The root of it is unwilliug to acknowledge his condition as
P'''^^- one of only partial knowledge. He is
86 man's natural ignorance of god. [Lect. III.
hence reluctant to comply with the terms upon which alone
any solid knowledge is attainable. In the eifort to be omni-
scient he trangresses the laws of thought, and the consequence
of intellectual transgression is no less fatal in the sphere of
speculation than of moral transgression in the sphere of duty.
He is struck with blindness, his foolish heart is darkened.
It is this same pride which kept the world for so many
^„ , , ., centuries ignorant of the true method of
Effects of pnue up- o
on philosophy in the philosophy. That mctliod is only a state-
''''^* ' ment of the form and limits of our know-
ledge, and as long as man was not content to restrict him-
self within those limits ; as long as he aspired to compass
in his thought the essential nature and properties of being
and the whole system of the universe, he was left to blunder
as a fit retribution for his presumption. It was not weak-
ness, it was pride, that seduced him from the way of truth.
Pride, in the sense of self-independence and self-sufficiency,
is the very core of sin, and it was but a development of its
real spirit and temper when man undertook to make his
own understanding the absolute measure of truth. We are
apt to represent the aberrations of philosophy as springing
from infirmity, from the want of proper guides or suitable
helps, like the mistakes of a child in its first effi)rts to walk.
But this is an error ; the law of truth is in man's reason,
and if he errs it is because he presumptuously overlooks,
denies or despises it. He has the guide, but will not fol-
low it. His vain speculations are in defiance of, and not
in obedience to, the intellectual laws of his own constitution,
and his errors are at once sins and judgments.
We have seen how vanity of mind superinduces a denial
of the primitive cognitions of reason, and plunges specula-
tion into regions inaccessible to our faculties, or sets man on
efforts to attain a species of knowledge which is not adapted
to his nature. To this may be added the
^^crotchetsforprinci- ^^.^^^^^^^^3 ^^ ^cccpt crotchcts for princi-
ples, and analogies for inductions, upon
slight and accidental grounds — grounds of superficial plans-
Lect. III.] man's natural ignorance of god. 87
ibility or apparent competency to explain a given class of
phenomena. These false maxims, once admitted, work mis-
chief in the whole extent of their application. If accepted
as universal truths, they must convert philosophy into a
vast collection of delusions. Take, for example, the
crotchet that in all knowledge there must be a resemblance
between the immediate object and the mind — that the soul
can cognize only through something analogous to itself —
and you have at once the foundation of an absolute system
of idealism. You deny the possibility of an immediate
perception of matter — an immediate knowledge of any things
but our own thoughts — and the step is easy from the denial of
the knowledge of the external world to the denial of its exist-
ence, and then the progress is natural to universal skepticism.
Another element which must be taken into the account
in estimatino; the tendency of sin to per-
Influence of sin upon ~ j i.
speculation through vcrt spcculatiou is tlic irrcgular influence
the imagination. r>. -j.- r\ "D^Tlx Ij.
ot imagination. Our iiiugnsh translators
seem to have regarded Paul as particularly signalizing this
faculty as the seat of vanity ; " they became vain in their hn-
ax/inations." Butler styles it a " forward delusive faculty."
Its true office is to be a handmaid to the understanding,
vivifying its conceptions and imparting a glow of life and
beauty to the knowledge of nature. It is
The true office of ,i -i • ,i i i • i, i.'
thisfticuitv "^^ medium through which our emotions
are excited in the absence of their appro-
priate objects. By imagination we mean not simply the
power of vividly representing to the mind the objects of its
past perceptions or of its present thoughts, but that combi-
nation with other faculties by virtue of which new forms
and new objects are created. It is by virtue of this faculty,
in this sense, that theories in science are constructed from
remote analogies — that accidents give intensity to the con-
ception of particular objects, and make them the centre of
associations which exist only in the heated mind. Taken
in this sense, we may say with Hunie,^ that " nothing is
^ Treat. Human Nat. b. i., p. iv., ? 7.
88 man's natural ignorance of god. [Lect. III.
more dangerous to reason than the flights of unagination,
and nothing has been the occasion of more mistakes among
, ., philosophers. Men of bright fancies may,
Delineation of its ••■ •■• '-> •' '
influence wiieu per- in this rcspcct, bc Compared to those an-
gels whom the Scriptures represent as cov-
ering their eyes with their wings." The influence of im-
agination in perverting speculation appears in the tendency
to frame an hypothesis from slight and accidental coinci-
dences. The imagination represents the connected things
so vividly that we are tempted to cognize the connection as
a necessary part of themselves. Hence the substitution of
fancied for real causes; hence superstition substituted in
the place of j)hilosophy ; hence arise the arts of magic and
the belief of prodigies and signs. We can see how, through
the irregular influence of the imagination, objects that have
become strongly associated with our joys and sorrows may
be invested with attributes that do not belong to them ; as,
for example, the vegetable, the mineral, the beast, that from
some accidental circumstance has been the occasion of im-
j^arting to us a valued good or delivering us from a dreaded
evil. The object henceforward becomes the centre in our
minds of a whole class of associations waked up by the
vividness of our emotions. We insensibly attribute to it
intelligence and design, and end by making it a god. The
imagination takes the place of reason, and attributes to the
fancied cause all the properties and attributes of the real
Author of our blessings. In the same way natural objects
become centres of thoughts awakened by disgust, and end
in being made the personal objects of hatred and contempt.
The causes which first set the fancy to work in particular
directions it is impossible to specify. Here Satan has a
commanding field of operation. But the fancy once set to
work we can readily perceive how the facts
Key to polytheism. . i , i i c l^
of experience and the phenomena ot nature
can be completely transformed. We have the key to the
polytheism which has prevailed in all heatlien lands. We
know the forge in which its innumerable gods have been
Lect. III.] man's natural ignorance of god. 89
made. We know the author of their various attributes and
works. Now, here is a pregnant proof of the disturbing
power of sin. A faculty which God intended to be a hand-
maid and minister is made the guide of our nature. Rea-
son takes the place of a subordinate, and man creates by the
same process both worlds and gods for himself. Here, too,
we see the same principle of pride — the exaltation of his
own being. He makes and unmakes ; he becomes creator
and Lord ; he becomes the supreme God of all.
Combine now these two causes, a perverted reason and a
perverted imagination ; replace the laws of belief by ground-
less crotchets, and picture the world in the colours of fancy ;
let false principles and a lively imagination unite their re-
sources, and let the end be consistency of thought in a
scheme of the universe ; and we have a key to human delu-
sions in the sphere of speculation. We can see the door
through which sin introduces the prolific progeny of error,
superstition, witchcraft, sorcery, idolatry and even athe-
ism itself.
(2.) But we proceed to signalize another form in which
sin still more fearfully perverts the nature
The perverting in- *' ■■■
fluciice of sin in the aud character of God. It is through the
sphere of morals, • n c m • itt i
iniiuence ol an evil conscience. We do
not propose to consider the manner in which depravity dis-
torts our moral judgments themselves, often leading us in
speculation to question the first principles of right or to
resolve them into modifications of pleasure and pain. We
do not allude to its power in misleading its victims in the
estimate of their own character, or in blinding the mind to
the atrocity of particular instances of wickedness. The
. „ . , ,. point we have in view is to illustrate the
especially in relation i
to the character of tcudcncy of a pervcrtcd conscience to mis-
represent the nature and character of God.
McCosh^ has strikingly illustrated what he calls " an attract-
ing and repelling principle" in the religious life of our fallen
race. " First, there is a feeling in man," says he, " prompt-
' Divine Government, p. 44.
90 man's natural ignorance of god. [Lect. ni.
ing him to seek God, if haply he may find him. Transient
feelings of gratitude, the fear of danger, the keen sense of
sin, the fear of punishment, all these would draw or drive
him into the presence of God." After enumerating the cir-
cumstances under which this feeling conspicuously operates,
he proceeds to mention that " there is also a repelling prin-
ciple, and it is the latter which is so very mysterious. It is
a fact — and the explanation is to be found in an evil con-
science— that there is something in human nature which
would drive man away from his ISIaker. When his better
feelings would prompt him to fall down before God, a hand
from behind is felt to be holding him back, and he hesitates
and procrastinates till the time for action is over." To the
action and reaction of these opposite principles he traces the
" strange contradictions of the human soul "
thotrir '"^ in relation to_ religion. "It is drawn to
God, and yet it is repelled from God when
it comes near him, as the electrified ball is repelled as soon
as it comes in contact with the object which attracted it.
Man is constrained to acknowledge God, and constrained to
tremble before the God whom he acknowledges. He would
escape from God only to feel that he is chained to him by
bonds which he cannot break. He would flee fi"om God,
but feels himself helpless as the charmed bird with the eye
of the serpent fixed upon it. He would go forth like Cain
from the presence of the Lord, but he has God's mark upon
him, and is still under his eye in all his wanderings. He
would flee from the presence of God, like the rebellious
projihet, into a region of thought and feeling where the re-
membrance of God can never trouble him, but it is only to
find himself brought back by restraints laid upon him. In
his conduct toward his God there is prostration and yet
rebellion ; there is assurance and yet there is terror. When
he refuses to worship God, it is from mingled pride and
alarm ; when he worships God, it is from the same feelings ;
and the worship which he spontaneously pays is a strange
mixture of presumption and slavish fear. Hence, the vibrat-
Lect. III.] man's natural ignorance of god. 91
ing movements of the world's religious history. Under
this double influence, attractive and repulsive, man's eccen-
tric orbit is not so much like that of the planets, with their
equable motion and temperature, as like that of the comets,
now approaching, as it were, within the scorching beams of
the central heat and light, and again driven away into the
utmost and coldest regions of space, and seeming as if they
were let loose from all central and restraining influence."
To appreciate the result produced by the joint operation
of these two principles, so happily signalized by McCosh, it
must be borne in mind that the attraction is without love,
and the repulsion without reverence. The sympathies which
draw men to God do not spring from any sense of the Divine
excellence or any apprehension of the Divine glory. There
is nothing approximating to a spirit of fellowship. Their
needs and their burdens, their weaknesses and dangers, or
the transient play of emotions upon sudden occasions of
benefits received or ills averted, — these are the cords which
attract us to our Maker. In the effort to escape from God
guilt is the predominant controlling motive. \Ye fear and
tremble, but we are not awed into any just
Fearing, yet hating, . .
reverence lor His majesty, or any just con-
ception of the sanctity of His justice. We hate while we
tremble.
When now we call to mind that a man seeks harmony in
his conscience as well as in his speculations — that he is as
anxious to be at peace with himself in the reflections which
he makes upon his own life and character as to be sensible
of mutual consistency and coherence in his philosophical in-
quiries— we can easily perceive that an evil conscience must
evil conscience ^^ ^ perpetual sourcc of false representations
must misrepresent of God. Whcn guilt raulvlcs iu tlic brcast,
the man blasphemes the justice of his Judge.
His self-love will prompt hira to stigmatize the punishment
of himself as remorseless cruelty ; and taking the hue of liis
own feelings, he will clothe God in colours of blood. He
will become a monster who must be avoided or appeased.
92 man's natural ignorance of god. [Lect. Ill,
Hence those savage religions which startle as much by the
ferocity of their rites as by the enormous blasphemy of their
doctrines. Or, when the rites of propitiation are less revolt-
ing, they still lead to a degradation of God by figuring Him
as a being who can be bribed, wheedled or cajoled. A
guilty conscience, unwilling to relinquish its iniquities and
yet anxious to be delivered from apprehensions of punish-
ment, prompts a man to represent the Deity as subject to
the weaknesses and follies of humanity. The whole system
of worship is projected upon the principle of ministering to
the vanity of the Almighty. As His justice is regarded as
personal revenge, the satisfoction of that justice consists in
soothing His wounded pride. God is to be flattered and
caressed with external marks of submission and esteem ; He
is to be flattered or insulted accordingly as He conducts Him-
self well or ill to the worshipper. The real spirit of idola-
trous worship, as a spirit of bribery, flattery and deceit, is
seen in the manner in which the heathen were accustomed
to treat their gods when they refused to succour them in
times of distress. Thucydides tells us that during the
prevalence of the plague in Athens the temples and images
and altars were entirely deserted and religion treated with
contempt, because their prayers had not been successful in
staying the progress of the pestilence. " The ancient Egyp-
tians," says McCosh, " in times of severe national distress,
took their sacred animals to a secret place and put them to
death, and threatened their gods that if the calamity did
not pass away they would disclose the mysteries of Isis or
expose the members of Osiris to Typhon. Augustus re-
venged himself for the loss of his fleet by storms on two
several occasions, by forbidding the statue of Neptune to be
carried in the procession of the gods." Conscience fills the
mind with prejudices against the nature and character of
God, as a personal insult to ourselves fills our hearts with
prejudices against the man, however excellent in himself,
who has mortified our self-respect. We cannot judge rightly
of one whom we hate and one whom we fear. In this way
Lect. III.] man's natural ignorance of god. 93
the guilty are betrayed into the most insulting reproaches
of their Maker, The being whom their fears picture is a
strange and hideous combination of malice, of weakness and
of vanity. No wonder that under the united influence of
guilt, self-love and the power of sin, under the united in-
fluence of an evil conscience and of evil passions, men have
made to themselves a God whom it is a shame to worship.
When to these causes we add the force of imagination, when
we give it impetus and energy by the very intensity of the
feelings, we have the key to the monsters which, under the
name of deities, have accelerated that degradation of the
species in which they took their origin. Here we have the
The true solution of truc solutiou of supcrstitiou and will-wor-
Bupeistition and will- ship, whether they appear in forms of
cruelty and blood, or in the softer shapes
of flattery and pretended praise. These same causes also
lead to a bold denial of providence. The repulsive principle
drives off all thoughts of God and the Divine government ;
and it is even made a proof of His dignity and blessedness
that He takes no interest in the affairs of men. If He exist
at all. He exists in solitary selfishness, and never permits
His eternal slumbers to be broken by such petty concerns as
the acts or fortunes of His creatures. He is despoiled of
His providence in compliment to His majesty. The Epi-
curean, in his refusal to worship, illustrates, only in a differ-
ent way, the same low thought of God as a victim of vanity,
which the devotee of superstition carries out in his deceitful
homage. Thus it comes to pass that none know God. The
Ajjostle touches the core of the difficulty when he traces it
to their invincible repugnance to give Him the glory which
is His due. They refuse Him the love to which His infinite
holiness is entitled. His light departs from the soul; it
henceforward gropes in darkness ; stumbles at the first prin-
ciples of truth ; enthrones imagination as the regulative
measure of thought ; and when roused by a guilty conscience
and evil passions gives us a being whom it would be our
honour to despise. The heart begins in malice, and ends
94 man's natural ignorance of god. [Lect. III.
by the creation of a Deity who is a fit subject for that
malice.
(3.) We have now seen how conscience, in the bosom of a
sinner, becomes a fruitful source of ignorance and mistake in
relation to God. We have seen how it crouches and flatters —
how it seeks to purchase peace by rites and sacrifices that
involve any suffering but that of the crucifixion of sin. But
there is a principle which prompts man to worship some-
thing as an object in which it can find complacency. It is
not content with distant homage ; it wants something in
which it can feel that there is a mutual sympathy with
itself — something which shall take the place of that commu-
nion with God which constitutes the essence of true religion.
The perverting in- ^his principle of worship or of fellowship
fluence of sin in the -with God, uudcr tlic pcrvcrtlng influcncc
sphere of worship. r» • i i i • • i /» •
oi sm, becomes an additional source of ig-
norance and error. The God whom it seeks cannot be found.
The living God has retired ; He has left the soul to dark-
ness and solitude. Hence a substitute must be found, and
the result is the invention of images as symbols of a presence
whij3h is no longer real. We imitate communion by the
embrace of the idol. We transfer to it the sentiments of
reverence which we profess for God, and by a natural de-
lusion we impart to it a fictitious consciousness of our rev-
erence and respect. This want of a present God, and this
determination to make Him present, have no doubt exerted
a wide influence in the inventions of idolatry. The reaction
of the image upon the mind of the worshipper, in depressing
his religious knowledge, is too obvious to require illustration.
This seems to have been also the opinion of Calvin^ as to
the origin of idolatry : " That idolatry has its origin in the
idea which men have that God is not present with them
unless His presence is carnally exhibited, appears from the
example of the Israelites. Up, said they, make us gods
which shall go before us ; for as for this Moses, the man
that brought us up out of the land of Egypt, we wot not
^ Instit. Lib. I., c. xi., § 8. ,
Lect. III.] man's natural ignorance of god. 95
what is become of him. (Ex. xxxii. 1.) They knew,
indeed, that there was a God, whose power they had ex-
perienced in so many miracles, but they had no confidence
of His being near to them, if they did not Avith tlieir eyes
behold a corporeal symbol of His presence as an attestation
to His actual government. They desired, therefore, to be
assured by the image which went before them that they
were journeying under Divine guidance. And daily expe-
rience shows that the flesh is always restless, until it has
obtained some figment like itself with which it may vainly
solace itself as a representation of God. In consequence of
this blind passion, men have, almost in all ages since the
world began, set up signs on which they imagined that God
was visibly depicted to their eyes." According to this view
idolatry is a confession that God has departed. It is the
effort of human presumption to countervail the consequences
of His absence, or rather the invention of human pride to
do without Him. It is literally bringing Him down to us.
The account which has now been given of the causes of
man's ignorance and errors in relation to
These views con- r^ i . , i • i ,i
firmed by Paul, ^OQ sccms to me to DC preciscly the same
as that which Paul has given in the pas-
sage from his Epistle to the Romans, already cited. The
root of the evil was the depravity of their hearts, manifested
in their refusal to glorify God as God. They had no real
love to His name, they saw no beauty in His holiness, and
felt no sympathy with His glory. They were destitute of
true religion. Instead of contemplating the Divine Being
%vith reverence, gratitude and delight, they became vain in
their reasonings — in their speculations upon his nature, his
attributes and his relations to the creatures. Sin appears in
the understanding as a principle of vanity, and, in leading
men to deny the first principles of intelligence, makes their
minds cease to be intelligent. Their unintelligent heart was
darkened. Intelligence in its fundamental laws being sub-
verted, men become a prey to their passions, their fancies,
their prejudices and their fears, and pass through all the
96 man's natueal ignorance of god. [Lect. III.
stages of religious degradation until they make themselves
as vile as the gods they have invented.
Substantially the same is the teaching of Solomon, that
God hath made men upright, but they have
and by Solomon. . .
sought out many inventions. ihe word
translated inventions has special reference to the subtleties
of vain speculation. It is applied (2 Chron. xxvi. 15) to
" the engines invented by cunning men" introduced by
Uzziah into Jerusalem, "to be on the towers and on the
bulwarks to shoot arrows and great stones withal." It ex-
actly expresses, as Hengstenberg suggests, " those so often
plausible and brilliant reasonings of the natural under-
standing which perplex the heart and lead away from the
wisdom that is from above ; those speculations of a heart
turned away from God, which are perpetually penetrating
into the Church from the world; those profane and vain
babblings and oppositions of science, falsely so called,
against which the apostle utters his warning in 1 Tim.
vi'. 20." Hengstenberg very justly adds : " Since the fall,
man has forgotten that he should, in the first instance, take
up a receptive position in relation to the wisdom that is
from above, and that such a position is the only right one ;
but instead of that he goes hunting after his own phantastic
and high-flown thoughts. The only way of throwing off
this severe disease, and of escaping from the bonds of one's
own thoughts and imaginations, is to unlearn the serpent's
lesson, ' Ye shall be as gods, knowing good and evil ;' to re-
turn to our dependence on God ; to renounce all self-acquired
knowledge ; and leaving all our own fancies and conclusions
to sink in Lethe's stream, to accept the Divine teachings
alone, according to our Lord's saying in Matt. xi. 25 : ' I
thank thee, O Father, that Thou hast hid these things from
the wise and prudent, and hast revealed them unto babes.' " ^
If we have succeeded in exhibiting the real causes of re-
ligious error and perverseness — if we have shown that there
is a disturbing power in sin which hinders and counteracts the
' Comment on Eccles. vii. 29.
Lect. III.] man's natural ignorance of god. 97
normal development of reason, the religious condition of the
world, however low and revolting, has no tendency to diminish
the arguments which the light of nature affords to the being
and attributes of God. That which may be known of God
is clearly manifested, though men may put a veil upon their
eyes and refuse to see it. They may shroud themselves in
the darkness of their corruptions, but the light shines around
them notwithstanding their blindness. To prove that
human ignorance upon this subject is universal is only to
prove that corruption is universal. The effects must be
coextensive with the operation of the cause. In the sense
of nature as created, all may and ought to know God ; in
the sense of nature as corrupted, practical atheism is our
sad inheritance.
II. But if man in his fallen and degenerate condition
could yet compass a just speculative know-
The profounder igno- it r r^ t ii" j.j-1
ranee of man's heart. l^dgC of God aud hlS government, there IS
a profounder ignoraiice which would still
settle upon his heart. This speculative knowledge is largely
attained in countries which are distinguished by the light
of the Christian revelation. The humblest peasants are
familiar with truths of which Plato and Aristotle had no
glimpse. They are sound upon questions which distract,
perplex, torment, confound the understandings of presump-
tuous sophists. They know that God is an eternal, inde-
pendent, personal Spirit ; that He made the heavens and the
earth ; that He governs all creatures and all their actions ;
and that He is infinitely good as He is infinitely great. But,
with all this knowledge, they yet fail to glorify Him as God.
They want that loving light which warms as well as con-
vinces. They want the beams of that beauty and glory
which shall make them love and adore. They have no
communion with Him. Sin, as the nega-
Sin Winds us to the ,• /» .i i-n /• /^ i • . i i p
glory there is in God. ^^^^ ^^ ^'^^ l^^G of God lU thc SOul of man,
is a principle of blindness to all that in
God which makes Him an object of delighted worship.
Corrupted nature can never give birth to a single affection
Vol. I.— 7
98 man's natural ignorance of god. [Lect. III.
which is truly religious. Depravity seals the man against
all the energies which are involved in genuine holiness. In
order to this spiritual, vivifying Divine knowledge, there
must be an influence from above, opening our blind eyes
and touching our wayward hearts ; and in order to this in-
fluence there must be redemption, atonement, reconciliation
with God. The cross is the only place where men can
truly find God, and the incarnate Redeemer the only being
in whom a sinner can adequately know Him. Apart from
the mediation of Christ there is and can be no real godli-
ness in any portion of our fallen race. All had gone astray,
and all were perishing upon the dark mountains of error.
Still, though the speculative knowledge of God can pro-
indirect benefit, ^lucc uo truc rcligiou, it docs always pro-
froni the mere specula- ducc an amendment of public manners. It
tive knowledge of God. . . . • i •
drives away superstition with its cruel and
its deceitful rites ; it elevates the standard of general moral-
ity ; and, if it does not make man intrinsically better, it
makes him externally more decent. The morality of Chris-
tian nations is far in advance of that of heathenism in its
palmiest days. Crimes to which Athens and Rome attached
no stigma — the unnatural lusts which were there indulged
without shame — dare not confront the public opinion of any
Christian state. Speculative knowledge gives a right di-
rection to the conscience ; restraining influences are multi-
plied, even where sanctifying grace is not felt. Read Paul's
appalling description of the civilized heathen society of his
day, and you will be sensible, at once, of the prodigious
change which Christianity, as an external institute, has
wrought in the manners of the people among whom it is re-
ceived. The crimes which he mentions would be driven in
Britain and America to cover themselves with the darkness
of night and hide their heads in holes and corners. It is
not that men are intrinsically better; they are only less
wicked. It is not that their hearts are changed, but Chris-
tianity has hemmed them in with restraints. They love
God no more now than in the days of Nero ; but their depravity
I
Lect. Ill], man's natural ignorance of god. 99
has been tiirnecl into other channels, and moral forces are
combined to repress their lusts, of which the heathen never
had a notion. The Gospel, therefore, is an immense bless-
„, „ , „ ins;, even where it does not communicate
The Gospel exalts o'
where it may not re- salvatiou. It cxalts man where it does not
redeem him. It sets moral powers to work
which are mighty in their effects, even though they fail to
reach the seat of the disease.
III. A question now remains which in a mawkish and
skeptical age deserves to be thoroughly un-
Heathenism : a mis- i x j j.i x* • j.i 1
fortune or a crime ? dcrstood— the qucstioii conceming the moral
estimate which should be put upon the
errors and superstitions of those who are destitute of the
light of revelation. There are many who represent hea-
thenism as a misfortune and not a crime, and exhibit its
victims as objects of pity and not of indignation. Men have
gone so far as to maintain that the primitive condition of
man was one of rudeness and ignorance, and that the various
superstitions of the world have been successive steps in the
progressive education of the race. The abominations of
idolatry are the innocent mistakes of childhood. It has been
further alleged that they are sincere in their worship, and
as they honestly aim to pay homage to His name, God will
graciously accept the will for the deed. These and all
similar apologies are guilty of a fundamental error. They
mistake the real secret of man's ignorance of God. So far
are the heathen from feeling after Him w^th any real desire
to find Him in His true character, that the grand purpose
of their inventions is to insult and degrade Him, and to
reign supreme in His place. Looked at in its true light,
heathenism is a crime, or rather a combination of crimes, so
enormous and aggravated that the marvel is how a God of
infinite justice and purity could endure it for a single day.
Its mother is sin and its daughter is death. In judging of
it, men imperceptibly lose sight of the fact that the heathen
are men like themselves, rational, moral, religious ; that they
have a nature in all respects like ours — the same primitive
100 man's natural ignorance of god. [Lect. Ill,
cognitions, the same laws of belief, the same conscience in
its fundamental commands, and the same instinct for personal
communion and worship. Their constitution, as spiritual,
responsible beings, in no respect differs from our own.
Taking this thought along with us, we must of course judge
of their principles, their character and conduct as the prin-
ciples, character and conduct of rational beings. To the bar
of reason they are certainly responsible. Now our whole
argument has shown that these reasonable beings, in close
conspiracy with the devil, have systematic-
A systematic perver- ii ,t -i j.Ij.1"
sion of reason. ally corruptcd and perverted their reason.
They have suppressed its utterances when-
ever it speaks to them of God. They have listened to it in
the affairs of life, but when it points to the Invisible and
Supreme, they have boldly said to it that it lied, and that
they would follow another light. Is there nothing monstrous
in this ? Heathenism is really an attempt to put out the
eye of the soul — nay more, to extinguish the very being of
the soul ; for its essence is intelligence, and intelligence is
sujjpressed in these very contradictions to first truths implied
in heathenism. Then, again, rational beings are bound to
regulate their faith by the laws of evidence. They are not
to believe without just proof. They must give a reason for
the faith that is in them. Bring heathenism to this test, and
what are its proofs of its countless rabble of gods ? What
evidence can it adduce for the Divine appointment of its
monstrous systems of worship ? If the question were asked,
Who hath required this at your hands ? what rational
answer could these reasonable beings give ? These systems
are so manifestly the products of their imagination, the
spawn of a whorish fancy by a corrupt heart, that they
would, perhaps, be amazed that any evidence were exacted.
Then what shall we say to the crimes which
The crimes which it ^j^^j^. religiou has sauctificd ? Those brutal
sauctines. o
lusts ; those bacchanalian revels ; the open
contempt of all the ties which bind man to his fellows ;
homicide, fratricide, parricide ; what shall we say of these.
Lect. in.] man's natural ignorance of god. 101
and of the men who have made it a merit, an act of devotion
to God, to be stained with these enormities ? Their con-
sciences judge right in the ordinary relations of life ; they
know the obligations of truth, justice and benevolence.
How can they be justified in extinguishing this conscience,
this voice of God within them, when they touch the subject
of religion ? If they are responsible at all, surely they are
responsible for crimes like these. Nothing can excuse them
which does not remove them from the rank of moral beings.
Add to this that in the matter of worship they oifer
flattery for praise, bribes for penitence, and wages for sin.
They have no love to God, no spiritual communion with
their Maker, though their nature tells them this is the very
life and soul of worship. Instead of this holy and spirit-
ual exercise they substitute the presence of stocks and stones,
of birds and four-footed beasts and creeping things, and
would j)alm oif this mummery to an image as an adequate
compensation for the absence of holy love.
If anything can be said with truth, it is that heathenism
is unnatural and monstrous. And how can it be main-
tained that a man is innocent when he has done violence to
all that is great and noble about him ? What is heathen-
ism in its last analysis but a determined effort in the alli-
ance and interests of hell to extinguish reason rather than
admit the true God? As to the notion that idolaters are
sincere in their worshij^, if it means that
The plea of their lie- ,i it j.1 • i • j.1 j. • xl
ing" sincere." ^^^^J oelicve thcu^ lics, that IS the very core
of the charge against them. How can
they as reasonable beings believe without guilt a mass of
stupendous falsehoods which outrage common sense ? Their
reason never brought them to this pass ; it was something
which silenced reason. If by " sincerity" is meant that
they design the honour of God, then the core of their guilt
again is that they have such thoughts of God as to suppose
that He can be pleased with what would degrade a man.
He who thinks to honour me by slander and insult, by
making me approve and reward the most abominable crimes,
] 02 man's natural ignorance of god. [Lect. III.
has certainly strange notions of honour ; and the more sin-
cerely they honour God after this fashion the more they
deserve to be damned for hushing that monitor of God
which speaks spontaneously in their consciences.
It is a shame to apologize for idolaters. We may pity
them, but we must condemn them. They are without ex-
cuse. Their ignorance is wilful and obstinate.
The true view of heathenism is, that it is the consumma-
„ ,, . . ^^ tion of human depravity. It is the full
Heathenism is the i -^
consummation of de- development of the principle of sin in its
'"'*" ■^' workings upon the intellectual, the moral,
the religious nature of man. It is a development directly
counter to that which is normal and right. It is the last
stage which the mind reaches in its retrograde movement.
It is as complete an unmaking of the work of God in man
as it is possible to conceive. The only sense in which it is
a preparation for the gospel is that it shows the hopelessness
of man Avithout it. God has permitted it to take place on
a large scale that He might demonstrate the real tendencies
of sin. If the fact were not before our eyes, we might be
tempted to doubt whether reasonable beings could sink so
low. If we knew nothing of history, and for the first time
were made acquainted with the various schemes of idolatry
and superstition, we should hesitate in attributing to those
who invented and those who received such systems the epi-
thet of rational. They could not, we should be apt to feel,
be men like ourselves. But there stands the fact, and there
it stands as an unanswerable proof, that sin is the murderer
of the soul. It extinguishes the life of intelligence, the
life of conscience and the life of religion. It turns man
into a monster and clothes his Maker in garments of slianie,
and when it has done its Avork of death it complacently
wipes its mouth and says, " I have done no evil." Surely
the Avicked shall be turned into hell, with all the nations
that forget God.
As to the first authors of idolatry, it deserves further to
be mentioned that they not only sinned against the light
Lect. III.] man's natural ignorance of god. 103
of reason, but against the light of revelation. Adam and
^, ^ . , , ^ the patriarchs were not left Avithout Divine
The first idolaters '■
sinned against reveia- guidance in relation to the worship of God.
They had an express law which they
knew to be from Him. Those who departed from this
law, or corrupted it by their own arbitrary inventions, were
guilty of wilful and deliberate apostasy. They did not like
to retain God in their knowledge. The principle which
prompted their apostasy is the principle which lies at the
root of all the subsequent aberrations of their children.
None sought after God, none desired the knowledge of His
ways, none were disposed to glorify His name ; and the con-
sequence was that they were given up to walk in the light
of their own eyes and after the imagination of their own
hearts, and instead of light to embrace only the shadow
of death.
LECTURE IV.
THE NATURE AND LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE
OF GOD.
"ITrE have already said that all the speculations of the
' ' human mind in relation to the Supreme Being may
be reduced to three questions : An sit Deus f Quid sit Deus f
Qualis sit Deus f — that is, they all have reference either to
His Existence, His Nature or His Attributes. The first has
been the subject of the precedino; lectures :
Quid sit Deus? '' ^ ^ '
the second now demands our attention.
To the question concerning the nature and extent of our
Two contradictory kuowledgc of God, two auswcrs directly
answers : (1.) God per- contradictory havc bccu returned by philo-
I'ectly comprehensible. , ^-^ ■, ,^ ti/-^t
sophers. One party has amrmed that God
is not only comprehensible in Himself, it being His nature
to be intelligible, but that the actual compreliension of His
essence, as made up of the ideas which constitute absolute
reason or intelligence, is the condition of intelligence in re-
lation to every other object. We may not only know Him,
but we can know nothing else without knowing Him.
" Philosophy," says Cousin,' " will not deny the accusation
of wishing to penetrate into the depths of the Divine essence
which common opinion declares to be incomprehensible.
There are those who Avould have it incomprehensible.
There are men, reasonable beings, whose vocation it is to
comprehend and who believe in the existence of God, but %vho
will believe in it only under the express condition that this
existence is incomprehensible. What does this mean ? Do
^ Introduc. to Hist. Phil., Linberg's Trans., p. 132.
104
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 105
they assert that this existence is absolutely incomprehensi-
ble? But that which is absolutely incomprehensible can
liave no relations which connect it with our intelligence,
nor can it be in any wise admitted by us. A God who is
absolutely incomprehensible by us is a God who, in regard
to us, does not exist. In truth, what would a God be to us
who had not seen fit to give us some portion of Himself, and
so much of intelligence as might enable His wretched crea-
tui'e to elevate himself even unto Him, to comprehend Him,
to believe in Him ? Gentlemen, what is it to believe ? It
is, in a certain degree, to comprehend. Faith, whatever be
its form, whatever be its object, whether vulgar or sublime —
faith cannot but be the consent of reason to that which rea-
son comprehends as true. This is the foundation of all
faith. Take away the possibility of knowing, and there
remains nothing to believe, for the very root of faith is re-
moved. Will it be said that God is not altogether incom-
prehensible?— ^that He is somewhat isomprehensible ? Be
it so, but let the measure of this be determined, and then I
will maintain that it is precisely the measure of the com-
2)rehensibility of God which will be the measure of human
faith. So little is God incomprehensible that His nature is
constituted by ideas, by those ideas whose nature it is to be
intelligible. . . . God, the substance of ideas, is essentially
intelligent and essentially intelligible."
The other party represents the Divine nature, in common
with the nature of every other being, as
inSipSlnsTwe!'"^ Utterly beyond the reach of thought. It
never can be a positive element of con-
sciousness. God is and ever must be the great unknown.
The language in which the writers of this school sometimes
express themselves is so strong as to convey the notion that
God is so entirely aloof from all relation to our faculties
that we know, and can know, absolutely nothing about Him
but the bare fact of his existence.
" We cannot," says Bishop Browne, as quoted by Pro-
106 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV.
fessor Fraser/ " be said only to have indistinct, confused and
imperfect apprehensions of the true nature of God and of
His real attributes, hut none at all in any degree. The true
meaning of the word incomj)rehensible is that we have no
idea at all of the real, true nature of God." Those patris-
tic representations of the Deity which make Him " the un-
known subject of attributes absolutely unknown/' to which
Bishop Browne subsequently refers, are traced by Berkeley^
to the Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite. This author,
Berkeley observes, " hath written upon the Divine attri-
butes in a very singular style. In his treatise of the Celes-
tial Hierarchy he saith that God is something above all
essence and life, ut:e(} Tzaaav ouaiav xai qtorjV) and again in his
treatise of the Divine names, that He is above all wisdom
and understanding, u>t£/> no.aav aoifiav xal auveatv ; ineffable
and innommable, dypr^ro^; xal, di^wi^v/uoc; ; the wisdom of God
he terms an unreasonable, unintelligent and foolish wisdom,
TT^v dXoyov xal dvouu xal fio)f>dv aotfiav. But then the reason
he gives for expressing himself in this strange manner is,
that the Divine wisdom is the cause of all reason, wisdom
and understanding, and therein are contained the treasures
of all wisdom and knowledge. He calls God uTiipaoifoz
xal uTtiit^w^, as if wisdom and life were words not worthy
to express the Divine perfections ; and he adds that the
attributes, unintelligent and unperceiving, must be ascribed
to the Divinity, not xaz iUst<f'iu by way of defect, but xad'
bTiEpoY^YjV, by way of cminency, which he explains by our
giving the name of darkness to light inaccessible." This
mode of dealing with the Divine nature Berkeley very
happily characterizes as " the method of growing in expres-
sion and dwindling in notion, as clearing up doubts by non-
sense and avoiding difficulties by running into affected con-
tradictions."
Sir William Hamilton, whose philosophy by no means
leads to a total denial — on the other hand it expressly pos-
tulates a necessary faith and a relative knowledge — of trans-
• Essays in Philos., p. 216. ^ Minute Pliilos., Dial, iv., § 19.
Lect. IY.] limits of our KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 107
ceudcnt Existence, has yet, at times, expressed himself in
terms which justify the remark of Professor Fraser,' that
" the Scottish philosopher seems to cut away every bridge
by which man can have access to God." To maintain the
absolute incognoscibility of God is to maintain the absolute
imj)ossibility of religion. The philosopher, accordingly,
who in modern times has so triumphantly demonstrated
that ontological science is a " mere fabric of delusion," was
but consistent with himself when he resolved the essence of
religion into obedience to the moral law.
The truth lies between these extremes ; God is at once
known and unknown. In His transcendent
Truth in the midJle. -p, . , i i • n '
Beuig, as absolute and infinite, though a
necessary object of faith. He cannot be an object of thought.
We cannot represent Him to the understanding, nor think
Him as He is in Himself. But in and through the finite
He has given manifestations of His incomprehensible reality,
which, though not sufficient to satisfy the demands of spec-
ulation, are amply adequate for all the ends of religion.
Human knowledge is the same in form, whatever may be
the diversity of its objects. The knowledge of God is, con-
sequently, not different in kind from the knowledge of any
other being. Though unlimited in Himself, the absence of
limitation in Him does not remove the limitation of our
faculties, and we are compelled to know Him, as men, under
the same conditions and restraints under which we know the
finite. There are three conditions which
Three roiiditions of • , -i rri
all kuowiedge. cousciousncss iicvcr can transcend, ihe
first is, that the immediate matter of our
knowledge is not things as they are in themselves, but things
as they appear — phenomena, and not the transcendent reality
which underlies them and imparts to them their coherence
and their unity. We know matter, we know mind, not
absolutely as matter or mind, but as that which appears to
us under the forms of extension, solidity, figure, motion, etc.,
or that which appears to us under the forms of thinking,
1 Essays in Philos., p. 222.
108 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV.
feeling, willing. Our knowledge, therefore, is confined to
phenomena, and to phenomena only. Another condition is,
that we know only those appearances of things which stand
in relation to our faculties. There may be other appearances
which they are capable of presenting to other intelligences.
It would be unphilosophical to assume that our senses ex-
haust all the properties of matter, or our consciousness all
the properties of mind. All that we can say is, that they
exhaust all the appearances or phenomena which we are ca-
pable of knowing. Others may exist, but their existence to
us is a blank. De non apparentibus et non existcntibus eadem
est 7'atio. The third is, that in knowing phenomena, and the
phenomena related to us, we are irresistibly impelled to pos-
tulate a transcendent something beyond them, as the ground
of their coexistence and uniformity. As these " phenomena
appear only in conjunction," says Sir William Hamilton,^
" we are compelled by the constitution of our nature to think
them conjoined in and by something ; and as they are phe-
nomena, we cannot think them the phenomena of nothing,
but must regard them as the properties or qualities of some-
thing that is extended, solid, figured, etc. But this some-
thing, absolutely and in itself — i. e., considered apart from its
phenomena — is to us as zero. It is only in its qualities, only
in its effects, in its relative or phenomenal existence, that it
is cognizable or conceivable; and it is only by a law of
thought which compels us to think sometljing absolute and
unknown, as the basis or condition of the relative and known,
that this something obtains a kind of incomprehensible
reality to us." To this unknown something, in its generic
sense, as comprehending the basis of all phenomena, we ap-
ply the name of substance ; in its specific sense, as indicating
the basis of the phenomena of extension, we call it matter ;
as indicating the basis of the phenomena of consciousness,
we call it mind or spirit. " Thus mind and matter " — I re-
sume the Avords of Hamilton — " as known and knowable, are
only two different series of phenomena or qualities ; mind
' Metaphys., Lect. viii.
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 109
and matter, as unknown and unknowable, are the two sub-
stances in which these two different series of phenomena or
qualities are supposed to inhere."
Hence in our knowledge of the finite there are evidently
two elements or factors. There is, first, the
PliPiioniena and sub- 1 j.' 11 ll'l i
gjj^^^g relative and phenomenal, winch can be con-
ceived and known ; this is the j)roper object
of thought. There is, secondly, the substance or substratum,
the quasi absolute, which cannot be represented in thought,
but which is positively believed as existing. One element
addresses itself to intelligence and the other to faith. Both
are felt to be equally true. Both concur in every cognition
of the finite. Take away the belief of substance, and you
destroy the unity of phenomena ; take away the conception
of phenomena, and you destroy the conditions under which
the belief of substance is realized. It is in and throuo-h the
phenomena that substance is knoicn; they are the manifest-
ations of it as a transcendent reality ; it is a real existence
to us under these forms. As, then, the properties of matter
Properties reveal ^"^ miud are rclativc manifestations of
substance, and the fi- transccndeut rcalitics beyond them, so the
nite the infinite. . • i i i •
finite, considered as such, is a relative
manifestation of an absolute and infinite being; without
whom the finite is as unintelligible as a phenomenon with-
out substance. The notion of cause is a necessary element
of reason. The notion of the finite is the notion of an eifect,
of something dependent in its being. A finite absolute is a
contradiction in terms. The causal nexus as much necessi-
tates the belief of the infinite and absolute when we contem-
plate the finite and dependent, as the nexus of substance and
accident necessitates the belief of substance when we contem-
plate phenomena. Without the infinite, no finite — without
the absolute, no relative, is as clear and unambiguous an ut-
terance of human reason as no properties without a subject.
"The really necessary causal judgment," says Professor
Fraser,^ " has, as it seems to us, another reference altogether,
1 Essays, p. 242.
110 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV,
than to laws of nature and uniformities of succession among
the finite changes of the Universe. It is a general expression
of the fundamental conviction of reason, that every finite event
and being dependfi on and practically reveals infinite or trans-
cendent Power. It is a vague utterance of dissatisfaction
with an absolutely finite Universe — totum, teres atque rotun-
dum — and of a positive belief, not only that finite objects
exist, but that they do not exhaust existence, seeing that they
depend on God. We are intellectually dissatisfied as long
as the object of which we are in quest is within the range of
logical laws, and therefore recognized as a power only in-
definitely great. The dissatisfaction projects reason beyond
the realm of finite, and therefore scientifically cognizable,
existence. The mental necessity which thus conducts us to
the Transcendent Being and Power, with or without the in-
tervention of finite beings and second causes, is the root of
the only truly necessary causal judgment we can discover."
The finite accordingly is a real, though oi;ily a relative,
manifestation of the infinite. It gives the fact of its exist-
ence; we know that it is, though we do not know it as
it is.
In all this there is nothing peculiar either in our know-
ledge or our ignorance of God. The mystery which shrouds
His being is the same in kind with the mystery which
shrouds the being of every other object. In both cases
there are the same elements — an incomprehensible reality
■which transcends the capacit}' of thought, and comprehensi-
ble phenomena which are readily moulded into the forms
of the understanding ; and in both cases the comprehensi-
ble is the exponent, the manifestation, the all that is know-
able by us, of the incomprehensible. Properties reveal sub-
stance, and the finite reveals the infinite — not that properties
are like substance, or the finite like the In-
infinUel'b-irreTelis u! ^"1^. Wc havc uo right to make the one
rejiresentative of the other. But projicr-
ties arc the modes under which substance appears to our
understandings, and the finite the mode under which the
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. Ill
absolute appears. " We know God," says Calvin/ " who is
Himself invisible only through His works. Therefore the
apostle elegantly styles the worlds za jxr] ex (faiuo/xii^cou
^Xenofitva, as if one should say, ' the manifestation of things
not apparent.' This is the reason why the Lord, that He
may invite us to the knowledge of Himself, places the fab-
ric of heaven and earth before our eyes, rendering Himself,
in a certain manner, manifest in them. For His eternal
power and Godhead, as Paul says, are there exhibited.
And that declaration of David is most true, that the heav-
ens, though without a tongue, are yet eloquent heralds of
the glory of God, and that this most beautiful order of
nature silently proclaims His admirable wisdom. ... As
for those who proudly soar above the world to seek God in
His unveiled essence, it is impossible but that at length they
should entangle themselves in a multitude of absurd fig-
ments. For God, by other means invisible, as we have
already said, clothes Himself, so to speak, with the image of
the world in which He would present Himself to our con-
templation. They who will not deign to behold Him thus
magnificently arrayed in the incomparable vesture of the
heavens and the earth, afterwards suffer the just punish-
ment of their proud contempt in their own ravings. There-
fore, as soon as the name of God sounds in our ears, or the
thought of Him occurs to our minds, let us clothe Him with
this most beautiful ornament ; finally, let the world become
our school, if we desire rightly to know God."
As it is the causal nexus which upon the contemplation
of the finite elicits in consciousness the necessary belief of
the Infinite, and as the effects which we behold, being effects,
cannot be the attributes or properties of God, the question
arises. What are the intuitions by which
The question. • i i i
we represent in thought the comprehen-
sible element of our knowledge? How, in other words,
do we think God ? AVhat are the data which we combine
in the conception, and what is our security that these data
' Comment, on Genesis, Argument (Calvin Transl. Soc), vol. i., pp. 59, 60.
112 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OP GOD. [Lect. W.
are +he real appearances of such a Being to minds like
ours?
To this the only satisfactory answer which can be given
is, that all the intuitions, or, as Locke would express it, all
the simple ideas, which enter into the complex notion of
God, as thought by the human understanding, are derived
from the human soul. The j)0ssibility of theology depends
upon the postulate that man reflects the image of His
Maker. We have seen that reason is so constituted that
when adequately developed it spontaneously ascends from
the phenomena of exj^erienee to a First Cause, an abso-
lute and infinite Being which it is constrained to construe
as intelligent, powerful and good, as a just moral Ruler
and the supreme object of worship) and adoration. Intelli-
gence, wisdom, power, liberty, goodness, justice, truth, right-
eousness and beauty, — these are attributes without which
God is God no more. Whence do we derive these con-
cepts ? Whence are our notions of know-
All concepts of God i -i -t l x j.1 o ^Tti
from the humaa soul, ledge, gooduess and truth? \\ hence our
notion of power? Most evidently they
spring from our own minds. Our own consciousness is the
storehouse from which they are drawn. We can conceive
no intelligence but the human ; Ave can think no power but
that which is suggested by the energy of our own wills ; we
can have no moral intuitions but those which are given by our
own consciences. Man, therefore, sits for the picture that
he sketches of God. But is God only man upon a larger
scale? Is the infinite only a higher degree of the finite ? It
is a saying of the Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite — and it
has generally been accepted as a sufficient indication of the
truth — that in ascending from the creature to God we pro-
ceed by the method of causality, of negation and of emi-
nence. In the way of causality I am constrained to affirm
that every perfection which is contained in the effect was
previously contained in the cause. But as the perfections
of the creature exist under many limitations and conditions
which are inconsistent with the notion of the Infinite, I am
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 113
led in the way of negation to remove those restrictions and
defects, and to posit the perfections in the abstract. Then,
by the way of eminence, I strive to represent these perfec-
tions as expanded even to infinity. Thouglit struggles to
magnify until it sinks back upon itself exhausted in the
effort. Examples of all these methods the Scholastic
divines^ profess to find in the Scriptures. Thus, Psalm
xciv. 9, 10 is an instance of the way of causality : " He
that planted the ear, shall He not hear ? He that formed
the eye, shall He not see ? He that chastiseth the heathen,
shall not He correct ? He that teacheth man knowledge,
shall not He know?" In Numbers xxiii. 19 we have an
illustration of the method of negation : " God is not a man,
that He should lie ; neither the son of man, that He should
repent. Hath He said, and shall He not do it ? Or hath He
spoken, and shall He not make it good ?" The method of
eminence is signalized in Isaiah Iv. 8, 9 : " For my thoughts
are not your thoughts, neither are your ways my ways, saith
the Lord. For as the heavens are higher than the earth, so
are my ways higher than your ways, and my thoughts than
your thoughts."
This is the- process — and it is a process natural to reason,
as inevitable as the laws of thought — by which we are
led to the belief of an absolutely perfect being. The
notion of an ens realissimum is not the arbitrary product of
the fancy, but the necessary result of speculation, when a
cause is sought for the manifold phenomena of the finite.
Relative perfection is construed as the manifestation of the
absolute. It is the form under which it aj)pears to our con-
ditioned consciousness. It is not the same with it, nor like
it, but reveals it — reveals it as existing ; reveals it as a neces-
sary article of faith conceived only under analogy. The
relative perfection, in other words, is the form or symbol
under which the absolute appears.
And here let me explain the terms absolute and infinite in
their relation to God, which have become household words
1 De Moor, c. i., ? 13.
Vol. I.— 8
114 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lfxt. IV.
of modern philosophy. The absokite is that which is self-
existent and underivcd — which exists with-
Jd%'nuTLvi^'l out dependence upon, or necessary relation
to, any other being. The infinite is that
which includes all reality, all being and all perfection within
itself. It is the totality of existence. It is not the unfinish-
able of Sir William Hamilton, for that is essentially imper-
fect. It is that . absolute which he has described as the
Telecoz of the Greeks — a complete whole, to which nothing
can be added and from which nothing can be taken. In
the senses here explained the infinite and the absolute co-
incide. They are only different phases of one and the same
thing. There can be no infinite without the absolute, no
absolute without the infinite. There cannot be necessary
self-existent being which is not also unconditionally un-
limited being. Hence, among divines, the absolute and in-
finite are, for the most part, interchangeable terms. " The
metaphysical representation of the Deity," says Mansel,^ "as
absolute and infinite, must necessarily, as the profoundest
metaphysicians have acknowledged, amount to nothing less
than the sum of all reality. ' What kind of an absolute
being is that,' says Hegel, ' which does not contain in itself
all that is actual, even evil included?' We may repudiate
the conclusion with indignation, but the reasoning is unas-
sailable. If the absolute and infinite is an object of human
conception at all, this, and none other, is the conception re-
quired. That which is conceived as absolute and infinite
must be conceived as containing within itself the sum, not
only of all actual, but of all possible modes of being. For
if any actual mode can be denied of it, it is related to that
mode and limited by it ; and if any possible mode can be
denied of it, it is capable of becoming more than it now is,
and such a capability is a limitation. Indeed it is obvious
that the entire distinction between the possible and the actual
can have no existence as regards the absolutely infinite ; for
an unrealized possibility is necessarily a relation and a limit.
^ Limits of Eel. Thought, Lect. ii.
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 115
The scholastic saying, Deus est actus purus, ridiculed as it
has been by modern critics, is in truth but the expression in
technical language of the almost unanimous voice of philo-
sophy, both in earlier and later times." To this quotation
may be added a confirmatory quotation from the Living
Temple of John Howe : ^ " Necessary being is most unmixed
or purest being, without allay. That is pure which is full of
itvself. Purity is not here meant in a corporeal sense [which
few will think], nor in the moral ; but, as with metaphysi-
cians, it signifies simj)licity of essence. And in its present
use is more especially intended to signify that simplicity
which is opposed to the composition of act and possibility.
We say, then, that necessary being imports purest actuality,
which is the ultimate and highest perfection of being. For
it signifies no remaining possibility, yet unreplete or not filled
up ; and consequently, the fullest exuberancy and entire con-
fluence of all being, as in its fountain and original source.
We need not here look further to evince this than the native
import of the very terms themselves, necessity and possibility ;
the latter whereof is not so fitly said to be excluded the
former, as contingency is, but to be swallowed up of it; as
fullness takes up all the space which were otherwise nothing
but vacuity or emptiness. It is plain, then, that necessary
being engrosses all possible being, both that is and (for the
same reason) that ever was so. For nothing can be, or ever
was, in possibility to come into being, but what either must
spring, or hath sprung, from the necessary self-subsisting
being. So that unto all that vast possibility a proportionable
actuality of this being must be understood to correspond. . . .
Necessary being can never alter, and consequently can never
come actually to be what it already is not ; upon which ac-
count it is truly said. In ceternis, posse et esse sunt idem.
Wherefore in it is nothing else but pure actuality, as profound
and vast as is the utmost possibility of all created or produ-
cible being ; i. e., it can be nothing other than it is, but can
do all things ; of which more hereafter."
1 Pt. I., chap, iv., I 2.
116 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV.
Now the question arises, What can we know, or rather
what can we think, of absohite and infinite perfection ? As
The absolute not de- infinite and absolute, it is obvious that we
finable, yet the mind canuot represent it in thought at all. We
demands it. i p • i •
cannot define it so as to make it enter as a
jJositive element in consciousness. But still absolute per-
fection is an imperative demand of reason ; the relative is
unmeaning without it. The human mind cannot dispense
with the faith of it. So far from being a chimera, or a mere
illusion of metaphysical speculation, it is rooted and grounded
in the very structure of the soul. But because we cannot
conceive the perfections of God, as they are in themselves
and as they exist in Him — that is, because we cannot think
them as infinite and absolute — does it follow that in trying to
think them we think nothing at all ; or if we think anything,
we think only a delusive appearance ?
This brings us back to our original question, to answer
which it must be recollected that our con-
The question answered. . /. . f r-i -i
cejjtion of the perfections of God embraces
two elements — a positive and a negative one. The positive
one is the abstract notion of any particular perfection, such
Positive and negative ^s wisdom, intelligence, justice, truth, be-
eiements of the con- nevolcncc Or powcr, fumishcd by the phe-
ception. .
nomena of our own consciousness. Ihe
negative one is a protest against ascribing the perfection to
God under the limitations and conditions of human experi-
ence.
A perfection abstractly considered is only a generalization
of language ; it is incapable of being realized in thought ex-
cept as given in some special and definite manifestation.
Knowledge in the abstract, for example, has no real exist-
ence ; it is only a term expressive of that in which all single
acts of knowledge concur, and applicable alike to every form
of cognition. It marks a relation which uni-
Go^wviedgir''" versally obtains. Now, when we attribute
knowledge to God, we mean that there exists
in Him a relation analogous to that signalized by this term-
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 117
among us. "Wlien we undertake to realize the relation as it
exists in God, we transcend the limits of our faculties. "VVe
can only say that it is to Him what the highest perfection
of cognition is to us. But as we are obliged to think it in
some concrete form, we conceive it as a species of intuition,
in which the Divine consciousness penetrates at a glance the
whole universe of being and possibility, and surveys the
nature and relations of things with absolute, infallible cer-
tainty. The relation in Him expresses all that we compass
by intuition, reasoning, imagination, memory and testimony.
The analogy is real and true. The things analogous are by
no means alike. God has not faculties like ours, which are
as much a badge of weakness as a mark of distinction and
honour. He knows without succession, and apprehends all
relations without reasoning, comparison or memory. He is
not subject to the condition of time nor the necessities of in-
ference. But though knowledge in Him is manifested dif-
ferently from knowledge in us, yet the essence contained in
the abstract relation finds its counterpart in a manner suited
to an infinite consciousness. Hence we think Divine, under
the analogy, not under the similitude, of human cognition.
There is that in Him which stands in the same relation to
certainty as intuition to us. And Locke long ago remarked
that we can have a clear and precise notion of relations, even
when the things related are very partially or obscurely ap-
prehended.
In the same way power, abstractly considered, expresses the
relation of a cause to its effect. In itself
and how we attribute • •, • •. i
to Him power, ^^^ ^^^1 ^^ morc conccivc it lu its humau
than its Divine manifestations. It is that
in the cause which produces the effect, and we think it only
in connection with its effects. Now, this relation is con-
ceived as subsisting in God with reference to the products of
His sovereign will. There is something in Him analogous
to what we experience in the operations of our own Avills.
We think of void space. We conceive it occupied by body
which has just been called into being. We cannot repre-
118 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV.
seut the rationale of creation, but we can clearly compre-
hend the kind of relation implied in the creative fiat. It
is as intelligible as that between impulse and motion.
The same holds in the case of goodness, justice and love,
and all the moral and intellectual perfec-
goodness, justice, love. , i • i -i i * i • i
tions which we ascribe to the Almighty.
The abstract notions are generalizations from the sphere of
our own experience, and we think them in God as some-
thing; which is the same to Him as these relations are to us.
The thing positively represented is the human manifestation
in its purest form, but it is attributed to God in the way of
analogy, and not of actual similitude. His infinite perfec-
tions are veiled under finite symbols. It is only the shadow
of them that falls upon the human understanding. Such is
the process. A perfection is given in man under manifold
forms and conditions. The perfection is reduced to an ab-
stract notion, equally realized in all and equally cogitable in
all, but in itself actually inconceivable. We ascribe it to
God in the perfection of its essence as an abstract notion,
and endeavour to think it under relations in Him analogous
to those in which it is revealed in us. We
aiw^rau^gSr"' ai-e sure that there is something in Him
which corresponds to these relations in us.
Hence the positive element in our efforts to think God is
always analogical.
"Thomas Aquinas," says Berkeley,^ "expresseth his
sense of this point in the following manner : All perfec-
tions, saith he, derived from God to the creatures are in a
certain higher sense, or (as the Schoolmen term it) eminently
in God. Whenever, therefore, a name borrowed from any
perfection in the creature is attributed to God, we must ex-
clude from its signification everything that belongs to the
imperfect manner wherein that attribute is found in the
creature. Whence he concludes that knowledge in God is
not a habit, but a pure act. And, again, the same doctor
observes that our intellect gets its notions of all sorts of
1 Minute Philos., Dial, iv., U 20, 21,
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 119
perfections from the creatures, and that as it apprehends
those perfections, so it signifies them by names. Therefore,
saith he, in attributing those names to God we are to con-
sider two things : first, the perfections themselves, as good-
ness, life and the like, which are properly in God ; and,
secondly, the manner which is peculiar to the creature, and
cannot, strictly and properly speaking, be said to agree to
the Creator. And although Suarez, with other Schoolmen,
tcacheth that the mind of man conceiveth knowledge and
will to be in God as fiiculties or operations by analogy only
to created beings, yet he gives it plainly as his opinion that
when knowledge is said not to be properly iu God, it must
be understood in a sense including imperfection, such as dis-
cursive knowledge, or the like imperfect kind found in the
creatures ; and that none of those imperfections in the know-
ledge of men or angels, belonging to the formal notion of
knowledge, or to knowledge as such, it will not thence fol-
low that knowledge in its proper, formal sense may not be
attributed to God ; and of all knowledge taken in general
for the clear, evident understanding of all truth, he expressly
affirms that it is in God, and that this was never denied by
any philosopher who believed a God. It was indeed a cur-
rent opinion in the schools that even being itself should be
attributed analogically to God and the creatures. . . . But
to prevent any man's being led by mistaking the scholastic
, , , ,. , ,^ use of the terms analogy and analogical
Scholastic use of the "^ "^ ^ ^
term anaingicai ex- into an opiuiou that wc canuot frame in
^ '""^ ■ any degree a true and proper notion of
attributes applied by analogy, or, in the school phrase,
'predicated analogically, it may not be amiss to inquire into
the true sense and meaning of these words. Every one
knows that analogy is a Greek word used by mathematicians
to signify a similitude of proportions. For instance, when we
observe that two is to six as three is to nine, this similitude
or equality of proportion is turned analogy. And although
2')roportion strictly signifies the habitude or relation of one
quantity to another, yet in a looser and translated sense it
120 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV.
liatli been applied to signify every other habitude, and con-
sequently the term analogy comes to signify all similitude
of relations or habitudes whatsoever. Hence the School-
men tell us there is analogy between intellect and sight, for-
asmuch as intellect is to the mind what sight is to the body,
and that he who governs the state is analogous to him who
steers a ship. Hence a prince is analogically styled a pilot,
being to Ijie state as a pilot is to his vessel. For the further
clearing of this point, it is to be observed, that a twofold
analogy is distinguished by the Schoolmen — metaphorical
and proper. Of the first kind there are frequent instances in
Holy Scripture attributing human parts and passions to
God. When He is represented as having a finger, an eye or
an ear — when He is said to repent, to be angry or grieved —
every one sees that analogy is merely metaphorical, be-
cause those parts and passions taken in the proper significa-
tion must in every degree necessarily, and from the formal
nature of the thing, include imperfection. When, therefore,
it is said the finger of God appears in this or that event,
men of common sense mean no more but that it is as truly
ascribed to God as the works wrought by human fingers are
to man, and so of the rest. But the case is different Avhen
wisdom and knowledge are attributed to God. Passions
and senses, as such, imply defect, but in knowledge simply,
or as such, there is no defect. Knowledge, therefore, in the
proper, formal meaning of the word, may be attributed to
God proportionably — that is, preserving a proportion to the
infinite nature of God. We may say, therefore, that as
God is infinitely above man, so is the knowledge of God
infinitely above the knowledge of man, and this is what
Cajetan calls analogia proiwih facta. And after this same
analogy we must understand all those attributes to be-
long to the Deity which in themselves simply and as
such denote perfection. We may, therefore, consistently
with what hath been premised, affirm that all sorts of per-
fection which we can conceive in a finite spirit are in God,
but without any of that alloy which is found in the crea-
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 121
tures. This cloctriDe, therefore, of analogical perfection in
God, or of knowing God by analogy, seems very much mis-
understood and misapplied by those who would infer from
thence that we cannot frame any direct or proper notion,
though never so inadequate, of knowledge or wisdom as they
are in the Deity, or understand any more of them than one
born blind can of light and colours."
This passage of Berkeley, aimed at the theory of Bishop
Browne, maintained in the Divine Analogy, which seems to
l^reclude the possibility of any real or certain knowledge of
God, labours under one defect. It takes
Berkeley criticised. , .
for granted that we have a positive notion
of knowledge, wisdom and every other human perfection,
simply and in themselves. Yet no one has more conclusively
shown than himself that abstract terms have no objects cor-
responding to them, but are only contrivances of language
for the abridgment of human thought. They express noth-
ing that can ever be conceived apart frOm individuals. We
cannot, therefore, think knowledge in general except as mani-
fested in some particular instance of cognition. In the given
instance we can leave out of view what is special and distin-
guishing, and attend only to what equally belongs to every
other instance ; but something that has been given in intui-
tion must be represented in thought. Hence, to attribute
knowledge to God is to think Him as knowing in some way.
We must take some form of human consciousness and trans-
fer it to Him. But the most perfect form, that of intuition
itself, is manifested in us under conditions which cannot be
applied to God. But the most perfect form is the highest
under which we can conceive it. As, therefore, we cannot
attribute it in this finite form to God, all that we can say is
that knowledge in Him is analogous to knowledge in us.
It is a relation which implies absolute certainty and infalli-
bility. We attribute the finite to God
mel^t'aprotesr '''" ^^^^^ ^ protcst that the finite form only
expresses a similarity of relation.
Again, the difference betwixt Divine and human know-
122 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV.
ledge is not one simply of degree. It is a difference in kind.
God's knowledge is not like ours, and therefore we are
utterly unable to think it as it is in Him. We can only
think it under the analogy of ours in the sense of a simi-
larity of relations. It is to Him what ours is to us. It is
to the whole universe of being, actual and possible, what ours
is to the small portion that presents itself to our faculties.
This protest is only a series of negations — it affirms sim-
ply what God is not, but by no means enables us to conceive
what He really and positively is. It is the infinite and ab-
solute applied to the attributes which we are striving to
represent. Still these negative notions are of immense im-
portance. They are clear and pregnant
Importance of these /• • j.i j. j.i • • x j j.
negative ideas. couiessions that there IS a transcendent
reality beyond all that we are able to con-
ceive or think, in comparison with which our feeble thoughts
are but darkening counsel by words without knowledge.
They reveal an unknown sphere to which the region of the
the known bears no more proportion than a point to infinite
space. They stand as an awful warning of the immensity
of human ignorance. Besides this, they are regulative prin-
ciples, which indicate how far Ave are at liberty to reason
from the positive element of our knowledge, and apply our
conclusions to God. When the potency of these conclusions
lies in the finite forms under which the abstract perfection
is thought, and not in the perfection itself, abstractly con-
sidered, we may be sure of error. We are then making
God altogether such a one as we ourselves, and transfer-
ring to Him the limitations and conditions which attach to
our finite consciousness. Incalculable mischief has been
done by reasoning from human conceptions of the attributes
of God under their human manifestations, and silently over-
looking those salutary negations which if attended to would
at once convict our conclusions of blas-
The negative ele-
m nt of positive ng- phcmy. Hcucc the negative in thought
has a positive regulative value. It is a
beacon to warn us and to guide us.
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 123
The result of this inquiry into the nature and extent of
our knowledge of God may be summed up
Sum of results. • ^ n ^^ • ' ' A 1
ni the lollowmg propositions. As we know
only in and through our own faculties, our knowledge must
be determined by the nature of our faculties. The conditions
of consciousness are such that we can never directly appre-
hend aught but the phenomenal and relative ; and yet in the
apprehension of that we are constrained to admit a real and
an absolute as the necessary explanation of appearances.
The infinite is never apprehended in itself; it is only known
in the manifestations of it contained in the finite. As exist-
ing, it is known — it is a positive affirmation of intelligence ;
but it cannot be translated into the forms of the understand-
ing— it cannot be conceived, except as the annihilation of
those limitations and conditions which are essential to the
possibility of human thought. We know that it is, but we
know not lohat it is. In our actual concept of God, while
we are constrained to recognize Him as an infinite and ab-
solutely perfect being, yet we are unable to realize absolute
and infinite perfection in thought. We only know that it
must be ; but our utmost efforts to grasp it amount to nothing
more than the transmutation of a series of negations into de-
lusive affirmations. The matter of our thought, in repre-
senting the Divine perfections, is taken from the phenomena
of human consciousness. The perfections which we experi-
ence in ourselves are reduced to their utmost abstraction and
purity, and then applied to God in the way of analogy. We
do not know His perfections, consequently, as they are in
themselves or in Him, but as they appear to us under finite
forms and symbols. This analogical conception, however, is
accompanied with the belief that the relative necessarily im-
])lies the absolute ; and therefore in the very act of imperfect
thought our nature protests against the imperfect as an ade-
quate or complete representation. We feel that we see
through a glass darkly — that it is only a glimpse of truth
that we obtain ; but the little, though partial and defective —
a mere point compared to the immense reality — is inexpress-
124 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV.
ibly iirccious, for its object is God. If it is only the hem
of His garment that we are permitted to behold, it impresses
us with a sense of His glory.
This relative, partial, analogical knowledge of God is the
Catholic doctrine of theologians. If au-
heie.''° "^"'"^ ^* °'"' thorities were needed, I might quote them
even ad nauseam. Let a few examples suf-
fice. " His essence, indeed," says Calvin,^ " is incompre-
hensible, utterly transcending all human thought; but on
each of His works His glory is engraven in characters so
bright, so distinct, and so illustrious that none, however dull
and illiterate, can plead ignorance as their excuse." Again : ^
" Hence it is obvious that in seeking God the most direct
path and the fittest method is not to attempt with presump-
tuous curiosity to pry into His essence, which is rather to be
adored than minutely discussed ; but to contemplate Him in
His works, by which He draws near, becomes familiar, and
in a manner communicates Himself to us."
" The terms by which attributes are predicated of God,"
says Cocceius,^ " are employed in condescension to our modes
of thinking and speaking. For, as Nazianzen affirms, to
know God is difficult, to speak Him is impossible ; or rather,
to speak God is imj^ossible, to know Him is still more im-
possible. His attributes are to be understood analogically.
The perfections which we find in the creatures testify to a
fountain inconceivably more perfect in God, to whicli the
creature is in some measure assimilated and bears M'itness."
" We cannot have," says Charnock,^ " an adequate or suit-
able conception of God. He dwells in inaccessible light —
inaccessible to the acuteness of our fancy, as well as the
weakness of our sense. If we could have thoughts of Him
as high and excellent as His nature, our conceptions must be
as infinite as His nature. All our imaginations of Him can-
not represent Him, because every created species is finite ; it
cannot, therefore, represent to us a full and substantial notion
1 Inst., Lib. I., c. v., I 1. ^ i^gt.^ Lib. I., c. v., ? 9.
2 Sum. Theol., c. ix., ? 33. * Works, vol. i., p. 274.
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 125
of an infinite being. We cannot think or speak worthily
enough of Him, who is greater than our words, vaster than
our understandings. Whatsoever we speak or think of God
is handed first to us by the notice we have of some perfection
in the creature, and explains to us some particular excellency
of God, rather than the fullness of His essence. . . . But the
creatures whence we draw our lessons being finite, and our
understandings being finite, it is utterly impossible to have
a notion of God commensurate to the immensity and spirit-
uality of His being. God is not like to visible creatures,
nor is there any proportion between Him and the most
spiritual." In another place he says,^ " God is, therefore, a
spirit incapable of being seen, and infinitely incapable of
being understood. . . . There is such a disproportion be-
tween an infinite object and a finite understanding, that it is
utterly impossible either to behold or comprehend Him."
" It is a true rule of theologians," says Macrovius,^ " that
God and the creature have nothing in common but the name.
The reason is, because God differs from a creature more
than a creature from nonentity." ^
" God," says Augustin,^ " is ineffable ; we can more readily
say what He is not than what He is."
I come now to consider the objection, that if our know-
ledge of God is only relative and analogical,
The objection that . ® •' . o ^
relative and auaiogi- it canuot DC acccptcd as any just or true
cai knowledge does not representation of the Divine Being, but of
represent God to us. i ~'
something essentially different. It is not
God that we know, but a mere series of appearances — the
products of our own minds, which we have substituted in
His place and hypostatized with His name. If nothing
more were meant than that we do not know God as He is
in Himself, and as, consequently, He knows Himself, the
objection would certainly have to be admitted. No such
knowledge is competent to the creature. The finite can
^ Vol. i., p. 256. ^ Theol. Polem., c. iv.
3 Cf. Th. Aquin. Sum. Theol., Pars Prim., Qu. xii., 3, 4.
* Enarrat. in Psalm Ixsxv. 12.
126 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV.
never hope to comprehend the Infinite as the Infinite com-
prehends itself. But if it is meant — which it obviously must
be if the objection is designed to destroy the foundations of
religion — tliat our knowledge of God does not apprehend the
appearances which such a being must make to minds con-
stituted like ours, that the things which we think are not
real manifestations of the Infinite, adapted to our faculties
of intelligence, the objection is assuredly without reason.
Either our whole nature is a lie, or the Being whom we thus
know under finite symbols is the supreme and everlasting
Jehovah. We know Him as the cause, the prime producing
cause of all that exists ; and this is no delusion. The re-
lation in which He stands to His works is clear and unam-
biguous, though the mode in which He realizes it transcends
our capacity of thought. We know Him as intelligent and
good. Wisdom and benevolence are conspicuously displayed
in the general order and special adaptations which fall within
the compass of our experience; and unless that primitive
law of intelligence which compels us to think design as the
only adequate explanation of such phenomena is a lie, then
we are sure that God is wise and knowing and good. Con-
science gives Him as a moral ruler, and consequently as the
supreme disposer of all things ; and unless conscience is false,
the testimony must be accepted as true. Every part of our
nature points to Him, and bears record to His character in
the relations which He sustains to us. We must, therefore,
construe our whole nature into an organ of deceit, or recog-
nize these partial and relative conceptions as just conceptions
of God as far as He appears to us. Beyond that appearance
we do not venture to go. Every step we take in reaching
our highest conceptions of God is a step under the impulse
and direction of principles of belief which constitute an es-
sential part of our being, and without which we should be
little better than the beasts that perish. Our knowledge as
far as it goes is true, if our faculties are not false. If our
faculties are false, any other knowledge which was in and
through them would be equally liable to suspicion. The
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 127
symbols under which we represent God are not arbitrary
creatures of the fancy, but the necessary products of thought
in obedience to laws which it cannot transgress ; and which,
while a proof of limitation and defect, are, at the same time,
a guarantee of truth. All that we pretend is to know God
as He appears, and what we maintain is that it is really He
who does so appear.
The objection in question is equally valid against all
human knowledge. It is the old cry of
all knowfedge"*^ ^ ° tlic skcptic. It is uot matter that we
know, it is not mind that we know ; it is
only the phenomena of which we are conscious, and these
phenomena may be the fantastic creations of the thinking
subject, or shadows which come and go upon the surface of
our being without any cause to which we can assign them.
How do we know that the j^roperties which we attribute
to matter really represent anything in matter, or how do we
know that such a thing as matter exists at all ? How do
we know that thought, volition, feeling are the properties
of any j)ermanent subject, rather than transient events
which succeed each other in time without being at all de-
pendent upon each other, or upon aught else, for their
existence ?
There is but one answer to all such sophistical objections.
We are obliged to trust in the veracity of
Answer to the ob- cousciousncss. We kuow bccausc wc be-
jection.
lieve. Consciousness assures us of our own
existence as a thinking subject, and consciousness also assures
us of the existence of another world without us. We accept
matter and mind as facts, because our nature constrains us
to believe them. The phenomena under which we think
them, the same consciousness represents as the appearances
which the'i/ make to us ; and therefore we accept them as
their appearances, as their attitude and relation to our intel-
ligence. It is precisely the same with our knowledge of
God. The man, therefore, Avho is free from scruples as to
the existence of the soul or the material world, who is per-
128 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV.
suadcd that the phenomena which they present to him are
not vain and delusive shows, but sober and permanent real-
ities, is inconsistent with himself in denying equal certainty
to our knowledge of God. His argument, legitimately car-
ried out, would land him in universal skepticism. It is
enough that we have the same guarantee for the truth and
certainty of our knowledge of God as we have for the truth
and certainty of our own being and the existence of an outer
world. The knowledge of both is subject to the same lim-
itations, the same suspicions, the same cavils. They stand
or fall together. If one is shadow, all is shadow ; if one
is solid, all is solid and substantial. There is no middle
ground. We know absolutely nothing, or what we know
is true as far as we know it. Our knowledge is imperfect
because we are imperfect. The plenitude of being cannot
appear to us, but what our faculties are capable of receiving
is none the less to be relied on because they do not receive
all that actually exists.
" It does not follow," says Mansel,^ " that our representa-
tions are untrue because they are imperfect. To assert that
a representation is untrue because it is relative to the mind
of the receiver, is to overlook the fact that truth itself is
nothino; more than a relation. Truth and falsehood are not
properties of things in themselves, but of our conceptions,
and are tested not by the comparison of conceptions with
things in themselves, but with things as they are given in
some other relation. My conception of an object of sense
is true when it corresponds to the characteristics of the ob-
ject as I perceive it, but the perception itself is equally a
relation and equally implies the co-operation of human
faculties. Truth in relation to no intelligence is a contra-
diction in terms. Our highest conception of absolute truth
is that of truth in relation to all intelligences. But of the
consciousness of intelligences different from our own we
have no knowledge, and can make no application. Truth,
therefore, in relation to man admits of no other test than
'^ Limits of Eel. Thought, Lect. v.
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 129
the harmonious consent of all human faculties, and as no
such faculty can take cognizance of the Absolute, it follows
that correspondence with the Absolute can never be re-
quired as a test of truth. The utmost deficiency that can
be charged against human faculties amounts only to this :
that we cannot say that we know God as God knows Him-
self— that the truth of which our finite minds are susceptible
may, for aught we know, be but the passing shadow of some
higher reality which exists only in the Infinite Intelligence."
Confusion has no doubt been introduced into the subject
by silently interpreting phenomenon and appearance as equiv-
alent to a sham or dream. They are contemplated as void
of reality. But what is reality ? What is the only reality
which our faculties can grasp ? It is not a thing in its ab-
solute nature, as it exists in itself independently of any per-
ceiving mind ; nor even a thing, as Mansel expresses it, " as
it must manifest itself to all possible intelligences under all
possible laws of apprehension." But reality is that which
we perceive to exist, and we perceive it as existing under
the relation in which it stands to our faculties. The phe-
nomenon is nothing but the reality manifested to conscious-
ness under the conditions of consciousness itself. It is
not, then, a sham, a dream, a mere shine. The contrast
of reality is those fictions or creatures of imagination wliich
in dreams may be mistaken for realities, but which in our
waking moments we know to be manifestations of nothing
apart from ourselves. Hence a phenomenal or a relative is
none the less a real knowledge ; it is the knowledge of real
existence as that existence is manifested to us. The exist-
ence is independent of us ; the manifestation is in and
through the relation of the object to our consciousness.
But I proceed to affirm, in the next place, that our rela-
This knowledge of ^^^e analogical knowledge of God is not
God both true and only truc and trustworthy, but amply ade-
adcquate. r> ii i c t • t
quate lor all the purposes oi religion. It
does not satisfy the needs of speculation, but it is admira-
bly adapted to the ends of devotion. If it is lacking in that
Vol. I.— 9
130 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lkct. IV.
characteristic which has a tendency to puff up, it is not lack-
ing in the other and nobler quality — the tendency to edify.
In order to appreciate the force of this consideration, it
must be borne in mind that man's j)resent
It is also adapted to t,. . i /» i i t , i ,
our present condition, couditiou IS uot hual and Complete, but
initial and preparatoiy. He is looking
forward to a better and more exalted state. The know-
ledge which he needs is the knowledge which will best
adapt him to acquire and intensify those habits of thought
and of feeling and of action which shall find their full
scope in his future condition. His present business is
education, and not satisfaction or enjoyment. To say
that he needs education is to say that he is imperfect,
and that there are impediments to his proficiency which
it demands patience, industry, energy and perseverance to
surmount. These imj)ediments serve at once as a motive to
stimulate exertion, and as the means of fixing more firmly
into the character the activities they call forth. The inten-
sity of an action measures its tendency to generate and ma-
ture a habit. To a being under discipline an absolute know-
ledge of Divine things, were such a knowledge conceivable or
possible, would be wholly unsuitable. There would be no
room for faith, for consideration, for candour, for the bal-
ancing of motives ; there would be no trial of one's love of
truth, or duty, or good. If we knew as God knows, we
should be as God is. What discipline requires is a mixed
state, in which men may to some extent control their opin-
ions and regulate their choice — a state in which evil, to say
the least, is possible. In such a state the real principles
which determine and constitute the moral character of the
man are capable of being fully displayed. Error may be
accepted as well as truth, temptations may prevail as well as
be overcome, man may revolt from as well as obey God.
But the great thing to be attained is the habit of entire
acquiescence in the will of God as a matter of free, volun-
tary choice. God presents Himself as a portion to the soul
to be chosen, not forced upon it ; and in order that the choice
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 131
may have its full significancy in determining and express-
ing character, it must be made under circumstances in which
there can be motives and inducements to the contrary.
Hence our imperfection in knowledge is the badge of our
probationary condition. Absokite, demonstrative certainty
would preclude all trial, all choice — that is, a state to be
won as a prize, and not one in which to begin a moral
career.
In our present condition we have just that kind of know-
ledge which is suited to our circumstances and our destiny.
Man's earthly state may be contemplated in three aspects :
1. As a state of pure and unmixed proba-
Three aspects of ,• . i-ii ,i o , r»i' 'iii
man's earthly state. ^^^n, lu which by thc free act of his will he
was to determine the permanent type of his
being. 2. As a state of sin and misery, the legal and natural
consequence of his free determination in his previous state.
3. As a state of partial recovery, in which he is to acquire a
meetness for the inheritance of the saints in light. Contem-
plated in his first estate, he had to the full that relative ana-
The relative analo- logical kuOwlcdgC which falls tO the lot of
gicai knowledge of ^ig facultics. He kucw his relations to
God suited to tlie first, r^ t t •
(jrod as his creator, his moral ruler and his
final reward. He knew the rule of his duty, both natural
and positive, and was w^arned of the consequences which
must result from transgression. But his knowledge, as im-
perfect and analogical, was founded in faith ; it rested upon
principles which he was obliged to accept, but which he could
not explain. He was thus brought, even in the sphere of
the understanding, face to face with the will of God. He
was capable of asking questions which he could not answer.
He could project his reason beyond the limits which circum-
scribed his faculties. All this was admirably suited to him,
as a being to be confirmed in perfect acquiescence with the
will of God. If he should be content with his prescribed
limits, and make the law of his life " not my will, but Thine
be done," he had the gracious promise that what he knew
not now, he should know hereafter. To complain, therefore.
132 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV.
of the limitations of his knowledge is to complain that he
was put upon probation at all. Higher knowledge would
have rendered all trial a mockery. To have been able to
answer all questions Avould have been equivalent to the im-
possibility of being deceived or seduced. Hence Adam's
knowledge was exactly the kind of knowledge suited to his
religion. Had he followed his nature — simply believed
where it prompted him to believe without the ability to com-
prehend ; had he been content to know only where science
was possible to his faculties ; had he been willing to accept
as facts what he could not explain as science, — had he, in
other words, submitted with cheerfulness to the appointment
of God, he might have maintained his integrity for ever.
An absolute knowledge is as incompatible with probation as
mathematical certainty with doubt. The understanding
would have absolute control if it had absolute knowledge.
But there is no medium between absolute and relative know-
ledge. The latter may differ from itself in degrees, but all
the decrees of it are in contradiction to absolute science.
The objection we are considering is not to the degree in
which man, as man, has it, but to the kind of knowledge
itself. The objection would abolish all limitation, and have
our theology the ectypal theology of God.
In the next place, contemplate man in his fallen condition
as a sinner, and the knowledge which he
and to the second, , • i i n i •
has IS, as precisely, adapted to his state.
It is enough to make manifest his guilt and depravity. It
reveals the abnormal tendencies of his soul. It affords a
conspicuous proof of the charge which God brings against
the race, and at the same time prevents the race from sup-
pressing its real dispositions under a constraining, external
pressure. Man is lai'gely at liberty to express himself — to
develop the very core of his moral condition. The diffi-
culties and perplexities he encounters in solving the enigmas
of his being only afford opportunity of exhibiting in brighter
colours the real enmity of his heart against God. They
enable him to prove that he is a sinner beyond the possi-
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KlSfOWLEDGE OF GOD. 133
bility of doubt. At the same time they furnish the instru-
ments bj which the Holy Spirit prepares him for the recep-
tion of the gospeL They give rise to a conflict, a struggle ;
the tendency of which, under the influence of grace, is to
mould and subdue. To give an elect sinner absolute know-
ledge would be to dispense with the whole j)rocess of con-
viction of sin, and all those conflicts of pride, faith and un-
belief by which, in humility, he is led to the Saviour.
There Avould be no room for self-examination, for faith or
for prayer. To give a non-elect sinner absolute knowledge
would be to make him a devil and to drive him to despair.
If we contemplate man in his state of partial recovery,
relative knowledge is the knowledge which
and to the third aspect i • 1j.1j.1*1j_' tt i i
of our condition. alouc IS adapted to his duties. He has to
form a holy character ; he has to form it
within comparatively a short period. His graces must be
put to the test and tried and strengthened. He must be
liable to the assaults of doubt, of fear, of unbelief. He must
be exposed to imposture and deceit, that his candour, sin-
cerity and love of truth may have scope for exercise, and in-
crease in their intensity. He must walk, therefore, by faith,
and not by sight. Now all this is incompatible with abso-
lute knowledge ; it is incompatible with even much higher
degrees of relative knowledge than we now enjoy. Hence,
in every aspect our knowledge is enough for the ends of
religion. All that is required is true humility — a spirit of
perfect contentment with our lot. If we see through a glass
darkly, it is because a brighter vision would be destructive
of the ends of our present moral state.
Then, again, the finite symbols under which we know
It also converts our ^^^^ ^"11 a natural transitiou from our
daily life into an ar- natural to our rcligious life ; or rather are
gument for devotion. , , i-i i •^ ^• o •
the means by which our daily life is con-
verted into an argument for devotion. If it is only in the
creature that we see God, the creature should be obviously
subordinated to the glory of God ; and if human affections
are to be directed toward God, the relations under which
134 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV.
they are developed with reference to each other are the
relations under which they must fasten on Him. " We
are not called upon," says Mansel/ "to live two distinct
lives in this world. It is not required of us that the house-
hold of our nature should be divided against itself — that
those feelings of love and reverence and gratitude which
move us in a lower degree toward our human relatives and
friends should be altogether thrown aside and exchanged
for some abnormal state of ecstatic contemplation, when we
bring our prayers and praises and thanks before the footstool
of our Father in heaven. We are none of us able to grasp
in speculation the nature of the Infinite and Eternal, but
we all live and move among our fellow-men, at times need-
ing their assistance, at times soliciting their favours, at times
seeking to turn away their anger. We have all, as chil-
dren, felt the need of the supporting care of parents and
guardians ; we have all, in the gradual progress of educa-
tion, required instruction from the wisdom of teachers ; we
have all offended against our neighbours, and known the
l)lessings of forgiveness or the penalty of unappeased an-
ger. We can all, therefore, taught by the inmost conscious-
ness of our human feelings, place ourselves in communion
with God when He manifests Himself under human im-
ages. ' He that loveth not his brother whom he hath seen,'
says the Apostle Saint John, ' how can he love God whom
he hath not seen?' Our heavenly affections must in some
measure take their source and their form from our earthly
ones ; our love toward God, if it is to be love at all, must
not be wholly unlike our love towards our neighbour ; the
motives and influences which prompt us when we make
known our wants and pour forth our supplications to an
earthly parent are graciously permitted by our heavenly
Father to be the type and symbol of those by which our
intercourse with Him is to be regulated."
There is another aspect in which our partial knowledge,
so far from weakening the grounds of religious worship,
1 Limits of Eel. Thought, Lect. iv.
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 135
has a tendency to strengthen them. If there were an absolute
ignorance of God, there could be no wor-
Our partial know- 1 1 • r> i i i i i
ledge strengthens all ship at all J II tlicrc wcrc au absolute know-
the grounds of wor- j^j^^^ ^^.^ sliould bc the cquals of God, and
consequently free from all obligation to wor-
ship. It is our dependence, marking us out as finite beings,
which renders us creatures of religion. It is this which gives
rise to prayer, to gratitude, to obligation, to trust and to duty.
Religion cannot be predicated of the infinite and self-suffi-
cient. It is the characteristic of the rational and intelligent
creature. Those finite symbols under which God is repre-
sented to us, and thought by us, furnish just the intimations
of His character which are suited to be the basis of reve-
rence and love. He is our Creator, our Redeemer, our
Benefactor, our Ruler and our Judge. He is wise and
powerful and good. He is faithful, merciful and just.
These are the attributes which inspire confidence, and these
are the relations under which religious affections are elicited
and fostered. But if we should stop at the finite symbols,
our religion would degenerate into earthly forms. We
should love God as we love a man, and reverence His cha-
racter as we honour a superior. Hence, to complete the
notion of religious worship we must introduce the other ele-
ment of our knowledge, in which God is negatively pre-
sented as transcending the capacity of thought. It is only
as we believe that He is independent of all limitations and
conditions — that He is self-sufficient, unchangeable and eter-
nal, that the heart can freely go out to Him with the full-
ness of its homage. There is no limit upon our affections
when the object is known to be unlimited in its right and
fitness to receive them. The very darkness which shrouds
this infinitude reacts upon our worship, and expands our
emotions into rapture and adoration. An awful sense of
sublimity, grandeur and majesty is awakened in the soul.
The ground on wdiicli we tread becomes holy ground ; we
are constrained to take the shoes from our feet, and stand in
wondering awe as we gaze upon the glory of the Lord.
136 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV.
Separate from God the finite iuiages in which we clothe
His perfections, and there would be nothing to justify or
regulate our worship. Restrict Him to these finite appear-
ances, and there would be nothing to warrant the peculiar
condition of mind which we call religion. Combine the two
elements together, and you have the object upon which the
soul can pour forth all its treasures, and feel itself exalted
in the very act of paying homage. The positive element
of our knowledge provides the basis for extending to God
our human aifections ; the negative element transforms those
affections into a sublimcr offering than any creature would
be authorized to receive. A finite superior may be admired ;
only an infinite God can be adored. " I love God," says
Gregory Nazianzen, " because I know Him. I adore Him
because I cannot comprehend Him." " What we deny of
God," says the venerable John Owen, " we know in some
measure, but what we affirm we know not ; only we declare
what we believe and adore." We have light enough to see
that the object is transcendently glorious, and when it
passes beyond our vision into regions of illimitable excel-
lence, where we have no faculties to pursue it, we are only
the more profoundly impressed with the exceeding riches
of its glory. It is the very light of eternity which darkens
time. It is the brilliancy of the blaze which dazzles and
confounds us. My ignorance of God, therefore, in the par-
tial glimpses which I get of Him is only a stronger argu-
ment for loving Him, If what I see is so inexpressibly
sublime and worthy — and what I see is only a point com-
pared with what I do not see — surely I should have no fears,
no hesitation or reluctance in surrendering myself unreserv-
edly and for ever to Him whose name is only a synonym
for the plenitude of glory. How admirably is our know-
ledge adapted to the ends of religion ! He who would
quarrel with the present arrangement could never be con-
tent unless God should seat him as an equal upon His
throne, for as long as he remains finite he can have no
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 137
other kind of knowledge, however it may differ in degree
from that which he now enjoys.
The account which has been given of the nature and ex-
This view of our *^°* ^^ '^^^^' knowledge of God is in perfect
knowledge of God harmouy with the teaching of Scripture.
agreeable to Scripture. _ ,, i i ^^ • i
In no respect/ says Mansel, ' is the
theology of the Bible, as contrasted with the mythologies of
human invention, more remarkable than in the manner in
which it recognizes and adapts itself to that complex and
self-limiting constitution of the human mind which man's
wisdom finds so difficult to acknowledge. To human reason
the personal and the infinite stand out in apparently irrecon-
cilable antagonism ; and the recognition of one in a religious
system almost inevitably involves the sacrifice of the other.
The Personality of God disappears in the Pantheism of
India ; His infinity is lost sight of in the Polytheism of
Greece. In the Hebrew Scriptures, on the contrary,
throughout all their variety of books and authors, one
method of Divine teaching is constantly manifested, appeal-
ing alike to the intellect and to the feelings of man. From
first to last we hear the echo of that first great command-
ment : ' Hear, O Israel ! the Lord our God is one Lord ;
and thou shalt love the Lord thy God with all thine heart,
and with all thy soul, and with all thy might.' God is
plainly and uncompromisingly proclaimed as the One and
the Absolute : ' I am the first, and I am the last : and be-
side me there is no God.' Yet this sublime conception is
never for an instant so exhibited as to furnish food for that
mystical contemplation to which the Oriental mind is natu-
rally so prone. On the contrary, in all that relates to the
feelings and duties by which religion is practically to be
regulated, we cannot help observing how the Almighty, in
communicating with His people, condescends to place Him-
self on what may, humanly speaking, be called a lower level
than that on which the natural reason of man would be in-
clined to exhibit Him. While His personality is never suf-
' Limits of Kel. Thought, Lect. v.
138 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV.
ferecl to sink to a merely liuman representation — while it is
clearly announced that His thoughts are not our thoughts,
nor His ways our ways — yet His infinity is never for a mo-
ment so manifested as to destroy or weaken the vivid reality
of those liuman attributes under which He ajjpeals to the
human sympathies of His creature. ' The Lord spake unto
Moses face to face, as a man speaketh unto his friend.' He
will listen to our supplications ; He will help those that cry
unto Him ; He reserveth wrath for His enemies ; He is ap-
peased by repentance ; He showeth mercy to them that love
Him. As a King, He listens to the petitions of His sub-
jects ; as a Father, He pitieth His own children. It is im-
possible to contemplate this marvellous union of the human
and Divine, so perfectly adapted to the wants of the human
servant of a Divine Master, without feeling that it is indeed
the work of Him who formed the spirit of man and fitted
him for the service of his Maker. ' He showeth His AVord
unto Jacob, His statutes and ordinances unto Israel. He
hath not dealt so with any nation ; neither have the heathen
knowledge of His laws.' "
" But if this is the lesson taught us by that earlier mani-
festation in which God is represented under the likeness of
human attributes, what may we learn from that later and
fuller revelation which tells us of One who is Himself both
God and man ? The Father has revealed Himself to man-
kind under human types and images, that He may appeal
more earnestly and effectually to man's consciousness of the
human spirit within him. The Son has done more than
this : He became for our sakes very man, made in all things
like unto His brethren ; the Mediator between God and man,
being both God and man. Herein is our justification if we
refuse to aspire beyond those limits of human thought in
which he has placed us. Herein is our answer if any man
M'ould spoil us through philosophy and vain deceit. Is it
irrational to contemplate God under symbols drawn from the
human consciousness? Christ is our pattern, for Mn Him
dwelleth all the fullness of the Godhead bodily.' Is it un-
J
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 139
philosophical that our thoughts of God should be subject to
the law of time ? It was when the fullness of time was come
God sent forth His Son. Does the philosopher bid us strive
to transcend the human, and to annihilate our own person-
ality in the presence of the infinite ? The Apostle tells us
to look forward to the time when we shall ' all come in the
unity of the faith, and of the knowledge of the Son of God,
unto a perfect man ; unto the measure of the stature of the
fullness of Christ.' Does human wisdom seek, by some
transcendental form of intuition, to behold God as He is in
His infinite nature ; repeating in its own manner the request
of Philip, ' Lord, sliow us the Father, and it sufficeth us ? '
Christ Himself has given the rebuke and the reply : ' He
that hath seen Me hath seen the Father ; and how sayest
thou, then, Show us the Father ? ' "
The principle which we have endeavoured to illustrate,
Consequence, of the touchiug the limits of humau knowledge in
principle herein iiius- relation to Diviuc thlugs, is prcguaut with
trated :
important consequences.
1. In the first pkice, it conclusively shows that there can
It shows that there ^6 uo such thing as a scicucc of God. We
is no such thing as a can hardly use the terms without the sus-
science of God. . . n t ^ i -xtr i •
picion 01 blasphemy. Were such a science
possible, it would lay bare the whole field of existence ; it
would reveal the nature of creation ; the relation of the finite
and the infinite in all the points of their contact ; and the in-
most essence of things. It would be the very knowledge
which God has Himself. But if we are restricted to ap-
pearances, or to the relative manifestations of realities, our
science, at best, can be but the result of multiplied com-
parisons, and can hardly extend beyond the order and suc-
cession of phenomena. Real being, as it exists in itself, or
in relation to the Divine mind, must remain an impenetra-
ble secret. AVe have to assume it as a fact, but we can
neither explain nor conceive it. We cannot make it a term
in logic, and reason from an analysis of its contents. Science
can o'o no farther than observation can accumulate its facts.
140 LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV.
The inexplicable must ahvays be of larger extent than the
simple and comprehensible. As, then, the limits of human
thought encounter mysteries in every department of nature —
mysteries which we are obliged to accept, though they defy
every effort to reduce or overcome them ; as matter is a
mystery, mind is a mystery, substance is a mystery, power
is a mystery — surely we must expect nothing less than mys-
teries when we enter the sphere of the infinite. God is, in-
deed, the great incomprehensible. As the principle of all
things, if we could comprehend Him we should in Him
comprehend everything besides. As the sum, therefore, of
all incomprehensibility, whenever we touch His Being or
venture to scrutinize His purposes and plans we must ex-
pect clouds and darkness to be round about His throne. A
theology which has no mysteries ; in which everything is
level to human thought, and capable of being reduced to
exact symmetry in a human system ; which has no facts that
command assent while transcending the province of human
speculation, and contains no features which stagger the wis-
dom of human conceit ; — a system thus thoroughly human
is a system which is self-condemned. It has no marks of
God upon it. For His footsteps are on the sea, and His
paths in the great waters, and His ways past finding out.
There is no searching of His understanding. Such a system
would be out of harmony with that finite world in which
we have our place. For there mystery encompasses us be-
hind and before — in the earth, the air, the sea and all deep
places, and especially in the secrets of our own souls. INIan
lives and breathes and walks amid mystery in this scene of
phenomena and shadows, and yet he would expect no
mystery in that grand and real Avorld of which this is only
a dim reflection !
2. In the next place, this principle suggests the real
-^ . , , ,, cause of most of the errors in theology, and
It iioiiits out the o. '
real cause of most thc rcal solutiou of its uiost pcrplcxing
heresies. , ,
problems.
Most heresies have risen from believing the serpent's lie,
Lect. IV.] LIMITS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. 141
that our faculties were a competent measure of universal
truth. We reason about God as if we possessed an absohite
knowledge. The consequence is, we are lost in confusion
and error. We assume the infinite in our words and think
the finite in our minds ; and the conclusion can only be a
contradiction or a falsehood. The Unitarian professes to
understand the Infinite Personality of God, and rejects the
doctrine of the Holy Trinity with a smile of contempt. He
forgets meanwhile that his argument has only proved that
there cannot be three human persons in the same numerical
essence. He has quietly eliminated the very element which,
for aught he knows or can show, redeems the doctrine from
all reasonable objection. Until he can tell us lohat the In-
finite is, we need not listen to him while he undertakes to
inform us lioni the Infinite is. It is so easy to slide into tlie
habit of regarding the infinite and finite as only ditfcrent
degrees of the same thing, and to reason froni one to the
other with the same confidence with which, in other cases,
we reason from the less to the greater, that the caution
cannot be too much insisted on that God's thoughts are not
our thoughts, nor God's ways our ways. To treat the power
which creates and the human power which moves a foreign
body as the same thing ; to apply to creation the laws and
conditions which limit the mechanisms of man ; to represent
the infinite as only a higher degree of human knowledge ;
and to restrict each to the same essential conditions and
modifications, is to make man God, or God man — a funda-
mental falsehood, which must draw a fruitful progeny in its
train.
3. Our ignorance of i\\e Infinite is the true solution of the
It solves the most ^^^^t pcrplcxiug problcms whicli cncouuter
perplexing problems us at evcry stcj) iu the study of Divine
of Theology. , -j^-, , . , / • ■ i
truth. NVe have gained a great ponit when
we have found out that they are really insoluble — that they
contain one element which we cannot understand, and with-
out which the whole must remain an inexplicable mystery.
The doctrines of the Trinity, of the Incarnation, of the Pre-
142 LIMITS OF OUU KNOWLEDGE OF GOD. [Lect. IV
science of God and the Liberty of Man, the Permission of the
Fall, the Propagation of Original Sin, the Workings of Ef-
ficacious Grace, all these are facts which are clearly taught ;
as facts they can be readily accepted, but they defy all efforts
to reduce them to science. Their feet rest upon the earth,
but their head is lost in the clouds. Our wisdom is to be-
lieve and adore. The limits of human knowledge are a
sufficient proof that thought is not commensurate with exist-
ence ; that there are things which the very laws of thought
compel us to accept, when it is impossible to reduce them
into the forms of thought ; that the conceivable is not the
standard of the real ; that " there are more things in heaven
and earth than are dreamt of in our philosophy."
It is a great lesson when man has learned the enormity
of his ignorance. True wisdom begins in humility, and
the first dictate of humility is not to think of ourselves
more highly than we ought to think.
LECTURE V.
THE NAMES OF GOD.
AMONG the methods whicli the Scriptures employ to
answer the question concerning the nature and per-
fections of God is the use of personal and attributive names.
These names, unlike proper names among
..l°,\n!inl J7" men, not only serve to denote the object
names among men. j j J
and to make it a subject of predication in
thought, but they also signify, or, in the language of the
schools, connote, the qualities by which the object is distin-
guished. They are not unmeaning marks, discriminating
one individual from another, as if by an arbitrary sign, but,
like general terms, they are expressive of concepts which
are realized only in God. They are applied to Him be-
cause they contain a meaning which suits Him. They were
assumed in condescension to our weakness, that we might be
assisted in coming to a knowledge of His being and His
character. They are a part of God's plan
T t!l!.J„„ „°.,v ™L^° of teaching the race, as it is through the
of teaching our race. o " o
explanation of names in Avhich the sum
of human attainment is recorded and preserved that the
parent and teacher develop the opening faculties of the
child, and stimulate and encourage its expanding curiosity.
In relation to those which are not attributive, their very
employment as proper names to designate a definite object
of thought has obscured the connotation on account of
which they were originally selected. They have ceased, in
a great measure, to answer any other end than to single out
the Deity as the subject of predication. They express Him
143
144 THE NAMES OP GOD. [Lect. V.
as a whole, and not under any particular aspect. We must
trace them to their origin if we would understand the j^re-
cise share they have contributed in the gradual progress
of revelation to the Christian concept of God. Each has
played a part in the j)roduction of the general result, and it
is curious as well as instructive to trace the successive steps
by which God has progressively unfolded
God has gracUially tt- ir • . j ^ ±- .
unfolded uimsuif. Mimseli lu ucw aspccts and relations to
the human mind, until it has reached its
present relative maturity of knowledge. Many streams
have discharged their contents into a common reservoir,
and it is remarkable that as the reservoir has increased
„, ..... in quantitv the number of tributaries has
The names diminish i /
in number as the rev- bcCU diminished. TllC HcbrCW, the ear-
elation advances. t i p i •
liest language oi revelation, was quite co-
pious in its names of God. The Greek, the next and only
other language, with the exception of a very limited use of
the Chaldee, employed by inspiration, has but two terms to
designate the Divine Being as a total object of thought.
And yet these two terms contain the fullness of the Hebrew
vocabulary. When the idea was in process of being formed
and matured there were many concurrent elements which
were specially marked and distinguished. When the idea
was fully completed, or as fully as the limits of human
thought will allow, the elements were no longer distin-
guished from each other, but the object was thought in its
collective unity as a whole. One or two comprehensive
names include everything.
Jerome,^ following the computation of the Jews, enume-
rates no less than ten names of God in Hebrew : " El,
Elohim, Eloe, Sabaoth, Elion, Eser-Ieje, Adonai, Jah,
Jehovah and Saddai." But Eloah and Elohim are evi-
dently the same name in different numbers, one being sin-
gular and the other plural. Sabaoth is not a name itself,
but only a descriptive epithet applied to other names of
God, particularly Jehovah. It is usually translated hosts,
^ Epist. ad Marcell. de Decern Nom.
Lect. v.] THE NAMES OF GOD. 145
and seems to be a compendious expression for the universal do-
minion of God. The Lord of Hosts is the Lord of all worlds
and of all their inhabitants. Three others in the list are pro-
bably variations of one and the same name — Jehovah, Ehyeh
and Jah. The two most important desig-
Two of the Hebrew . p nt i l_ • i • ji tt i
names predominant. natious of God which occur m the Hebrew
Scriptures are unquestionably Elohim and
Jehovah. These are the most common and the most com-
plete. They seem to contain within themselves every attri-
bute which every other title connotes, and are consequently
rendered, and rendered very properly, by dso^ and xupio^ in
Greek. The use of them in the Pentateuch is very remark-
able.^ There are (a) sections in which the name Elohim
either exclusively or predominantly obtains ; (b) there are
sections, again, in which the name Jehovah is tlie exclusive
or ^predominant one ; (c) there are other sections in which
the names are promiscuously used ; and then (d) there are
others in which no name of God appears at all. From the
seventh chapter of Exodus onward, with two or three ex-
ceptions, the name Elohim almost entirely disappears,
(a.) The sections in which the name Elohim prevails are —
1. From the beginning of the first chapter
Elohim sections. . ii.i
of Genesis to the third verse of the second —
the account of the creation. 2. The fifth chapter of Gene-
sis— the generations of Adam, Avith the exception of the
twenty-ninth verse. 3. The sixth chapter, from the ninth
to the twenty-second verse — the generations of Noah.
4. The seventh chapter, from the ninth to the twenty-
fourth verse — the entrance into the ark, except that in the
sixteenth verse the name Jehovah appears. 5. The eighth
chapter, to the nineteenth verse — the end of the flood.
6. The ninth chapter, to the seventeenth verse — the cove-
nant with Noah. 7. The seventeenth chaj)ter — the insti-
tution of circumcision. Here also the name Jehovah ap-
pears in the first verse. 8. The twentieth chapter —
1 Delitzsch, Com. Gen. Einleit, p. 30. Conf. note, p. 63, the substance
of which is given in the text.
Vol. I.— 10
146 THE NAMES OF GOD. [Lect. V.
Sarah's deliverance from Abimelech. Here again Jeho-
vah is found in the eighteenth verse. 9. The tAventy-first
chapter, to the twenty-first verse — the birth of Isaac and the
sending away of Ishmaeh Jehovah here again appears in
the first verse. 10. The twenty-first chapter, from the
twenty -second to the twenty-fourth verse — Abraham's
league with Abimelech. In the thirty-third verse we
have Jehovah again. 11. The twenty-fifth chapter, to the
eighteenth verse — the sons of Keturah, Abraham's death
and the generations of Ishmael. The word, however,
occurs but once in all this section. 12. From the forty-
sixth verse of the twenty-seventh chapter to the ninth
verse of the twenty-eighth chapter — Jacob's dismission
to Haran, and Esau's marriage. We have Elohim once
and El-Sliaddai once. 13. The thirty-first chapter —
Jacob's departure from Laban, with the exception of the
third and tlie forty-ninth verses, in whicli we have Jehovah.
14. Chapter thirty-third — Jacob's return home. 15. Chap-
ter thirty-fifth — Jacob's journey to Bethel. 16. From chap-
ter forty to chapter fifty — the history of Joseph in Egypt.
In the eighteenth verse of chapter forty-nine we have Jeho-
vah. 17. The first and second chapters of Exodus — Israel's
oppression in Egypt and the first preparation for deliverance.
With Elohim is interchanged in these sections El-Shad-
dai and El ; in connections, such as El-Elohe-Israel (chap,
xxxiii. 20), or by itself alone (chap. xxxv. 1 , 3), and only
once Adonai (chap. xx. 4).
(b.) The sections in which the name Jehovah prevails
are — 1. From Genesis, second chapter,
Jehovah sections. /> i i • t i
fourth verse, to third chapter, twenty-
fourth verse — the beginning of the history of man. 2.
Chapter fourth — the history of the first seed of the woman.
3. Chapter sixth, from the first to the eighth verse — the
increasing corruption before the flood. 4. Chapter sev-
enth, from the first to the eighth verse — entrance into the
ark. 5. Chapter eighth, from the twentieth to the twenty-
second verse — Noah's altar and Jehovah's blessing. 6. Chap-
Lect. v.] the names of god. 147
ter ninth, from the eighteenth to the twenty-ninth verse —
Noah's prophecy of the nations. 7. Chapter tenth — the
table of original settlements. 8. Chapter eleventh, from
the first to the ninth verse — ^the confusion of tongues. 9.
Chapter twelfth, from the first to the ninth verse — Abram's
journey to Canaan upon Jehovah's call. 10. Chapter
twelfth, from the tenth to the twentieth verse — Abram in
Egypt. 11. Chapter thirteenth — Abram's separation from
Lot. 12. Chapter fifteenth — Abram's faith and covenant-
offering. 13. Chapter sixteenth — Ishmael's birth, Hagar's
flight and return. 14. Chapter eighteenth — Jehovah's visit
to Abraham in his tent. 15. Chapter nineteenth — the de-
struction of Sodom and Gomorrah, and Lot's last history.
16. Chapter twenty-fourth — Isaac's marriage. 17. Chap-
ter twenty-fifth, from the nineteenth to the twenty-sixth
verse — the birth of the twins. 18. Chapter twenty-sixth —
Isaac's sorrows and comforts. 19. Chapter twenty-seventh,
first forty verses — transition of the birth-right to Jacob.
20. Chapter thirtieth, from the twenty-fifth to the forty-
third verse — a new covenant between Jacob and Laban.
21. Chapter thirty-eighth — the birth of Pharez and Zarah.
22. Chapter thirty-ninth — Jehovah with Joseph in Poti-
phar's house and in prison. 23. Exodus, chapter fourth,
from the eighteenth to the thirty-first verse — the return of
Moses to Egypt. 24. Exodus, chapter fifth — Pharaoh's
rouffh treatment of the messengers of Jehovah.
In these sections, from Genesis, second chapter, fourth
verse, to end of chapter third, the name Jehovah-Elohim is
the prevailing usage, a combination which occurs only once
more (Ex. ix. 30) in the whole Pentateuch. The name
Elohim occurs in this section only in the mouth of the ser-
pent and the woman. The exceptions to the universal use
of Jehovah in the other sections are very few. The word
Adonai most frequently interchanges with Jehovah, but it
is always used in the form of a compellation or address.
(Gen. xviii. 3, 27, 30, 31, 32 ; xix. 18.) The combination
Adonai-Jehovah is characteristic of Deuteronomy. It is
148 THE NAMES OF GOD. [Lect. V.
found in Genesis, fifteenth chapter, verses second and eighth,
and, with the exceptions of the passages in Deuteronomy,
occurs nowhere else in the Pentateuch. As in the Elohini
sections that title interchanges with El, so in the Jehovah
sections that title interchanges with Adonai. The title
Adonai, however, is used by Abimelech in one of the
Elohim sections.
(c.) The sections in which Jehovah and Elohim are pro-
miscuously used are Genesis, fourteenth
Sections, where used i , ii , ii,i -.i ,i i>
promiscuously. Chapter — A Dram s battle with the four
kings; twenty-second chapter, first nine-
teen verses — the offering up of Isaac ; twenty-eighth chap-
ter, from the tenth to the twenty-second verse — Jacob's
dream at Bethel ; from chapter twenty-ninth, verse thirty-
first, to chapter thirtieth, verse twenty-fom-th — the birth
and naming of the sons of Jacob. Another section (Gen.
xxxii.) in the beginning and end is Elohimish, and in the
middle Jehovish. In Exodus, from the tlxird chapter, first
verse, to the fourth chapter, seventeenth verse — ^tlie call of
Moses — besides the name Jehovah, Elohim, with the article,
occurs eight times.
[d.) The sections in which no name of God apjjears at all
are Gen. xi. 10-32 ; xxii. 20-24 ; xxiii. ;
Sections, where not c-*— r> j •' a-i a tr- • -i m-\
used at all. ^xv. 27-34; xxvu. 41-45; xxix. 1-30;
xxxiv. ; xxxvi. ; xxxvii.
It would seem, from such an extent and variety of usage,
that it would be easy to discriminate the precise shades of
meaning by which these names are distinguished from
each other. But it must be confessed, after all the efforts
of elaborate ingenuity, that a steady and
The use is often in- •/■ t i* j^* • i i j.
discriminate uniiomi distuictiou IS by uo mcaus kept up.
There are numerous passages in which no
reason can be given for the use of one in preference to the
other. It is impossible to explain, for example, as Delitzsch
has remarked,^ why in all the sections — Gen. vi. 9-22, ix.
1-17, XX. 1-17, XXXV. — the name Jehovah is nowhere used.
^ Comment. Gen. Einleit., p. 32.
Lect. v.] THE NAMES OF GOD. 149
If it were declined by design, we are unable to detect the
because both names ^ature of tlic motive. The truth is, both
are complete designa- naiucs werc rcvereuced and honoured as full
and complete designations of God. They
denoted the same object, and denoted it in the integrity of
its attributes. Hence it was often a matter of indiflPerence
which was employed. The writer consulted his taste, and
used sometimes one and sometimes the other, merely to give
an agreeable variety to his style. Where there was no
danger of ambiguity there was no need of special caution in
the selection of his terms.
But still there are passages in which the use is the evident
result of design ; and it is in these passages, assisted by the
etymology of the words, that we are to seek for their true,
original connotation.
I begin with Elohim, because that is the first name of
God which appears in the Hebrew Bible.
It is the title under which He is described
as the Creator of the world. It was Elohim who called into
being the heavens and the earth — who spake light into ex-
istence, and separated the day from the night. It was He
who stretched out the firmament ; collected the waters ; up-
raised the dry land ; and who peopled the earth with all its
variety of plants and animals. It was He who studded the
sky with stars, and appointed the seasons of the earth. It
was He who made man in His own Divine image. We can-
not but think that the selection of this term in the account
of creation was a matter of design. There must have been
a peculiar fitness in it to express the relation of the Creator
to His works. We pass through the work of the days until
we come to the origin of man. There the Elohim appears
as not only one, but as also plural. He seems to be in con-
sultation with Himself: " Let us make man, in our image,
after our likeness." The noun, too, is in the plural number;
and while its concord with singular verbs indicates unity,
its plural form indicates plurality. These are all facts which
lie upon the surface.
150 THE NAMES OF GOD. [Lect. V.
The first inference which I draw is that this word by its
very form is intended to express the trine
T^Zlm. *''' *"" Personality of God. It is the name of the
Trinity — the Father, the Son and the Holy
Ghost. The consultation in Genesis i. 26 cannot be con-
sistently explained upon any other hypothesis. That alone
is enough to set aside the notion of a pluralis majestaticus,
or a pluralis intensionis. Then, again, we find that the work
of creation is promiscuously ascribed to each Person of the
blessed Godhead. It was, in fact, the work of the Trinity.
If this is a clear and indisputable truth, we should interpret
the narrative in Genesis in conformity with its light. Thus
far, I think, the ground is firm beneath us. "When the
great God is first announced to us. He is announced to us
by a name which proclaims Him as the Father, Son and
Holy Ghost — the God whom we adore, in the new creation,
through the Lord Jesus Christ.
But the question now arises. Why has this particular
word been selected to reveal this mystery ? "What special
significancy, apart from this personal allusion, does it con-
tain ? Here I confess myself perplexed. Among the con-
flicting etymologies which have been proposed, there are
only two which seem to me worthy of
serious consideration. The first is that
which derives it from nSx, alah in the Arabic signification
of the root, to reverence, to worship, to adore. According to
this etymology, it is applied to the Trinity as the sole object
of religious worship. The God who exists in these three
Persons is the only being to whom we are at liberty to direct
our prayers or our praises. We are His, for He made us,
and we are bound to honour Him in His threefold subsist-
ence ; for in this mysterious relation He is infinitely worthy.
Delitzsch takes the Arabic root in the sense of fear, and of a
fear which deprives us of our self-possession. He supposes
that it is applied, by a natural association, to the object
which excites this fear ; and pre-eminently to God, as the
truly terrible one. But this exposition is liable to insur-
Lect. v.] the names of god. 151
mountable objections. Such fear is not the normal relation
betwixt a rational creature and God — it is the product only
of sin ; and such fear, so far from being acceptable worship,
is utterly inconsistent with the genuine spirit of devotion.
God presents Himself to us to be loved and trusted. He is
only terrible to the workers of iniquity. The other etymology
derives the word from nSx, alah, to swear, and represents
the Trinity as engaged in an eternal covenant, which was
ratified betwixt them by the solemnity of an oath. It is
certain that the Son was constituted a priest for ever after the
order of Melchizedek by an oath. The council of peace was
between them both, and reference is supposed to be had to
this august transaction — a transaction which, in its historic
accomplishment, unfolds, in full proportion, the glorious
doctrine of the three in one — when God is introduced as
erecting the stage upon which the historic fulfilment should
take place. This, I think, is the real im-
The true import of j. i? xl j.1 rn • 'x • i
giyjji^j port 01 the name — the irinity in covenant
for man's redemption ; and if this be so, it
is very suggestive that the first title by which God proclaims
Himself to our race should be a title of blessedness and grace.
He appears in the old creation only as preparing the way
for the new. He is God the Creator, that He may be also
God the Redeemer.
The analogical application of this title to kings and mag-
istrates is compatible with either etymol-
This title applicaUo -r/* r^ -\ • nil tt •
tojjiugs ogy. it God IS so called because He is
the object of reverence and fear, then the
intimation is that subjects are bound to treat their rulers
with honour and respect. If the allusion is to the eternal
covenant as ratified by an oath, then the implication is that
magistrates arc ministers of God, bound by an awful sanc-
tion to be a terror to evil-doers and a praise to them that do
well. They are reminded that their authority is a sacred
trust, and that their claim to the hoinage of their people
depends upon the fidelity with which they discharge their
duties. The people, too, are reminded of their duties, espe-
152 THE NAMES OF GOD. [Lect. V.
cially the duty of reverencing authority as an ordinance
of God.
Cocceius adopts the derivation of Elohim from alah, to
swear, but interprets the oath as the sign not of the Eternal
Covenant betwixt the Persons of the Godhead, but of the
covenant into which God enters with men in the dispensa-
tion of His grace. The reference, according to him, is to
the promises of the gospel, and the faithfulness with which
they shall certainly be fulfilled to all who believe. The
jjredominant idea in this case, as in the other, is that of a
God in covenant, so that this, however explained, may be
taken as the fundamental meaning of the word.
The next title of God which appears in the Pentateuch,
and which is everywhere used with awful
Jehovah. . i ,>
reverence, is the tetragrammaton, the lour-
lettered word, Jehovah. The Jews since the exile have
ceased to pronounce it. The Talmud
Jewish superstition. i • i i
amrms that the angels in heaven dare not
utter it, and denounces fearful vengeance upon the bold
blasphemer who should attempt to profane it. But that
the name was familiar to the patriarchs,
The patriarchs used . i i -i j. i x xi r
the name. ^hat they wcrc accustomed to the use oi
it, and knew of no superstition which con-
verted it into a charm, is manifest from many passages of
the Pentateuch. Eve repeats it without hesitation and
alarm when she gives thanks that she had gotten a man
from the Lord [Jehovah] (Gen. iv. 1 ). In the days of Enos
it is expressly said that then men began to call upon the
name of the Lord [Jehovah]. Between Bethel and Hai,
Abram is said to have pitched his tent, to have built an
altar, and to have called upon the name of the Lord [Jeho-
vah] (Gen. xii. 8, conf Gen. xiii. 4; xiv. 22; xxvii. 16).
It is the angel of the Lord [Jehovah] who appears to
Hagar, predicts the future fortunes of her son and sends her
back to her mistress (Gen. xvi. 7-14). It would be tedious
to quote the passages all through the patriarchal history
which abundantly and conclusively show that the fathers
Lect, v.] the names of god. 153
were familiar with this august and glorious name. They
used it in their solemn worship and in their religious trans-
actions with one another.
The Jewish superstition seems to derive some counte-
nance from the memorable passage, Ex. vi.
tefpTeted/'' '' ' "" 2, 3: "And God spake unto Moses and
said unto him, I am the Lord [Jehovah],
and I appeared unto Abraham, unto Isaac and unto Jacob
by the name of God Almighty, but by my name Jehovah was
I not known to them." The correct interpretation of this
passage will give us the key to the precise aspects of His
character in which God would be contemplated under the
name Jehovah. The meaning is, not that the name was
unknown to them, but that there was something in the name
which they had not yet been in a condition to realize. It
contained a virtue, the efficacy of which they had not pre-
viously experienced, but which they were now about to be
privileged to witness. To appreciate the force of this ob-
servation, we must distinguish betwixt the absolute mean-
ing of the word, and the relation of that meaning to the
children of Israel. Absolutely, and in itself, it expresses
the essential nature of God, as the One, the Infinite, the
Eternal and the Unconditioned. It is a synonym for all
those perfections which transcend the capacity of thought,
and mark God out as the only true Existence in the uni-
verse— the ovTCDQ ov. It is derived from the substantive
verb to he; it is, indeed, the third person future of that
verb, and literally signifies he is or will he. When God ap-
plies it to Himself, without relation to the manner in which
a third person would speak of Him, He uses the first person,
and says, n^nx, Eliyeh, I am, or I will he ; or, '^IT}^ "^^^^ ^"D^y
Ehyeh Asher Ehyeh, I am ivhat I am, or I am what I will he.
It is equivalent to the " Who was, who is, and who is to
come," or " shall he," of the New Testament. It expresses
the absolute plenitude of being, an esse in which, to use the
language of Cocceius, there is no deesse. It includes eter-
nity, self-existence, immutability, simplicity, omnipotence,
154 ■ THE NAMES OF GOD. [Lect. V.
omniscience, and, in short, the consummation of all possible
perfections. It means, in brief, the entire essence of God
as He is in Himself
All this the patriarchs knew. But this absolute being
presents Himself, in this title, under a special relation to
His people. It implies that what He is in Himself He
will be to them, according to the measure of their capacity.
From the fullness that is in Him they shall receive and
receive abundantly, even grace for grace. His Jehovahshij)
is the pledge of the absolute fulfilment of all His promises.
He is all, and therefore can become all, to those who fear
Him. Hence to call Himself Jehovah is to proclaim the
stability of His covenant, and to pawn His very existence
in proof that He will become, and that from Himself, the
satisfying portion of His saints. It was this relation, most
precious and interesting, of the Absolute to us, which the
fathers had not yet fully apprehended. They knew God as
the Author of blessings, but the relation of those blessings.
to Himself — the fact that it was He in the blessing that
constituted its value — this great idea had not taken posses-
sion of their souls. They had not learned that God was in
all that He freely gave, and that it was only as He was in
it that the gift was really worth receiving. Hence this is
precisely the name which suits God as a Saviour and Re-
deemer. It exactly represents the relations of the Son
when He became flesh, gave Himself a ransom for our sins,
and becomes to us, by a mysterious but glorious union.
Wisdom, Righteousness, Sanctification and Redemption.
We are in Him and He in us. We are because He is, and
because He lives we shall live also.
Hence, from the nature of the case this name cannot be
analogically transferred to any creature,
This title not trans- . ^ ^
ferabie to any crea- liowevcr cmincut or cxalted. JNo crcature
*'^'"^' can communicate as from Himself He
can only give what he receives. His sufficiency is from
God. But the peculiarity of Jehovah is, that He gives what
is His own. He is life, and therefore imparts it. He is
Lect. v.] THE NAMES OF GOD. 155
holiness, and therefore infuses it. He is blessedness, and
therefore communicates it. He is salvation, and therefore
bestows it. All that he promises He is, and therefore
His promises are Yea and Amen in Christ Jesus. It is
this relation of the Absolute to the creature that con-
stitutes the peculiar signijficancy of the name of Jehovah.
And, therefore, in a different sense, we may adopt the lan-
guage of the Jew, and pronounce this to be a glorious and
an ineffable name. It is a name at which devils may well
tremble, for it reveals the unutterable depths of their pov-
erty, while saints and angels tremble and adore. This God
is our God for ever and ever. He will be our guide even
unto death.
The application of this name to Jesus Christ, which the
writers of the New Testament do not scruple to make, is a
pregnant and unanswerable proof of His absolute divinity.
Indeed it is only in Jesus Christ that the
Full import of it p n • j_ i} iA • • ^ i
oniyinJesLcinist. ™11 import of this name IS or can be real-
ized to us. Here and here alone is Jeho-
vah, as Jehovah, known by the rich experience of the heart.
If this exposition be correct, there was a peculiar propriety
when God was about to appear as the Redeemer of Israel
in His appearing under this name. It revealed Him as an
object of assured and steadfast faith. There is also a pro-
priety in the prominence which is given to it when the
sacred writers leave the history of the world at large, and
confine their narratives for the most part to the fortunes of
God's redeemed people — His Church. There is also an ex-
quisite beauty in God's appearing under the name Jehovah
when He summons the guilty pair into His presence, and
comforts them in their sorrow under the prospect of a great
Deliverer. There is also a peculiar force and emphasis in
the combination Jehovah-Elohim, as condensing the entire
sum of the relations in which the creature can stand to God.
The third name, Jah, is generally re-
garded as an abbreviated form of Jehovah.
Like it, it is exclusively appropriated to the Sujjreme God.
156 THE NAMES OF GOD. [Lect. V.
It is peculiar to poetry, and especially the poetry of praise.
Its combination with Jehovah might seem incompatible
with the notion that it is simply an abridgment of the same
word. Cocceius derives it from the word hn;, yaah, in the
sense of decency and Jitness; and in this sense it expresses
the harmony, beauty and glory of the Divine perfections.
It is the affirmation that God is, in all respects, like Him-
self, and the absolute standard of all that is becoming and
beautiful in the creature. According to this exposition, it
represents God in that very asj)ect of His being which
renders Him the object of our praise. It is, in other words,
a compendious expression for His unutterable beauty, and is
fitly joined with hallelu, as an exhortation to praise the Lord.
Adonai, pointed with a quametz, is also a name exclusively
applied to God. It implies sovereign do-
Adonai. ^j- , , \ ^ == _
mimon, and is equivalent to Lord and
Master. It implies a dominion, however, which is founded
in ownership, and is therefore peculiarly appropriate to God,
whether we contemplate Him as Creator or Redeemer. We
are His, for He made us, and we belong pre-eminently to
Christ, for He has bought us with His own precious blood.
This is the word which the Jews substitute for Jehovah
wherever Jehovah occurs in the sacred text.
Shaddai, sometimes preceded by El, sometimes alone, is a
term by which God is represented as Al-
Shaddai. "^ .
mighty and Supreme. It is rendered by the
Septuagint Tzavroxpdrtop. It is plural in its form, jjossibly
to express the intensity and fullness of the Divine power.
El, derived from S-ik, aul, or from Vn, ayl, properly sig-
nifies the Strong One. Used absolutely and
in the singular, it is restricted universally
to the true God. It represents Him as irresistible in His
purposes, vanquishing all obstacles, subduing all enemies,
and bringing His own purposes to pass.
Elyon, from nS;?, ahdi, to ascend, is pro-
Elyon. •' ' . ' . 1 1 .
perly an adjective with a superlative sense,
and describes God as the Most High ; or the High and Lofty
Lect. v.] the names of god. 157
One who inhabiteth eternity. It is equivalent to the iK/udTOi;
of the Greeks. It simply reveals, by an easy and obvious
figure, the absolute supremacy of God.
These are the names by which the nature and perfections
of God are compendiously set forth in the Old Testament.
There are many other titles which designate special relations,
such as Judge and Lawgiver, but these can in no sense be
regarded as proper names.
In Greek we have deo^ and xupio;;, which, whatever may
Two Greek titles ^^vc becu the Original ground of their use,
answering to Eiohim i;iow dcuotc tlic Suprcmc Jcliovah, and
and Jehovah. . • /, , . , ^ tt-*
signify at the same time the sum oi His
perfections, and of the essential relations in which He stands
to His creatures. The fundamental notion in xupcoz, Lord,
is certainly that of power and of rightful dominion ; but, in
the Sejjtuagint and New Testament it is made synonymous
with Jehovah, and must consequently be taken in the full
sense of that glorious name. The fundamental notion of
deoQ, God, may be that of the Arranger — God as the author
of the beauty and order in the Universe ; but the Septuagint
has made it equivalent to Eiohim, and we are to employ it
in no more restricted sense. Indeed, it was the only strictly
proper name among the Greeks for the supreme and ever-
lasting God.
These Divine names served a most important purpose
among the patriarchs in recording, preserving and giving
unity to their knowledge of God. They could hardly have
been dispensed with. The concept of an earthly object re-
quires a sign to hold its elements together ; much more does
such a concept as that of God. We see the value of names
in the instruction of children. It is through the explanation
of words that they are slowly and progressively conducted
to the knowledge of things. How graciously has God con-
descended, in the revelation of Himself, to our weakness and
our faculties !
LECTURE VI.
THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD.
WHEN we come to a closer determination of the nature
and attributes of God, we encounter the question,
Whether there is any sense in which He can be defined ?
That no human language can represent Him as He is in
Himself is perfectly obvious from the fact, that no human
thought can conceive Him in His infinite and absolute
essence. Here, in the words of the venerable Cyril of Jeru-
salem,^ our highest knowledge is to confess our ignorance.
The very notion, moreover, of defining the infinite, seems to
involve a contradiction. To define is to limit, to determine,
to restrict; but the infinite must cease to be infinite in
coming under these conditions of human
God indefinable, , . ..irti
thought. As it exists in itself, therefore, it
is manifestly indefinable. Add to this, that God transcends
all the distinctions of Logic which definition presupposes.
He is neither genus nor species. Intensely and exclusively
singular, He stands alone in His being ; there are none on
earth to be compared with Him, none in heaven to be ranked
with Him. " To whom then will we liken God, or what
likeness will ye compare unto Him ?" ^
But the case is different in relation to our own finite oon-
butwecanexpressour ccptious. Tlicsc, though inadequate to rep-
finite conceptions of rcscut God, may themselves be adequately
represented in language. If we cannot
answer the question, what God is in Himself, we can certainly
answer the question, what God is as He appears to us. We
1 Catechis., vi. 2. 2 Isa. xl. 18.
158
Lect. VI.] THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. 159
can combine our knowledge and our faith in the terms of a
description which, though not conformable with the laws,
may answer all the ends of a logical definition. Our ana-
logical concepts we can refer to a genus, and this genus we
can distinguish by the properties which we know and believe
We must conceive of ^ be csscutial to God. Wc think the
God as substance and Divinc, as wc do cvcry otlicr being, under
the relation of substance and attribute ; the
substance being determined by the attributes, and the at-
tributes conceived as manifestations of the substance. When
asked. Quid sit f we answer in terms descriptive of the sub-
stance ; when asked, Qualis sit f we answer in terms descrip-
tive of the attributes. In conformity with this view various
definitions have been given of God. Some
A definition of God t n tt* xI i i j i c i ^ •
considered. defiuc Him as the absolutely perfect bemg
— heing the genus ; and absolutely perfect,
the specific difiference. But the difficulty here is that no
positive knowledge is conveyed. We begin with a series of
negations, and can never translate ourselves beyond the
sphere of darkness in which we have placed ourselves. We
confound a faith in an unknown reality with a positive de-
termination of human thought. To this and all such defi-
nitions pretending to posit the essence of the absolute, the
following remarks of Van Mastricht^ are applicable : " This
is no more a legitimate definition of God than to say of man,
He is the most perfect sublunary being, would be a legitimate
definition of him. And yet who would accept such a defini-
tion, or admit it as any real explication of the human essence?
No more is that a genuine definition of God which simply
represents Him as the absolutely perfect being. For neither
the genus heing, to which He is assigned, nor the difference,
absolutely perfect, contains any real explication of His essence.
Not being, for that rather proj)Oses than explains it ; affirms
that it is, rather than what it is. Not absolutely perfect, be-
cause that seems to express a relation or comparison, by
which the essence of God surpasses the essence of every other
^ Quoted in De Moor, cap. iv., § 11.
160 THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lect. VL
thing. Everything whatever, as long as it is, is a something
perfect. Hence, by j^^rfection simjily, the essence of God
cannot be accurately discriminated from the essence of any
other thing. The addition of the qualifying epithet abso-
lutely, only institutes a comparison, but determines nothing
as to the nature of the things compared."
Perrone,^ the distinguished professor of theology in the
Jesuit College at Rome, makes the essence of God to consist
in His independence and self-existence. According to him,
an essence should always fulfil four condi-
A second definition ,• -iTii ill j1' •,••
considered. tious : 1. It sliould DC Something lutrmsic
to the thing; 2. It should distinguish it
from every other thing ; 3. It should be first in the order
of thought when we undertake to conceive the thing ; and,
4. It should be construed as the fons et origo of all its per-
fections. These conditions in relation to God, he maintains,
are realized in the notion of self-existence. This, then, is
the Divine essence. But what do we know of self-existence
apart from the denial of a cause ? What positive concept have
we from which we can deduce any positive conclusion what-
ever ? Just give to a man what he calls the notion of self-
existence and nothing else — the mere negation of a cause —
and what is he likely to achieve in the way of revealing the
only true God of our worship ? The negative can give no-
thing but the negative. Remove the manifestations which
God has made of Himself in the works of creation and
providence — remove the Scriptures, and leave us nothing
but the naked concept of necessary being — and it seems to
me intuitively obvious that it would be as barren of results
as the baldest identical proi^osition. As regulative, in the
sphere of positive thought, it is immensely important. But
as a fons et origo of perfections, it is as sterile as the sands
of Arabia.
"VYe dismiss, therefore, as frivolous all efforts to represent
the essence of God, as thought, in terms of the absolute. If
we ascribe to Him any attributes at all, we are constrained
^ Prselect. TheoL, Pt. I., c. iii., prop. iii.
Lect. VI.] THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. 161
by the constitution of our nature to think Him as a sub-
stance or subject in which these attributes inhere. That
substance must be determined by the nature of the attributes
themselves. And as we know of but two substances, mind
and matter, we are constrained to represent God under the
analogy of one or the other, according as the manifestations
in His works and the revelation of His vford shall decide.
He is either material or spiritual. Between these, so far as
known to us, there is no middle ; and which
to be asptru^'""^ ^^ ^^ thcsc most fitly represents the nature of
God is hardly susceptible of doubt.
The best definition, in a brief compass, is that contained
in the Shorter Catechism of the Westminster Assembly :
God is a Spirit, infinite, eternal and un-
The best definition. . tt- i • • 7
changeable m Uis being, wisdom, power,
holiness, justice, goodness and truth. Here the genus to
which the substance of God is referred is spirit, in strict
accordance with the Scriptures and the manifestations of
His nature which are made by His works ; the difference,
those qualities which belong to spirit in its full and normal
development, heightened beyond all bounds of conception
by terms which are borrowed from God as an object of
faith. In this definition there is an admirable combination
of what we know with what we are only able to believe,
and God is represented in language precisely as He appears
in thought. There is but one defect. It
But it is defective.
seems to me that the peculiar personality
of God should have been distinctly and prominently an-
nounced. He is not only Spirit, but Personal Spirit, and
not Personal barely, but Tri-persoual — the Father, the Son
and the Holy Ghost. To describe Him as a Spirit subsist-
ing in three Persons, and then as infinite, eternal and un-
changeable in all the perfections which are proper to Spirit,
is to make as near an approximation to an accurate defini-
tion as it is possible for our faculties to compass,^ Spirit
expresses the nature and answers the question, Quid sit?
1 Cf. De Moor, c. iv., § 12.
Vol. L— 11
162 THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lkct. VI.
The properties express the perfections and answer the ques-
tion, Quails sit f One can only be thought
Answer to the two ^^ ^^^ correlative of the other.' We know
questions.
the nature, as a 2")ermanent, unchanging
subject, only through the attributes by which it is revealed,
and know it only as their ground and centre of unity.
The notion of attributes arises from the nature of the
effects which we are constrained to ascribe to the agency of
God. We know what He is by seeing what He does. We
remark the traces of order and design
How we get our no- o
tions of God's attri- whicli are everywhere conspicuous around
us, and we immediately feel that the Au-
thor of the universe must be possessed of knowledge and
wisdom. We listen to the teachings of our own consciences,
and cannot but collect that He who compels us to distinguish
in our own souls betwixt the right and the wrong is Himself
a being of rectitude. The products of His will, in the
mighty works of His hands which are everywhere dis-
played to view, are in the same way confessions of His
power. Attributes, therefore, may be defined as the deter-
minations of the Divine Being to human thought, suggested
by the relations in which He stands to His works. They
are the modes under which we conceive Him.
All the attributes of God are essential ; that is, they are
nothing separate and distinct from God,
They are not sepa- ^ (j ^ Himsclf manifested in such and
rable froni His essence. -^ >-' ^ ^ ^
such forms. The same may be said of the
faculties of the human soul ; they are not something distinct
from the soul, and added to it as a complement to its being,
but are only the soul itself existing in such and such modes
of consciousness. We can logically discriminate betwixt
essence and properties ; and in every other being there are
properties which may be conceived as detached from the
essence, but in the case of God the essence and the proper-
ties completely coincide. He has no separable accidents.
All that He is. He is essentially. The importance of this
principle has been illustrated in the controversy with the
Lect. VI.] THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. 163
Socinians, who were willing to acknowledge the Holy Ghost
as an attribute of God, but were not willing to acknowledge
Him as God.
It is commonly maintained by divines not only that the
attributes are not distinct from the essence,
Their being all rad- ^^^ ^j^^^ ^j^ ^^,^ ^^^^ ^^^^jj distiuct from
ically one, '' 'i
one another. They are all radically one.
Wisdom, goodness, justice, power, anger, pity, love, — all
these, as they exist in God, are really one and the same
mode of consciousness. This conclusion is supposed to be
necessitated by the doctrine of the simplicity of God. He
is held to be absolved from every species of composition,
physical, logical and metaphysical. He is not a whole
made up of parts. He admits of no distinctions of genus
and species, or of substance and quality. He is nakedly
and absolutely one. There are and can be no differences or
distinctions in His nature. It is said, ac-
Sioi^u'LT"'^' cordingly, that if weascribe to Him attri-
butes really distinct from each other, each
would be a different thing, and the unity of God, instead
of being one, simple and indivisible, would be an aggregate
or sum of different qualities. I can understand how the
simplicity and unity of God absolve Him from physical and
loo:ical distinctions. I can understand that He is not com-
posed of parts, like body, nor capable of being classed under
genera and species, but I cannot understand why the meta-
physical distinction of substance and quality is at all incon-
„ , .,,.,, sistent with the most perfect simplicity.
Reply to this state- J- i ./
ment from the doc- If all distinctious of cvery kind are to be
trine of the Trinity, i i i /• .1 /^ Jl j r • -j.
excluded from the Godhead, how is it pos-
sible to reconcile the doctrine of the Trinity with the abso-
lute unity of the Divine nature? The very core of the
doctrine is that there are distinctions, and distinctions in
the essence of the Godhead without which there would and
could be no God at all. The truth is, absolute simplicity is
to us wholly unintelligible ; it is only the negation of every
form of composition. But when every form of composition
164 THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lect. VI.
is removed, the positive thing that remains transcends our
capacity of thought. We know not what it is, and it is
idle to undertake to reason from it as if it were a positive
element of knowledge.
To us the law of substance and quality is an intrinsic
condition of existence, independently of which we are un-
able to think any object whatever ; and as the law of human
knowledge is that of plurality and diifer-
our owu^iinds '^^ ° eucc, qualities must be presented as distinct
manifestations of their substance, or they
convey nothing to the mind. Absolute identity to beings
constituted as we are would be as bootless as absolute non-
entity. Tf the simplicity of the human soul is not disturbed
or impaired by distinct modes of consciousness, if it con-
tinues permanently one in the midst of the many, I see no
heresy in supposing that something analogous may obtain in
the infinite being of God, and that He reconciles variety
with unity, distinctions with simplicity, in a manner which
does not detract from His absolute perfection.
How the one in God appears as the many to us is ex-
plained by the distinction betwixt virtual or eminent and
„^ ^. ,. , . real difference. This distinction plays so
The distinction of r J
eminent and real dif- important a part in theological treatises
' that I shall take this opportunity to ex-
plain it. Distinction or difference is the negation of iden-
tity. Things can differ either in themselves or in our modes
of conceiving them. When they differ in themselves, the
difference is said to be real. When the difference is only in
our modes of conceiving, it is said to be virtual or eminent.
The reason of the term is this : the thing, though one and
simple in itself, in the manifold effects which it produces
and the manifold relations in which it is thought, is con-
strued as equivalent to them all, and as containing them in
a higher form of perfection than that in which they are real-
ized. A grain of Avheat, for example, is one and simple
in itself, but it may be conceived in various aspects and rela-
tions. It may be thought simply as a body, composed of
Lect, VI.] THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. 165
parts ; it may be thought as an article of food ; it may be
thought merely as a seed. Here are three modes of con-
ceiving the same thing, which yet abides in its unity. So
God, absolutely simple in Himself, contains in Himself what
is equivalent to all the effects He has produced. He is
potentially all that He does. That is eminently in Him —
that is, exists in the form of a higher perfection in Him —
which is realized in the outward universe.^
It is maintained, accordingly, that while in the intrinsic
relation of existence there is no real differ-
tfon^'Iud*" ^^^^ '^"''^ 6^1^^ among the attributes of God, all being
equally God Himself, in the extrinsic rela-
tions of working and manifestation differences emerge, but
the differences are in the effects and not in the cause. As
we conceive the cause, however, in relation to the effects, we
1 [" Distinction or difference is the negation of identity. Things are dis-
tinguished v/hich are not the same. A thing can be different from another,
either in itself or in our conception. When diiferent in itself, the distinction
is called real ; when only in our conception, it is called rational or mental.
" Things differ in themselves, either because they are separate, as Peter
and Paul ; or separable, as soul or body ; or relatively opposed, as father
and son. This species of distinction is called realis major. Things may
differ solely as the mode differs from the thing modified, as figure and
body, cogitation and mind. This distinction is called modal, or distinctio
realis minor. To these John Duns Scotus added a third — namely, between
two or more properties of the same thing, when they diflfer only in their
formal reason, as in man, animality and rationality ; in God, essence and
attributes ; and among the attributes themselves, as justice and mercy are
formally distinguished. This was called formal difference or distinctio
realis minima.
" Mental distinction is of two kinds — one purely arbitrary, as when we
distinguish between Peter and Cephas, there being no foundation for the
distinction in the thing itself, it is called distinctio rationis ratiocinanfis ;
the other is when there is a foundation in the thing, which though one and
absolutely simple in itself," is yet equivalent to many different things, and
on account of the variety of its effects causes us to consider it in different
aspects and relations, as a grain may be seed, food or body. So God, ab-
solutely simple in Himself, produces different effects, and therefore con-
tains in Himself what is equivalent to these effects, or rather superior to
them — contains it eminently. The same thing in Him makes differences
among the creatures. This is the distinctio rationis ratiocinatce, or virtual
difference." — Perrone, Pt. II., c. i.]
166 THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lect. VI.
give it a different determination according to the nature of
the effect. Knowledge and power, for examj)le, in God are
one and the same, but knowledge and power terminate in
different effects, and the difference of determination given
by these effects involves a corresponding difference in human
conception. This difference, depending upon the difference
of effect, and upon a corresponding difference in our mode
of conceiving, is called a virtual or eminent difference.
If the extrinsic relations under which we think do not
coincide with the intrinsic relations under which the attri-
butes of God exist, it would seem that our knowledge is
deceitful and illusive. To this it is replied, that the know-
ledge is real as far as it goes. It fails to tell us what God
is in Himself; in that aspect he is wholly incomprehensible ;
but it does unfold to us His relations to the creature. These
relations are real ; and though they seem to reveal a mani-
fold perfection in God, they are not delusive, so long as they
reveal what is still higher and better than anything which
can be conceived as many. Properly interpreted, the mani-
^ , , . , ^ fold in nature only teaches that there is
God shown to be One, ^ •'^
without any divers- that iu God wliicli is Competent to produce
'*^' it. He is eminently, in the resources of
His being, all that the universe contains. As one, He gives
rise to diversity, but the diversity is not in Him.
All this is ingenious, and to some extent intelligible, but
is very far from being a satisfactory account
Ingenious, but not ^ ^ distiuctiou which wc are coustraiued
satistactory.
to make in the attributes of God. No jug-
gling with scholastic technicalities can ever confound or fuse
into one modes of consciousness so really distinct as those
of intelligence and will. It may be that in the absolute
they are reduced to unity, but it is perfectly certain that we
cannot see how they are virtually the same. It may be that
pity and justice completely coincide as they exist in God,
but it is impossible for us to comprehend how the one is
eminently the other. The true view is, that this whole
subject transcends the sphere of our faculties. We can only
Lect. VL] THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. 167
obey the law of our nature ; and the very determinations
which lead us to ascribe any attributes to God lead us, at
the same time, to distinguish them. The differences may
be only apparent, but to us they must be construed as real
until the delusion is detected. That, however, never can
be done by abstract speculations on simplicity.
Seeing that we can know God only under the relation of
distinct properties and attributes, it is im-
Classification of at- j. j. j. i j_ i • l
tributes necessary. portaut to adopt somc comprchensivc mode
of classifying and arranging these mani-
festations of the Divine Being. In some treatises the
method is simply synthetic — adding attribute to attribute
as each is unfolded in the process of the argument. For
instance, they set out with Being; the temporal and the
contingent give the eternal and the necessary. Here are
two predicates to be applied to the first being. Eternity
implies immutability and infinity. Here are two other
predicates. Through the traces of order and design the
predicates of intelligence and goodness are collected ; and
so on through the whole list of the known attributes of God.
Here there is no classification. There is simply a process of
synthesis by means of a previous analysis. In this way the
attributes are generally treated in works on Natural Theology.
Among the schemes of distribution proposed by theolo-
gians the following divisions may be signalized: 1. Into
Absolute and Relative. The Absolute em-
Seven schemes of dis- i . i f ,• f r^ ^ , c
tribution signalized. "^races the pcrfcctions of God as out of
relation to the creature ; the Relative, the
same perfections as in relation to the creature. " Thus," to
use the illustration of De Moor, appropriated by Dr. Breck-
inridge,^ " goodness would be considered an absolute attri-
bute, while mercy would be considered a relative one, as
being founded in goodness, but having a special relation to
the creature ; and in like manner immensity would be con-
sidered an absolute, and omnipresence a relative, attribute ;
holiness an absolute, and punitive justice a relative, attribute ;
' Object. Theol., Book iii., c. xvii. Cf. De Moor, c. iv. I 19.
168 THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lect. VI,
and so of the rest." 2. Into Positive and Negative. The
Positive are those which can be affirmatively predicated of
God — such as wisdom, goodness, justice ; the Negative are
those which can only be expressed by negations — such as
infinity, eternity, immensity. 3. Into Quiescent and Active
or Operative. The Quiescent coincide with what have been
called the immanent perfections of God; the Operative, Avith
the transient. 4. Into Primitive and Derivative — those
from which others are derived, and those so derived. 5.
Into JNIetaphysical, Physical, or Natural — for all these
terms have been used to express the same class — and INIoral,
embracing those connected with intelligence and will. The
first set of terms includes all the attributes of God consid-
ered simply as the infinite and absolute ; the second, those
which belong to Him as a Personal Spirit. The most com-
mon distribution is — 6. Into Communicable and Incommu-
nicable.^ The Communicable refers to those of which some
analogy can be found in the perfections of the creature ; the
Incommunicable, to those which admit of no such analogy.
7. Into Internal and External ; " which division," says De
Moor,^ " is accommodated to the philosophy of Des Cartes,
according to which the whole nature of God is resolved into
mere cogitation, to the exclusion of everything else which,
except thought, can be conceived. From this jorinciple are
deduced only two internal attributes of God — Intellect and
Will ; because there are only two general modes of thought
— ^perception or the operation of intellect, and volition or
the operation of will. Hence all the other attributes of
God are considered merely as external denominations."
These distinctions, though variously expressed, are nearly
All these pervaded ^11 fundamentally the same. They are per-
i>y a common vein of yadcd by a commott veiu of thought — a
fact which cannot be explained without
admitting that they have a real foundation in the nature of
our knowledge of God. And yet the common idea which
^ Howe, Principles, etc., Part i., Lect. 17. Turrett. Loc. iii., Qu. 6,
2 Chap, iv., ^ 19.
Lect. VI.] THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. 169
pervades them has not been distinctly and consciously seized ;
otherwise the attributes would have been determined by
it, and not by the aspects in which they happen to be
contemplated. There is evidently this fundamental distinc-
tion between one of these classes and the other — that, in
the one case, what are called attributes or properties are not
specific determinations, but characteristics of every attri-
bute and property manifested in the relation of God to His
works. They are not a mode of consciousness or being,
co-ordinate with other modes of consciousness or being.
They are not related as memory and imagination in the
human soul, but rather as consciousness — the universal con-
dition of intelligence — to the whole soul. They are not ex-
pressive of particular forms of Divine agency, but are rather
pervading conditions — if we may indulge the solecism —
of the Divine existence. God is not wise and infinite, but
He is infinite in His wisdom as well as in His being.
"What He is determinately to human thought, that He is
infinitely, eternally and unchangeably. This is the dis-
tinction w^liich all these divisions tacitly recognize. It is
the absolute of faith transferred to the manifested and
known. It is God as believed lying at the basis of all that
is revealed, and never for a moment to be divorced from it.
The one set of properties might therefore be callc«i modes
of being — the other, properties of nature or determinative
properties. The one set may be referred to the fundamental
notion of necessary existence, the other to
disunctior"'"""*" the fundamental notion of a Personal Spirit.
Around these two central points we may
collect and arrange all that we can know of God. The first
notion gives Eternity, Immensity, Independence, Immuta-
bility ; the second gives Intelligence and Will, and all those
perfections which are included in the idea of a perfect Spirit.
Unity and Simplicity are included in both.
Communicable and incommunicable are terms very badly
chosen to express the ideas which they were intended to
convey. They seem to imply that the perfection in man is
170 THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lect. VI.
an emanation from the corresponding perfection of God, or
at least that the two are formally the same. But there is
really nothing that is strictly common betwixt them but the
word. They are analogous, but not alike. The relations
are the same, but the things themselves differ as widely as
the infinite and finite.
Dr. Hodge, in the " Outlines of Theology," ^ published
by his son, has suggested a classification
Classifications of /• .i ta* • jj*ii ^ • ^ • ' ^
jjpj^g ol the JJivme attributes wdiich coincides
almost precisely with that which I have
proposed. He makes four classes — "1. Those attributes
which equally qualify all the rest: Infinitude, that which
has no bounds ; Absoluteness, that which is determined
either in its being or modes of being or action by nothing
whatsoever without itself. This includes immutability.
2. Natural attributes ; God is an infinite Spirit, self -existent,
eternal, immense, simple, free of will, inteUigent, pjoioerful.
3. Moral attributes. God is a Spirit infinitely riyhteous,
good, true and faithful. 4. The consummate glory of all
the Divine perfections in union — the beauty of holiness."
Dr. Breckinridge, in his " Objective Theology," proposes
a classification much more complicated and
and of Breckinridge. . i • i
elaborate. It is developed in the seven-
teenth chapter of the work. A general view of it is con-
tained in the summary of the closing section : " According
to this method we are enabled to contemplate God succes-
sively— 1. As He is an infinite Being, and endowed Avitli
the proper perfections thereof. 2. As He is an infinite
Spirit, and endowed with the proper perfections thereof.
3. As being both, and endowed with all perfections that
belong to both, considered with reference to the eternal and
ineifaceable distinction between true and false, which is the
fundamental distinction with which our own rational facul-
ties are conversant. 4. As being endowed with all perfec-
tions with reference to the eternal and ineffaceable distinc-
tion between good and evil, which is the fundamental
1 Page 104.
Lect. YL] THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. 171
distinction with which our moral faculties are conversant.
5. As being endowed with all perfections which underlie,
which embrace or which result from the union of all the
preceding perfections. And so the classes of his perfections
would necessarily be — 1 . Those called Primary Attributes —
that is, such as belong to an infinite and self-existent Being,
simply considered. 2. Essential Attributes — that is, those
belonging to such a Being considered essentially as an infi-
nite Spirit. 3. Natural Attributes — that is, such as apper-
tain to an infinite Spirit, considered naturally, rather than
morally or essentially. 4, Moral Attributes — that is, such
as appertain to such a Being, considered morally, rather
than naturally or essentially. 5. Consummate Attributes —
that is, such as appertain to such a Being considered com-
pletely and absolutely."
It is obvious, in the first place, that the terms in which
this classification is expressed are unhappily chosen. "When
we read of Primary Attributes, we expect to meet as a matter
of course with others that are Secondary. But in this case
the protasis has no apodosis. Fundamental would have been
a better word than Primary. Then Essential and Natural
are so nearly synonymous that it can only breed confusion
to use them in contrast. Besides, all attributes of God are
equally essential. There are none, therefore, entitled, by
way of j)re-eminence, to usurp this distinction.
In the next place, the classification is confused. God as
Spirit is distinguished from God as intelligent. The natural
attributes are made pendants of the essential, as if there were
a faculty of knowledge in God apart from His knowledge
itself. Abating the perplexity and confusion both of thought
and language, the classification is substantially the same as
that of Dr. Hodge. The Primary attributes are those which
I have described as Modal, or all-pervading, and Dr. Hodge
has spoken of as qualifying all the rest. The Essential and
Natural are those which Dr. Hodge has called simply Nat-
ural— avoiding the implication that there is any distinction
between faculty and acts in the Divine understanding. The
172 THE NATURE AND ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lect. VI.
JNIoral arc the same in both divisions. The Consummate
do not exactly coincide, but they differ only in extension.
The simplest division is that ^^•hich is
The Bimplost divisiou. i i • i i .
grounded in the obvious distinction between
those perfections which j^ervade the whole being and every
other perfection of God, and those which are special and de-
terminative. Here the boundaries are clear and distinct.
The determinative attributes of God may be subdivided into
Intellectual and Moral — the two great outlines which include
all the excellence of a personal Spirit. The Consummate
attributes seem to me to be a needless distinction.
In the development of this subject the plan which I shall
pursue will be first, to treat of the nature of God as Spiritual
and Personal ; and then to unfold the attributes in the order
in which they have here been classed.
LECTURE VII.
SPIRITUALITY OF GOD.
THE spirituality of God is the foundation of all religious
worship. It is only as a spirit that He is possessed of
those attributes of intelligence, goodness,
This truth, the foun- .,• it i,,i i-i
dation of the worship, justice, powcr, holuiess and truth which
make Him the object of our prayers, our
praises, our confidence and hopes. It is only as a spirit that
He is a person, and, consequently, only as a spirit that He
can enter into communion with us and communicate to us
the tokens of His favour and His love. A blind force, a
stern and irresistible necessity, might be an object of terror
and of dread, but it would be absurd to pray to it, to trust
in it, or to love it. Our Saviour, in His interview with the
woman of Samaria, makes the spirituality of God determine
the nature and the kind of worship which we are to render
to the Father of our spirits. But the argument goes much
farther — it determines the ground of the possibility of wor-
ship. There could be no true worshippers at all, for there
would be nothing to which worshij) could be consi.stently
adapted, if God were not spirit.
More than this : the spirituality of God is not only the
foundation of all religious worship — it is
butes'^of God! '^''"" ^^^ foundation of all the Divine attributes.
Without spirit there could be no life;
without life, no activity ; without activity, no causal agency.
Infinity, immensity, eternity, simplicity and immutability,
as well as omniscience, holiness, goodness and truth, are
grossly incompatible with the notion of matter as compound,
173
174 SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. [Lect. VIT.
divisible, disecrptible, clestriictible. Hence, to deny that
God is spirit is tantamount to Atheism.
There is only one passage of Scripture in which it is ex-
plicitly affirmed that God is a spirit, but
Scripture proofs of ,i i j • • • t •,^ , - i • n
tho doctrine. '^"^ doctriuc IS imphcitly contained in all
the representations which it makes of His
nature and perfections. In John iv. 24 the direct testimony
of Christ has been evaded by making Spirit the accusative
case, and supplying the word seeks from the preceding verse.
The sense would then be not that God is a spirit, but that
God seeks the spirit, or demands the spirit from His wor-
shippers. This is the interpretation of Vorstius. The
reason which he assigns is, that the argument from the nature
of God to the nature of the worship He exacts is not valid
and consequential. It is not His nature, but His will that
determines the character of worship. But to this it may be
readily replied that the nature determines the will ; so that
the nature of God is the foundation, while the will of God is
the rule or measure of religious worship.^ If the reasoning,
it is contended, from a spiritual nature to a spiritual worship
is valid, then the inference would be sound from a bodily
worship, such as that enjoined upon the Jews, to a bodily
nature. But it is forgotten that the body is not the wor-
shipper, but only an instrument of w^orship. It is the means
of manifesting the inward condition — the outward expression
of the invisible spirit. Apart from this relation, bodily ex-
ercise profiteth nothing. There seems to be no good reason,
therefore, for departing from the ordinary interpretation :
God is a spirit. But even if we should adopt the exposition
of Vorstius, the spirituality of God might still, as Limborch -
suggests, be fairly collected from the text. Why should He
demand a spiritual worship if He were not a spiritual being ?
Why should He exact an homage that was wholly inconsist-
ent with his essential perfections ? — an homage, in fact, by
which the worshipper shows himself superior to the wor-
shipped.
^ Charnock, vol. i., p. 245. * Theol. Christ., Lib. ii., c. iv.
Lect. VII.] SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. 175
Among the passages in which tlie spirituality of God is
obviously implied are Numbers xvi. 22, in which lie is en-
titled The God of tlie spirits of all flesh ; and Hebrews xii.
9, in which He is denominated The Father of spirits. He
is evidently their Father, in the sense that they spring from
Him and are like Him. The contrast betwixt God and the
Egyptians in Isaiah xxxi. 3, " that the Egyptians are men
and not God, and their horses flesh and not spirit," proceeds
upon the assumption that God is pre-eminently spiritual.
The Third Person of the Trinity is unquestionably spirit.
Holy Spirit or Holi/ Ghost (for ghost and spirit are synony-
mous) is His proper name, and as Pie is substantially the
same with the Father and the Son, the Father and the Son
must be spirit also. All those passages, moreover, which
ascribe wisdom, knowledge, counsel, purjjose and decrees to
God — which represent Him, in other words, as possessed of
intellectual and moral perfections — are so many proofs of a
spiritual nature. As the stream cannot rise higher than the
fountain, the existence of finite and dependent spirits in the
case of angels and of men involves the existence of the Su-
preme and Absolute spirit as their principle and source. He
that planted the ear, shall not He hear ? He that formed
the eye, shall not He see ? He that chastiseth the heathen,
shall not He correct ? He that teach eth man knowledge, shall
not He know ? Abolish this doctrine of the Divine spirit-
uality, and the Scripture testimonies to God become a tissue
of contradictions and absurdities. It lies at the root of
everything they teach.
The ancient heathen philosophers concur in the same fun-
damental truth. The supreme God of
The ancient phiios- pj^^^^ ^^^^^ Aristotlc figurcs as thc Supreme
ophers coucur. o l
intelligence or mind. Socrates sought Him
as the explanation of the principle of order, and pursues the
argument from final causes in the very spirit of modern
teleologists. Plutarch^ calls Him a pure intelligence, simple
and unmixed in His own nature, but mingling Himself with
' Quoted in Owen, vol. viii., p. 147.
176 SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. [Lkct. YII.
eveiytlilng besides. And whatever may be said of the Pan-
theistic vein, the testimony to God as Mind is clear and de-
cisive in the well-known lines of Virgil :
" Spiritus intus alit, totamque infusa per artus
Mens agitat molem." ^
The spirituality of God is both a negative and a positive
truth. As negative it denies of Him the
loftTlrmateriar' propcrties and ^ affcctions of matter; it is
equivalent to immaterial. Hence He is
not a being who can be represented to sense, nor figured in
the imagination. He is not divisible into parts, nor circum-
scribed by space. He exists as an unit, simple and indis-
cerptible, and therefore indestructible. It is clear that a
material being cannot be infinite, or if he could be infinite
it would destroy the possibility of all finite matter. Its
nature is to be bounded by figure, and to exclude every
other matter from the space which it occupies. As bounded,
it cannot be infinite : as exclusive, if it were infinite, it would
absolutely fill the immensity of space and preclude the co-
existence of finite portions.
There have been those M'ho have interpreted literally the
language of Scripture which predicates of God bodily mem-
bers and organs, and have conseqaently sunk Him to the
low condition of corporeal existence. This coarse anthro-
pomorphism or anthropopathism, as it has
Ancient and n i -i i i t^i •
been called, was attributed to the Jibion-
ites, to the monks of Egypt and to the sect of the Audians.
It has certainly been maintained, in modern times, by more
than one disciple of Socinus. It was the
ThiteT "°*'^''°P°"°'- doctrine of Vorstius ; the doctrine of Bid-
die in the Catechism, so conclusively re-
futed by Owen in the Vindicice Evangeliccc; the doctrine of
Hobbes ; and still more recently the doctrine of Priestly.
It is now abandoned by the Socinians, who have approxi-
mated more closely than their predecessors to the spiritual
Deism of philosophy.
1 ^n. vi., 726, 727.
Lect. VII.] SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. 177
Tertullian has been accused of attributing a body to God,
and so far as the letter of the accusation is
Tertullian defended. i i i • • i i • j.
concerned the charge is unquestionably just.
But by body he evidently means nothing more than substan-
tial existence — something permanent and abiding, and not
like a breath of air or a transitory vapour. In the same
sense he predicates a body of the human soul, but yet de-
scribes it in a manner which precludes the notion of mate-
rial composition.^ Indeed he tells us articulately^ what he
means by hochj. " Nothing can exist," says he, " but as
having something by which it exists. As the soul, however,
exists, it must needs have something by which it exists.
That something is its body. Everything is a body of its
own kind. Nothing is incorporeal which has real exist-
ence." Body is, therefore, nothing more nor less than the
indispensable condition of existence. It is the permanent
element amid the variable and changing, and it is material
or spiritual according to the nature of the object. A passage
quoted in Kitto's Cyclopcedia, under the title Anthropomor-
phism, will show how far this celebrated father was from
anything like a material conception of God. "Divine
affections," says he, "are ascribed to the Deity by means
of figures borrowed from the human form, not as if He
were indued with corporeal qualities. When eyes are
ascribed to Him, it denotes that He sees all things ; when
ears, that He hears all things ; the speech denotes His will ;
nostrils, the perception of prayer ; hands, creation ; arms,
power ; feet, immensity ; for He has no members and per-
forms no office for which they are required, but executes all
things by the sole act of His will. How can He require
eyes who is light itself ? or feet who is omnipresent ? How
can He require hands who is the silent Creator of all things ?
or a tongue to whom to think is to command ? Those mem-
bers are necessary to men, but not to God, inasmuch as the
counsels of men would be inefficacious unless their thoughts
^ See Burton's Bampton Lectures, note 59.
2 Ad Prax., c. 7.
Vol. I.— 12
178 SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. [Lect. YII.
put their members in motion ; but not to God, whose ope-
rations folloAV His will without effort."
Tlie Scriptures themselves sufficiently guard against the
perverse application of their bold metaphors in attributing
the organs of the human body to the supreme God, when
they articulately remind us that His arm is not an arm of
flesh, nor His eyes eyes of flesh, neither seeth He as man
seeth.^ The same wonder which in one place is ascribed to
the " finder of God " is attributed in another to the imme-
diate agency of the Holy Ghost ; cf Luke xi. 20 ; Matt,
xii. 28. To the candid reader there is no danger of being
misled by such representations. They are obvious con-
descensions to the infirmities of human
of£;^:S::: thought, and are designed to signify that
there are acts of God analogous to those
for which we employ these members. When he is said to
see or to hear, the meaning is that He knows with as abso-
lute a certainty as we can obtain by the evidence of the eye
or the ear. These organs are simply symbols of knowledge.
His arm and hand the symbols of power, and His bowels
the symbol of tender compassion.^ The exposition of Ter-
tullian quoted above is clear and satisfactory.
It is remarkable, too, that no organs are ascribed to God
similar to those by which we perform the mean and disrep-
utable functions of the body, and no offices which savour
of weakness or of imperfection. The intent of Scripture
could not be more nicely discriminated. " To eat and sleep
are never ascribed to Him, nor those parts that belong to
the preparing or transmitting nourishment to the several
parts of the body, as stomach, liver, veins nor bowels, under
that consideration, but as they are significant of compas-
sion. But only those parts are ascribed to Him whereby
we acquire knowledge, as eyes and ears, the organs of learn-
ing and wisdom ; or to communicate it to others, as the
the month, lips, tongue, as they are instruments of speak-
1 2 Cliron. xxxii. 8 ; Job x. 4. Cf. Owen, vol. viii., p. 154.
2 See Charnock, i., pp. 262, 263.
Lect. VII.] SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. 179
ing, not of tasting ; or those parts which signify strength
and power, or whereby we perform the actions of charity
for the relief of others. Taste and touch, senses that ex-
tend no farther than to corporeal things, and are the grossest
of all the senses, are never ascribed to Him." ^
The immateriality of God is clearly implied in all those
God immaterial, as ^xts which represent His glory as being
not to be figured by incapablc of being -figured by images. The
second commandment forbids the making
of any graven image, or the likeness of anytliing that is in
heaven above, or in the earth beneath, or in the waters
under the earth. Moses reminds the Israelites that they saw
no manner of similitude when the Lord spoke to them in
Horeb out of the midst of the fire ; and enjoins upon them
to take heed to themselves lest they should be seduced to
make them a graven image, the similitude of any figure.^
The Apostle Paul reminds the Athenians that the Godhead
is not like unto gold, or silver, or stone, graven by art and
man's device ; ^ and the Saviour Himself appeals to the Jcavs
that they had never heard the voice at any time, nor seen the
shape of God.*
In the twenty-fourth chapter of Exodus there occurs a
passage which, at the first view, seems to be inconsistent
with the general teaching of Scripture : " Then went up
Moses and Aaron, Nadab and Abihu, and seventy of the
elders of Israel ; and they saw the God of Israel ; and there
was under His feet as it were a paved work of a sapphire
stone, and as it were the body of heaven in its clearness."
(Vv. 9, 10.) Onkelos renders it the glory of the God of
Israel ; and when we remember that God is invisible in
Himself, dwelling in light which no creature can venture to
approach, there can be no doubt that the allusion is to some
brilliant symbol of the Divine presence, in keeping with the
majestic pediment upon which it stood. "The colour of
sapphire," says Calvin,^ " was presented to them to elevate
^ Charnock i., p. 263. ^ j)eut. iv. 15, seq. » Acts xvii. 29.
* John V. 37. 5 Harm. Pent., vol. iii., p. 323.
180 SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. [Lect, VII.
their minds by its brightness above the workl, and therefore
it is immedia:tely added that its appearance was as of the
clear and serene sky. By this symbol they were reminded
that the glory of God is above all heavens ; and since in His
very footstool there is such exquisite and surpassing beauty,
something still more sublime must be thought of Him-
self, and such as would ravish all our senses with admi-
ration."
The positive thing which is involved in the sjjirituality
Positively, the doc- ^f God is that Hc is a self-conscious sub-
trine ascribes to God jcct, a Pcrsou posscsscd of intelligence and
will. We can conceive an immaterial sub-
stance which is not a person — such as the vital principle in
brutes, and the plastic nature which the ancients invented as
the soul of the world. There may be a receptivity of im-
pressions, of sensations, of presentations, and even of repre-
sentations of the imagination in memory, without any dis-
tinct consciousness of self. The phenomena appear and dis-
appear like the images of a mirror, but there is no feeling
which collects them into a common centre, and reduces them
to unity as the varied experiences of a single, permanent,
abiding subject. The brute knows not itself; it only knows
its sensations. It can never say, 3Iy thought, my wish, my
desire. What we call its soul is never realized to it as an
unit ; it appears only as a series of phenomena. When Ave
have learned to discriminate between our fleeting and tran-
sitory modes of consciousness and that which successively
subsists in these modes, when we learn to distinguish be-
tween the thinker and his thoughts, then we come to the
knowledge of ourselves. The broad and impassable dis-
tinction between mind and matter, between a person and a
thing, is, that the one knows and knows that it knows, while
the other is only an object to be known. The one has a free
activity, the other moves only as it is moved. The one acts,
the other is acted upon. Perhaps the clearest realization of
self-hood is in the phenomena of will. It was the doctrine
Lect. VII.] SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. 181
of Locke and the Scotch philosophers that our own exist-
ence was not directly given in consciousness,
Locke. •^.*' '
but was a matter of inference and necessary
belief. All that we can directly know are the phenomena
of self — its thoughts, sensations, desires ; but not self, or the
thinking principle itself. This principle has been success-
fully combated by Sir William Hamilton
Hamilton and Mansel. i-»»- -»«- i n i i t
and Mr. Mansel, and the dualism of con-
sciousness brought out in a strong and clear light. Mr.
Mansel has pressed the phenomena of will as decisive of the
question. " If," says he,^ " in the mental state which cor-
responds to the judgment, I will, there is no consciousness
of /, but only of will, it is impossible to place the essential
feature of volition, as has been done above, in the conscious-
ness of myself having power over my own determinations. Will,
and not I, being the primary fact of consciousness, the
causative power of volition must be sought in the relation
between will and some subsequent phenomenon ; and so
sought, it will assuredly never be found. It cannot be found
where Locke sought it, in the relation between the deter-
mination of the will and the consequent motion of the limb ;
for the determination is not the immediate antecedent of the.
motion, but only of the intervening nervous and muscular
action. I cannot therefore be immediately conscious of my
power to move a limb when I am not immediately conscious
of my power to produce the antecedent phenomena. Nor
yet can the causative power be found where Maine de Biran
sought it, in the relation of the will to the action of the
nerves and muscles ; for this relation may at any time be
interrupted by purely physical causes, such as a stroke of
paralysis ; and in that case no exertion of the will can pro-
duce the desired effect. We can escape from this difficulty,
the stronghold of skepticism and necessitarianism, by one
path only, and that is by a more accurate analysis of the
purely mental state, which will discover an immediate con-
sciousness of power in myself, determining my own volitions.'^
^ Metaphys., p. 175.
182 SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. [Lect. VII.
Here, then, is an immediate revelation of myself, and of my-
self as a power — as a real, abiding, subsisting thing. So far
is it from being true that our knowledge of matter is su-
perior to our knowledge of mind, that it is precisely the re-
verse which holds. The reality of matter I can never seize
at all, but the reality of self is given in every act of con-
sciousness. It is the only reality, apart from phenomena,
that falls within the province of our faculties. It is the only
thing that we are entitled to denominate being, as contra-
distinguished from appearance. " Personality," says Man-
sel,^ " like all other simple and immediate presentations, is
indefinable ; but it is so because it is superior to definition.
It can be analyzed into no simpler elements, for it is itself
one element of a product which defies analysis. It can be
made no clearer by description or comparison, for it is re-
vealed to us in all the clearness of an original intuition, of
which description and comparison can furnish only faint and
partial resemblances." God is a Spirit. God is a Person.
This is the highest conception which our finite faculties can
frame of His nature ; it is the noblest tribute which we are
capable of paying to His being.
• In paying this tribute, let it be mentioned, as distinctly
implied in personality, that we separate God from every
other being besides. He is not the universe. He is not
law. He is not the result of material organization. He is
in Himself, by Himself, and for Himself. His existence is
pre-eminently and absolutely His own. Separateness of
being is as essential to ijersonality as sim-
Separateness of . . . i i- r*
being in opposition to plicity or uuity. It distinguishes and dii-
everyformofPanthe- fepences. Heiicc, cvcry form of Paiithcism
is inconsistent with the noblest idea which
we are able to frame of God. He affirms Himself in affirm-
ing that He is not the finite ; as we affirm ourselves, as sub-
jects, in affirming that Ave are not the objects of our know-
ledge. Self and not-self divide existence, and each excludes
the other.
1 Metaphys., p. 182.
Lect. VII.] SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. 183
Let us consider some of the elements that are contained
in the proposition that God is a Spirit.
1. In the first place, it is equivalent to saying that God
has life ; and as the infinite Spirit that He
As spiritual, God is i ^•^ ' tt* ij? tt • j_i i
necessary life, lias liie lu Hmiseli. He IS the source and
fountain of all life, and possesses in Him-
self, in perfect fullness, what He has distributed in various
portions to the creatures of His hands. Hence, He claims
it as His prerogative to be the only living as well as true
God. He only hath immortality in Himself; and the high-
est and most solemn guarantee of truth which even a Divine
oath can give is found in the immutability of the Divine
life. " As I live, saith the Lord," is the most awful adju-
ration which even God can make. We know not what life
is, in any of its forms, in its own essential nature. It is so
subtle that it escapes the knife of the anatomist, the tests of
the chemist and the skill of the physiologist. It is every-
where present in the animal frame, but nowhere to be seized
and detected apart from its phenomenal effects. We know
what it does, but we are wholly unable to explain what it is.
It is the badge of honour among the works of God — as they
increase in life, they rise in dignity and worth. It is the
excellence of man's life, as a spiritual, thinking being, that
constitutes man's glory in the domain of sublunary exist-
ence. " On earth there is nothing great but man ; in man
there is nothing great but mind." This
and activity. t p • t . .
life implies activity — a power of self-motion
and of self-determination. The grounds of its action, in
reference to God, are solely within Himself. He is not
moved or impelled from without ; the springs of His energy
are all within, in the fullness and depths of His own being.
He never rests, never slumbers, never grows weary, never
relaxes His activity. To live is His blessedness as well as
His glory. Ceaseless action is the very essence of His nature.
It is a badge of imperfection among us that our energies be-
come fatigued by exertion, and that we require intervals of
relaxation and repose. One half of our lives is lost in sleep ;
184 SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. [Lect. YII.
and even in our waking moments continued intensity of
thought has a tendency to consume the frame which carries
so active a tenant. The brighter the candle burns, the more
rapidly it wastes away. We sigh for the period when we
shall be clothed with our spiritual bodies, and introduced into
a world in which there is neither sleep nor night ; in which
exertion shall be uninterrupted and complete ; in which all
the powers of the soul shall be eternally and intensely ex-
ercised, but exercised in such just and beautiful proportions
that the rapture shall become sobriety and the excitement a
calm. Yet even in its purest and most exalted state our
activity is limited and derived. It is and ever must be de-
pendent on conditions. But the activity, the life of God
is without restriction or defect. Self-originated and self-
sustained, it is equal to itself from everlasting to everlasting.
" My Father worketh hitherto, and I work." Could God
jjause in the ceaseless flow of His energies, the heavens must
cease to roll and the earth to move ; rivers cease to flow and
the ocean to receive them ; the general pulse of life would
cease to beat, and the awful silence of death pervade the
universe. It is as God lives that all else live besides.
They live and move and have their being in Him. The
pledge of universal safety is that He never slumbers nor
sleeps. How different is such a God from the indolent idol
of Epicurean philosophy ! How different the happiness
which flows from the fullness and energy of unimpeded ex-
ercise from the voluptuous repose which possesses attractions
only for ignoble natures ! It is true that man's sin has
added pain to labor and converted work into toil. But in
itself, the highest and freest activity is the highest bliss;
and God is infinitely blessed only as He is infinitely active.
2. But in the next place, the activity of God is not mere
motion or agitation. It is the highest and
thought Ind^Si.''"^ noblest of all activity--the activity of
thought and will. He is to Himself an
inexhaustible fountain of knowledge and action. He is
not a blind principle operating by a stern necessity, uncon-
Lect. VIL] SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. 185
sclous of the laws which determine and regulate His move-
ments. He is no remorseless fate, no soul of the world, no
abstract substance without definite qualities and attributes.
He knows what He does, and does it because He knows it
to be right and wise. He is the master of Himself. His
will is absolutely and unchangeably free, and in its free-
dom is never divorced from wisdom and justice. He is no
necessary cause, but He creates only because he chooses to
create. He dispenses His gifts according to His own sove-
reign pleasure. He rules in the armies of heaven and
among the inhabitants of earth, and none can stay His
hand or say unto Him, What doest Thou? He worketh
all things according to the counsel of His own will. It is
in this Being of knowledge and liberty, this Being of pure
sjDiritual life, that we recognize the God who made the
heavens and the earth, and in whom we live and move
and have our being, and whom we are bound to worship
with our whole souls. This is the God whose right it is to
reign, for He is worthy. What energy can be compared
with intelligence ? What Being so exalted as He who can
say, "1 know and I will"? These simple monosyllables
bridge a boundless chasm in the order of existence. And
how glorious must He be who stands at the head of this
order, and concentrates within Himself all the resources of
wisdom and knowledge and goodness — who gathers into the
burning focus of His own being every ray of intellectual
and moral beauty that is anywhere reflected in the bound-
less universe ! How glorious is God, who is all knowledge
and all will, whose very life is to know and will, with whom
to be and to know are synonymous ! One soul is greater
than a whole universe of matter. AVhat, then, must God be
who is an infinite Spirit !
3. In the third place, we may see the sense in which we
are to understand the unity and simplicity
The nature of God's /»/^l t j_1'j.'' '^ i-i
unity and simplicity. ^^ ^od. I mcau the intmisic unity which
pertains to His essence, and not the rela-
tive unity which excludes more than one such being. The
186 SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. [Lect. VII.
unity and simplicity are certainly the unity and simplicity
of spirit — an unity which is attested in every act of con-
sciousness. The human soul is one ; it cannot be resolved
into parts ; it cannot be divided, so that a portion shall be
here and a portion there. It always exists and acts in its
totality. The / is the very perfection of simplicity. But
when theologians go farther, and from abstract speculations
on the infinite preclude every species of distinction in the
modes of its existence, they are warranted by no finite an-
alogies, and transcend accordingly the limits of human
thought. What they say may be true, but they have no
means of verifying their assertion. The relative unity or
onliness of God precludes genera and species. His intrinsic
unity precludes separable accidents, but what warrant is
there for precluding the distinction of substance and attri-
bute, or precluding distinctions among the attributes them-
selves? The thing may be just and proper, but we can
never prove it to be so, and the only unity accordingly which
we are authorized to attribute to God is an unity analogous
to that of the human soul.
4. In the fourth place, because God is a Sjsirit, He can
Because spiritual, ^uter ^ iuto commuuiou with our spirits.
God can commune This is oue of the most mystcrious attri-
with our spirits. , r« • i i i i • i •
butes ot mnid — the power by which it can
impart to others the knowledge of what passes within itself.
It is this jieculiarity which lies at the foundation of the
possibility of society. If each soul existed only as an in-
dividual, and there was no medium by Avhich its thoughts
and feelings and affections could be communicated to other
souls, there might be contiguity in space, but there could be
no such moral unions among men as those which are pre-
sented in the Family, the Church and the State. Intense
individualism would be the law of all human life. We are
so familiar with the interchange of thoughts and feelings,
that we have ceased to marvel at the mystery it involves.
But it is a mystery notwithstanding, and a mystery Avhich,
while all must accept it as a fact, no human philosophy
Lect. VII.] SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. 187
can explain. Mind does hold commerce with mind. The
thoughts of one man can be transferred to another — the con-
sciousness of one man can to some extent be laid bare to
another. And so God can communicate with His intelli-
gent creatures. He can make known to them His attitude
in relation to them. He can enter into their souls, and
warm and irradiate them with the tokens of His favour, or
depress and alarm them with the sense of His displeasure.
It is His spirituality which enables Him to be communica-
tive, and which consequently enables Him to become the
jiortion of their souls. Apart from this He could not be
the supreme and satisfying good. Hence His spirituality
lies at the foundation of all true religion. Take that away,
and there is and can be no symjsathy betwixt the worshipper
and the worshipped. There may be contiguity and impact,
but there can be no union, no communion. Each would
still be a stranger to the other.
5. This subject reveals to us the real folly and danger of
Because Bpirituai, idolatry. By idolatry I here mean any
God cannot be repre- attempt to represent God by images, whe-
sented by images. i i • inn
ther those images are regarded really as
God, or only as symbols of His presence. The two things
are substantially the same. To worship the image, and to
worship God in and by the image, produce similar effects
upon the mind of the worshipper. His thoughts in either
case are regulated and determined by the object before Him.
Now every image is a falsehood in two
The idol, a twofold , t l^ n , ^ • ,
ijg respects. In the lirst place, it represents
the living by the dead. That which has
life in itself, whose essence it is to live, is figured by that
whose nature is essentially inert. There is no point of re-
semblance betwixt mind and matter. They exist only as
contrasts. Hence the image must be a doctrine of false-
hood ; it must lead the mind into wrong trains of thought
in reference to the nature of God ; it must degrade Him to
some of the conditions of matter.
In the next place, the image is a falsehood, inasmuch as it
188 SPIRITUALITY OF GOD. [Lect. VII.
represents a free activity by that which is the victim of a
stern necessity. God, as self-moved, cannot be symbolized
by any object whose law is to move only as it is moved.
Mechanical necessity can never figure freedom of will, and
yet this is the very core of the Divine Personality. It is
that which makes God the object of our worship.
These two fundamental errors must prove fatal in the
moral education of the worshipper. It is impossible to
think by the image and yet think in accordance with the
truth. A mechanical religion is the only w^orship that can
spring from idolatry. Hence it is that the Divine law
guards so sacredly the purity of Divine worship. To admit
images is to necessitate the moral degradation of God ; and
to degrade God is, inevitably, in the final reaction, to de-
grade ourselves. From the nature of the case, idolatry must
wax worse and worse as its fundamental falsehoods acquire a
stronger hold upon the mind. The only remedy is to pre-
vent the beginnings of the evil, and that is done in the stern
decree of the second commandment. A spiritual God can
only be worshipped in spirit and in truth. A free Personal
God can only be worshipped with a free personal will.
LECTURE VIII.
THE INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD.
TTAVING discussed the spirituality, and in a general
-■— '- way the personality, of God, the next thing in order
would be the peculiar mode of the Divine Personality in the
doctrine of the Trinity. But as that is an extensive topic,
and its introduction here would break the continuity of the
discourse in relation to the attributes, we propose to postpone
it until the subject of the attributes has been completed.
The topic, accordingly, which is now to engage our attention
is that division of the attributes which is commonly called
incommunicable, and which we have seen
Universal and all- . i in t i x
pervajing attributes, ^rc uuiversal and all-pervadmg, character-
izing alike the whole being and every per-
fection of God. They are special aspects of the absolute and
infinite — or rather applications of the general notion of the
infinite to special aspects in which God may be considered.
Contemplated with reference to the grounds of His being,
the infinite gives rise to the notion of independence or self-
existence ; with reference to the duration of His being, to
eternity ; with reference to the extent of His being, to im-
mensity ; with reference to the contents of His being, to all-
sufficiency ; with reference to the identity of His being, to
immutability. Independence, eternity, immensity, all-suf-
ficiency and immutability are therefore the forms under
which we recognize the distinctions which separate God by
an impassable chasm from every work of His hands. These
are the badges of Divinity — that glory which He will not
and cannot give to another. Without these, He would only
189
190 INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lect. VIIL
be a man or an angel on a larger scale. These, too, consti-
tute the veil which hangs over the mystery of His being — a
veil which, according to the inscription upon the temple of
Isis, no mortal will ever be able to remove. We can only
stand afar oif and gaze at the ineffable glory. We can adore
where we cannot understand. Let us treat of them in order ;
and first of Independence.
I. Independence, self-existence, necessary existence, ab-
solute being, are only so many different
Independence. .
modes of expressing one and the same
thing, and that thing is the negation of a cause. God has
never begun to be. His existence is dependent upon no
species of cause, either that of a superior will, or that resulting
from the union and combination of elements, which may
again be separated and reduce Him to nothing. He is be-
cause He is. " I am that I am." We can go no farther in
explaining the grounds of His being. The understanding is
paralyzed, but faith is not staggered. If there be caused
The mystery of ^^iug, there uiust bc uucauscd being ; and
caused and uncaused jf t^q are disposed to sliriuk from the mys-
tery of uncaused being, let us reflect again
and see whether caused being is any more easily comjire-
hended. Can we solve the mystery of power ? Can we ex-
plain how that which was nothing ever began to be ? Is
not creation as dark and inscrutable as underived existence ?
Do not the very limits of our faculties warn us of a world
beyond which those faculties were never designed to pene-
trate, save with the torch of faith ? The fact of creation,
the fact of a creator, we can easily grasp ; but how the one
came to be, and the other always was, is beyond our compass.
We have enough to regulate our worship, but not enough to
satisfy curiosity.
There are modes of expression in relation to tlie independ-
ence of God which, however they may be
Some modes of ex- ' j^' n i ^ ±^ j. f l j.
pression criticise 1. Justified by the poverty of language, are yet
liable to gross perversion and abuse. He
is said to be the ground of His own existence in a way which
Lect. VIII.] INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. 191
seems to imply that He is His own proper cause. Now
self-existence should never be taken in a positive, but a
negative sense. No being can originate itself. The very
notion is self-contradictory — for it involves existence and
non-existence at the same time. All that is meant is the
denial to the being of any origin at all. It has no cause,
nothing anterior or superior on which it depends. Necessity
is also sometimes represented as a ground of the Divine
existence, in such a way as to imply that it is a real, pro-
ductive cause, or at least a something prior in the order of
thouo-ht to the being; of God. Dr. Clarke is not free from
censure in this respect. He certainly treats necessity as
something closely akin to a cause, and deduces inferences
from it as if it were a positive principle which we were
able to apprehend. But necessity, like existence, is only
negative in its application to God. It expresses the fact
that, the finite being given, we cannot but think the existence
of the infinite. To us, that existence is necessary as the ex-
planation of what is caused and dependent. The necessity,
however, only involves again the denial of a cause. It is
simply the declaration that there must be an unoriginated
cause.
The independence of God is contained in every argument
Independence in- ^^^ich prOVCS His being. To dcuy it is,
voived in the very be- therefore, to deny the existence of any
°° ' God at all. If all is dependent, all is
finite, all is made, and yet there is nothing to depend upon
and nothing to make. We shall have an universe of crea-
tures and no creator — a chain of a limited number of links,
with nothing to hang on at the top and nothing to lean on
at the bottom ; or if the series be considered as infinite, we
shall have the contradiction of a whole which has no begin-
ning made up of parts each of which began. The first
aspect under which God appears to us in the field of specu-
lation is as the underived and independent. The mind
seeks an extra-mundane cause. It wants something to sup-
port the finite, and it never rests until the infinite is re-
192 INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lect. VIII.
vealed to its faitli. The Scrij)tures, too,
and everywhere pre- i , i • i i
BuppoHcdiu Scripture, eveijwhere presuppose the independence
of God. It is implied in His name Jeho-
vah, in His being the Creator of the heavens and the earth,
the first and last, the beginning and the end of all things.
A point so plain it were superfluous to establish by the
citation of jDassages.
It must not be forgotten that this independence pervades
every determinate perfection of God as well
Pervades every de- tt* i • tt • • i i i • ^
terminate perfection. «« ^^^^ beuig. Hc IS mdcpcndent lu know-
ledge ; He derives nothing from without ;
He has no teachers ; and He has nothing to learn. If in any
respect He were ignorant, in that respect He would be de-
pendent for His knowledge. He has no partners in coun-
sel ; His wisdom is as original as His nature ; and His power
is free from all limitations and conditions. He does what
He will among the armies of heaven and the inhabitants of
earth, and none can stay His hand or say unto Him, What
doest Thou? So, also. His righteousness, holiness, good-
ness and truth are as absolute as His nature. On the same
ground that He is at all, He is what He is.
II. Contemj)lated with reference to the duration of His
beino;, God is said to be eternal. His
Eternity. ■ . -, n -i ^ -r, ^ • i i
eternity is denned by iJoethius to be the
possession, at once total and perfect, of an interminable life.
It is represented by the Schoolmen as a stationary point — a
permanent and unchanging now, so as to exclude the notions
of succession and change. These are abor-
definru." '''°'*' '° tive efforts to realize in thought what trans-
cends the conditions of our consciousness.
We are subject to the law of time, and can think nothing
apart from the relation of time. A duration which is not
time is as completely beyond our conceptions as a place
which is not space. Even in regard to time we can think
it only " as an indefinite past, present or future." We can-
not represent it as absolutely beginning, for that would sup-
pose a consciousness within and out of time at the same
Lect. VIII]. INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. 193
moment ; and for tlie same reason we cannot suppose it as
absolutely ending. We cannot think the indivisible mo-
ment, the point which separates the past from the future ;
it is always gone before we can seize it. Eternity has been
divided into eternity a 'parte ante and a 2:)arte post, but the
division evidently involves a contradiction — the contradic-
tion of an eternity begun and an eternity concluded. We
are therefore obliged to maintain that time is not the same
as eternity ; and, inconceivable as the thing is, we are obliged
to affirm that eternity admits of no succession of parts. It
has no past, present or future. We are obliged to come to
the conclusion of Boethius and the Schoolmen, and yet when
we have reached that conclusion what is it that we positively
know ? Nothing but the fact that God in the mode of His
existence transcends time. We only deny to His conscious-
ness and to His being the limitations of
Our conceptions all T> j. l j. j. '^ • • -j^ li^
negative, ^^^ O'wn. But what ctcrmty is in itself
we are as ignorant of as we were before.
We deny to God beginning of life or end of days ; we deny
to Him succession of thought or change of state ; we deny
to Him the possibility of age or decay ; He is neither young
nor old. Beyond these negations we cannot go, but these
negations impress us with the conviction
yet Imply transcend- r» . i , n mr ,
ent excellence. ^i transcendciit exccllence. ihey assert
an absolute immortality which surpasses
all power of imagination or of thought. Time with its
remorseless tooth destroys everything around us ; kingdoms
rise and fall ; generation succeeds generation to the regions
of the dead ; trees wither and fade and perish -, the moun-
tain falling Cometh to naught ; Nature herself waxes old and
is ready to vanish away, but the Eternal God remains fixed
in His being, the same yesterday, to-day and for ever. His
years fail not. He is always the great " I Am." Eternity
is a mystery, but it is a mystery which shrouds and covers
unspeakable glory. How delightful to think in the midst
of universal change and desolation, that there is one Being
who liveth and abideth for ever — one Being who, when the
Vol. I.— 13
194 INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lect. VIII.
heavens shall be rolled up as a vesture, the sun blotted out,
and the moon and stars bereft of their brightness, can lift
His awful hand and swear by Himself, " Behold, I live for
ever !" Before the earth was, or the stars of the morning
sang together, or the sons of God shouted for joy, Jehovah
was. Were all the creatures annihilated by a single blow,
and the void of nothing to take the place which is now
filled by a teeming and a joyous universe, Jehovah would
still be. Above and beyond time and all its phenomena,
He is untouched by its changes and disasters. Eternity is
His dwelling-place, and " I Am" is His name.
III. Contemplated in reference to the extent of His be-
ing, God is said to be immense. This ex-
Immeiisity, t • i •
presses His relation to space, as eternity
expresses His relation to time. It implies that God in the
fullness of His essence is present to every point of space
in every point of time. Omnipresence is
flistineuished from tt- • •, • ^ t • ij* i-
omnipresence. ^^^ immensity coiisidcrcd m reiation to
His creatures. It is His presence to them ;
but as the created universe is limited. His presence, if He be
infinite, must extend infinitely beyond it. He is where the
creatures are, but He is also where creatures never are,
never have, been and never Avill be. But the immensity
of a simple essence is as incomprehensible as eternity. We
cannot conceive of infinite space, much less can we conceive
of an inextended substance, pervading every portion of this
boundless field in the entire plenitude of His being.
How spirits are related to space at all it is impossible to
say. They are not circumscribed by it
Relation of spirits ti i i ,i i , r-n •.
to space. hke body; they do not occupy or fall it;
and yet they are so restricted to it in their
energies and operations that we can properly say they are
here and not there. They have a presence of some kind, as
the soul is present in the body and the angels present in
prescribed spheres, necessitating locomotion in enlarging the
area of their working.
As God's immensity precludes all extension, so it pre-
Lect. VIII.] INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OP GOD. 195
eludes all mixture with other objects that exist in sj)ace.
Mixture with other ^^^ ^^^^^ being excludes another from the
objects in space, pre- same place. Two souls never exist in the
same body, and two angels have not the
same presence to any given locality. But God pervades
every other being without mixture or confusion. He is
as intimately present to our own souls as our own con-
sciousness. He knows every thought, He perceives every
desire ; there is not a word in our tongue, but lo ! He know-
eth it altogether. The whole universe stands naked and
bare to His inspection. And yet He is as perfectly distinct
from the universe and from every object in it as if He
dwelt in distant and inaccessible regions. One finite being
is not so completely diverse from another as God from every
creature that He has made. He is separated from the finite
by a chasm as boundless as His immensity.
Some have resolved the universal presence of God into
Not the mere vir- ^^^ virtual prcscncc of His power — mean-
tuai presence of His ing nothing morc than that He is capable
of producing effeists beyond His own im-
mediate locality, and that the symbols and means of His
authority are everywhere diffused, as a king may be said in
a modified sense to be present in every part of his domin-
ions. But such a presence is constructive, and to attri-
bute only such a presence to God is to deny His infinity.
If His essence sustains not the same relation to all space —
if there is a region, no matter how large, to which it is re-
stricted in its actual being — then God becomes finite and de-
pendent. The region beyond is aloof from Him, and He
can only act on it through instruments and means.
The Scriptures are abundant in their references to this
amazing perfection of God. " Whither,"
^^^OTpture testimony ^^^^^ ^j^^ Psalmist,^ " sliall I go from Thy
Spirit? or whither shall I flee from Thy
presence ? If I ascend up into heaven, Thqu art there ; if
I make my bed in hell, behold, Thou art there ! If I take
1 Ps. cxxxix. 7-10.
196 INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lect. YIII.
the wings of the morning and dwell in the uttermost parts
of the sea, even there shall Thy hand lead me, and Thy
right hand shall hold me." " Behold, the heaven of heavens,"
says Solomon,^ " cannot contain Thee." " Am I a God at
hand, saith the Lord, and not a God afar off? Can any
hide himself in secret places that I shall not see him ? saith
the Lord. Do not I fill heaven and earth ? saith the Lord." ^
It were useless to multiply passages. This is one of the
points in which the Sacred Scriptures show their immense
superiority to all the devices of human wisdom and policy.
The gods of the heathen were all local deities. They were
circumscribed in space, and subject to the conditions of time
and matter. It was reserved for a rude people, just escaping
from bondage and degradation, to reveal a sublimer theology
than the Porch, Academy or Lyceum ever dreamed of. A
spiritual, eternal, omnipresent, infinite God is the pervading
doctrine of a race, unskilled in letters and
and provea the Bible , , i , i • , j •
to be not of man. coustautly prouc to rclapsc mto supersti-
tion. How clear the proof that the Bible
is no contrivance of man !
It may be well to remark that, besides the essential pres-
„ . , . ence, the Scriptures sometimes speak of a
Special sense in ' 1 i
which God is said to prcscuce wliicli cousists in peculiar mani-
festations of the Divine favour or anger.
In the first sense God was present in the Jewish temple.
He there manifested His mercy and grace to the j^eople. It
was there He showed Himself pleased with their worship,
and answered the prayers and intercessions they made to
Him. In this sense, too, He is present in heaven. He
there communicates to saints and angels the richest tokens
of His love. They have free and undisturbed communion
with Him as the Father of their spirits. In the second
sense He is present in hell. He there reveals the tokens
of His justice. The impenitent and devils are made to feel
the Avcight of His displeasure against sin. And so God is
said to withdraw Himself and to hide His face ; not that
1 1 Kings viii. 27. ^ Jer. xxiii. 23, 24.
Lect. VIII.] INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. 197
His essential presence is diminished, but the marks of His
favour are withheld. He ceases to show Himself proj)itious.
The immensity, like the eternity of God, transcends all
finite conception, but as a regulative fact it
Practical uses of the ' i* ,i , , • . mii -j
doctrine. IS of the utuiost nnportancc. io the samt
it is full of comfort. He can never be re-
moved beyond the reach of his Redeemer and his Friend.
Go where he may, he is still surrounded with God, who
compasses him before and behind, and lays His hand upon
him. He knows our hearts infinitely better than we know
them ourselves. Those desires which we cannot utter, and
those penitent distresses which can only reveal themselves in
tears and groans, He thoroughly comprehends. Our whole
hearts are before Him in the nakedness of a perfect, infallible
intuition. He understands our wants, appreciates our weak-
ness and can accommodate His grace precisely to our case.
Men may misconstrue us ; they may impugn our motives,
traduce our characters and assail us with unjust reproaches;
how delightful the truth that there is One who knows us,
and who will bring forth our righteousness as the light, and
our judgment as the noonday ! What a rebuke, too, is this
truth to every species of hypocrisy ! How idle to think of
concealment from Him to whom the night is even as the
day, darkness as transparent as light ! And what a check
should it be to wickedness that we are ever with God — that
there is no darkness or shadow of death whither we can
escape from His presence. He pursues us more closely than
our own shadows in the sun. He is with us in the very
depths of our soul, in the most secret recesses of our con-
sciousness. Awake or asleep, at home or abroad, in sickness
or in health, by land or sea, we are still with God. Such
knowledge is too wonderful for us ; it is high, we cannot at-
tain unto it. Hence, too, under the Gospel, prayer can be
made everywhere, for everywhere the ears of the Eternal
are open. It is no longer at Jerusalem, nor yet at Gerizim ;
but in every spot of earth trodden by the foot of man true
worship may be offered, if offered in the name of Christ.
198 INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lect. VIII.
The whole earth has become a temjDle, and every place a
place for prayer.
IV. We come next to the all-sufficiency of God, which is
the infinite and absolute considered with ref-
AU-sufficiency. /. i -i-v* • -r» •
erence to the contents oi the Uivine ±>eing.
It means that God contains within Himself the fullness of
perfection and blessedness — that nothing can be taken from
Him and nothing added to Him. He is His own satisfying
portion, and the end and portion of all His
tuSortreLnlyelr" intelligent creatures. He can never want ;
he can never be subject to unsatisfied de-
sire ; he can never be disturbed by care or solicitude. He is
the jDcrfect good. All the perfections of all the creatures
are in Him, formally, eminently or virtually. Let me ex-
plain these terms. Perfections, according
Scholastic terms ex- ■.icill T'lJ'xx
pij^ijjgjj to the bchoohnen, were divided into two
classes, those that were absolutely simple —
shnplidter simpUces — and those that were only relative per-
fections, or perfections secundum quid, called also mixed.
An absolute jjerfection had no imperfection in it, and is bet-
ter than its opposite, or than any other thing with which it
is incompatible in the same subject. These perfections in
their own formal and essential nature, abstracted from the
conditions under which they manifest themselves in us, are
predicated of God, and are therefore said to be formcdiy in
Him. Mixed perfections have an element of imperfection
in them ; they are only relative to certain kinds of things,
and are called perfections because these things admit nothing
higher and better. They would cease to be what they are
if adorned with higher and better. Human reason, human
will, human intelligence are relative perfections, but they
are mixed with limitation and defect. The properties of
gold with reference to that metal are perfections, but they
are not simply better than other qualities with which in gold
they cannot co-exist. Now those perfections which are im-
perfect by limitation and defect are predicated of God in
the way of eminence — that is, they exist in Him in a higher
Lect. yill.J INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. 199
degree and more eminent degree. Perfections which are
purely relative, purely secundum quid, neither formally nor
eminently exist in God ; they are only in Him as in His
230wer to produce them, and are therefore said to be vir-
tually in Him.^ In this way God is made to contain the
23lenitude of the universe. His being is absolutely ex-
haustless in its contents, sufficient for Himself and sufficient
for all the creatures.
Here, too, is a truth too mighty for the grasp of our in-
tellects, and yet of the utmost consequence
Value of this truth. ' . . , „ „ , , t- •
as a regulative principle of faith. It is
this infinite fullness of God that makes Him the end and
felicity of the creature. Poor in ourselves, Avithout strength,
without resources, feeble as a reed, and easily crushed before
the moth, we are yet rich and valiant and mighty in God.
We have treasures which can never be consumed, resources
which can never be exhausted, and strength which can never
fail. With the everlasting God as our refuge we can bid
defiance to the universe besides. Though the earth be re-
moved and though the mountains be carried into the midst
of the sea, though the waters thereof roar and be troubled,
though the mountains shake with the swelling thereof, yet
we need not fear. Nothing can be lost so long as God re-
mains our friend. He is all in all.
V. We come now to consider the infinite and absolute
Avith reference to the permanent identity
Immutability. p /-* -ii y • ni-
or God s being, and this gives rise to the
notion of immutability. Immutability is indeed pnly an-
other form of asserting the simplicity and oneness of the
infinite. That which never began and can never end, to
which nothing can be added and from which nothing can be
taken, which knows na succession and is dependent upon
nothing without, is evidently incapable of change. Change
implies succession, and is possible only to a being conditioned
by time ; change implies causation, and is possible only to a
being limited and dependent ; change implies addition or
^ Cf. Perrone, also De Moor, c. iv., § 18.
200 INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lect. YIII.
subtraction, and is possible only to the defective or super-
fluous. The complete, the perfect, is beyond its reach.
Change is either from better to worse or from worse to bet-
ter, and is grossly incompatible with the notion of the infi-
nite, which contains the absolute fullness of perfection. This
truth, self-evident in itself, if the notion
Self-evident, yet also i» j.1. • £ -x l_ xi x* t i
Bet forth in Scriptme. «! ^^le mfinitc has cveu the negative valid-
ity which must certainly be assigned to it,
is abundantly proclaimed in Scripture : " For I am the
Lord ; I change not ; therefore ye sons of Jacob are not
consumed."^ "Of old hast Thou laid the foundation of
tlie earth, and the heavens are the work of Thy hands.
They shall perish, but Thou shalt endure ; yea, all of them
shall wax old like a garment, as a vesture shalt Thou change
them, and they shall be changed ; but Thou art the same,
and Thy years shall have no end."^ "God is not a man
that He should lie, neither the son of man that He should
repent ; hath He said, and shall He not do it, or hath He
spoken, and shall He not make it good"?^ "Every good
gift and every perfect gift is from above, and cometh down
from the Father of lights, with whom is no variableness,
neither shadow of turning." * " Jesus Christ, the same yes-
terday, and to-day, and for ever." * " The counsel of the
Lord standeth for ever ; the thoughts of His heart to all
generations." ^
The absolute immutability of God seems to be contradicted
by the fict of creation. A new relation was
.£:il^:T certainly superinduced._ The answer com-
monly given is : Relations ad extra imply
no change in the essence related ; God acquires a new de-
nomination, but no new accession to His being ; the title
Creator imports no addition to His nature ; the only real
change in the case takes place in the creatures which pass
from nonentity to being. But the question is, whether there
is not a modification of the Divine will in passing from non-
1 Mai. iii. 6. « Ps. cii. 25, 26. ^ Num. xxiii. 19.
* James i. 17. * Heb. xiii. 8. ^ Ps. xxxiii. 11.
LECT..VIII.] INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. 201
creation to creation. The universe began, and wlien it began
by the fiat of the Almighty, was not His will diiferently
determined from what it was before ? This difficulty we
conceive it impossible to answer. To say that He willed
from eternity to create just when He did — that the purpose
included the time and mode of its execution — does not solve
the problem. A will to create and a will creating do not
seem to be the same. It is true that the universe adds no-
thing to God and takes nothing from Him ; but does not
This question not to ^^c crcatiou of the universe imply a new de-
be solved, by reason of termination of His will ? This is one of
our ignorance. , . i • i • i
the questions which remind us of our igno-
rance whenever we undertake to speculate on the absolute.
"VVe shall meet it again when we come to the doctrine of
creation. In the mean time, let us be content to acknowledge
that our j^owers are not commensurate with the domain of
truth.
It has also been contended that the Divine essence was
The Divine essence modified by the incarnation of the Son.
not modified by the But tlic iucamation was only a new mani-
Incarnation, . n r^ -i -r itti.
testation ot (jrocl. It added nothing to the
essence of the Logos, into Personal union with whom the
humanity was apprehended.
The changes which take place in the universe are no
proof of the mutability of God, for to will
thlunivers^ ''°^*'^'° cliaiiges, and to change the will, are, as
Turrettin^ very justly remarks, very dif-
ferent things.
Those passages of Scripture which represent God as
changing His mind or purpose, as repenting
Scriptures wliich as- -i ... -■ . . , , ,
cribe change to God. aucl regretting and grieving, are all to be
interpreted as other anthropomorphisms.
They express no change in God, but a change in the events
of His providence — a change analogous to tliat which would
be produced in us under the influence of these feelings.
They are condescensions of the Divine Teacher to our narrow
1 Loc. iii., Qu. 11, § 7.
202 . INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lect. VIII.
capacities ; and as they are so thoroughly guarded from
abuse, they are admirably adapted to give vivacity and em-
phasis to the real idea they are intended to convey. It is
indeed one of the marks of the divinity of Scripture that it
can thus venture to clothe God in the forms of earth without
depressing His majesty or marring His glory. No human
author could have ventured on such a style without incurring
the certain risk of degrading the Almighty.
I need not add that the immutability of God is the foun-
dation of all our hopes. It is here that the
ourTrpt^s'""" °' "^^ heirs of the promise have strong consola-
tion. He can never deceive us in the ex-
pectations which He excites. He never falls short of, but
often goes immeasurably beyond, what He had led us to ex-
pect. Here is the pledge of His faithfulness, — He can never
change ; His counsel shall stand, and He will do all His
pleasure. The impenitent, too, may be assured that, with-
out a change in them, the threatenings of
His M^ord will be infallibly executed. He
will by no means clear the guilty. He can never be induced
to countenance or to tolerate sin. All efforts to secure His
favour Avhile we cling to our lusts are only insults to His
character, which represent Him as capable of being soothed
by flattery or bribed by rewards. It is the misery of sin
that it makes God altogether such an one as we ourselves.
It forgets His glory, and changes it into a lie.
It is delightful, too, to think that the immutability of God
is the immutability of wisdom and goodness
."dneilandTr^ and truth. It is no blind fate utterly re-
gardless of all moral distinctions. It is
rectitude itself ever abiding one and the same, and rendering
to all according to their dues. Injustice can never enter the
government of such a God. All will at length prove well.
I have now briefly and rapidly surveyed those attributes
which characterize God as the Infinite and Absolute. I
have contemplated Him in relation to the grounds, the du-
ration, the extent, the contents and the identity of His being.
Lect. YIII.] INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. 203
and have reached results which we are constrained to accept
as facts, but which we are wholly incompetent to explain.
These are the attributes which distinguish God ; it is these
which render every other perfection Divine. To deny any
one of them is to deny all, and to reduce existence to the
limited and contingent.
I cannot close without pointing out the immeasurable dis-
parity which this subject reveals between
Go^Td the creaTum ^lic uiost cxaltcd crcaturc in the universe
and its infinite creator. The tallest angel
has only a derived existence — it is absolutely dependent upon
the will of God. It sprang from a cause, and subsists only
in its cause. There was a time when it was not ; it could
again cease to be if God should so decree. Whatever in-
crease it has made in knowledge, power or excellence, it is
no nearer to independence to-day than when the light of con-
sciousness was first kindled within it. But how different
with God ! He leans u2)on nothing. He lives no borroAved
life. He asks no leave to be. He is because He is. His
throne is stable as eternity. His being immovable as des-
tiny. Strike out all the creatures, and He still is — glorious,
holy, majestic and blessed as when the morning stars sang
together and the sons of God shouted for joy. The universe
has added nothing to His bliss and can subtract nothing from
His fullness. Think, too, of an underived knowledge — a
knowledge which was never acquired ; which came from no
impressions from without ; which admits of no reasoning, of
no memory, of no succession of ideas ! Whence came this
knowledge? Thought reels and staggers at the problem,
and can only answer that it is like His being, independent
and original ; He knows because He knows. Think, again,
of its extent — all beings, all possible things, all the vicissi-
tudes of all the histories of all worlds — the whole universe,
with all its events from the first dawn of creation through
the endless cycle of ages, — all this present to His infinite
consciousness with an intuition easier and simpler than the
simplest perception of sight. The ages are but an instant.
204 INCOMMUNICABLE ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. [Lect. VIII.
and creation but a point. How little are we compared with
such a God ! Think, too, of an underived power — a power
to which there is nothing difficult ; to which it is as easy to
create a world as to move a feather, to uphold all things as
to speak a word. The universe lies in His hands as nothing ;
the nations are the small dust of the balance. He taketh up
the isles as a very little thing. He speaks and it is done.
He commands and it stands fast. What is man, what is an
angel, what is a seraph, compared to a being like this ?
In the next place, let us consider the disparity in the du-
ration of His existence. We are of yesterday, and know
nothing ; our age is but a span, our days but a hand-breadth.
We come forth in the morning, disappear in the evening,
and straight are seen no more. But from everlastino; to
everlasting the God that made us abides the same. Before
time began He was ; and when time shall cease He will
still be. Nothing can touch His being, for Eternity is His
dwelling-place. The earth has existed for ages which defy
all calculation ; it has witnessed stupendous changes ; it is
destined to witness more ; yet there was a time when there
was no earth, no sun, no moon, no stars, no angel, no man.
But there never was a time when there was no God. We
pass from infancy to age ; we add month to month and year
to year. But God has no age. He is no older now than
millions and billions of years before time began to roll. In
undecaying vigour He ever and ever abides. What a being
is God !
Think, besides, of His immensity. Here we are confined
to a spot of earth. Our being is limited to a narrow sphere.
We cannot stretch ourselves to the regions beyond. We are
fixed to our places. But where is the place of God "? Where
are the limits that circumscribe His being ? Where is the
point of space that eludes the scrutiny of His eye ? Go to
the eternal snows of the north, the burning deserts of the
tropics ; climb from world to world and from sun to sun ; or
sink even to the deep vault of hell — everywhere you shall
meet God. It is His hand that sustains the mountains. His
Lect. yiii.] incommunicable attributes of god. 205
breath that scorches the desert, and His arm that upholds
the worlds. Surely we may ask with the Psalmist, What
is man that Thou art mindful of him, or the son of man that
Thou visitest him ? We are indeed as vanity and less than
nothing in His sight.
Think, too, of His all-sufficiency. His infinite fullness,
the boundless wealth of His being. He needs nothing.
He has no occasion to go beyond Himself for absolute bless-
edness. In the person of the Trinity is a glorious society ;
in the infinite perfections of His essence is perfect good.
He can receive nothing from the creature, for it is only a
faint reflection of Himself. How diiferent is man — poor,
feeble, dependent man ! We have nothing that we can call
our own. The breath we breathe is borrowed ; we live only
as we are kept. The treasures we have to-day may be gone
to-morrow; we are the sport of accident and chance. A
straw can wound us, a fly can kill us. If you add to all
this the immutability of God, and then consider our chang-
ing and fitful history, the contrast is complete betwixt us
and the Author of our being.
With such an immense disparity how al^surd in us to
Rebuke of airo- tkiuk of Comprehending the plans of the
gance, cavilling and Almighty ! How arrogaut to arraign His
wisdom at our bar ! We presume to sit in
judgment upon His schemes, we question the arrangements
of His providence, we cavil at the unequal distribution of
His favours, we complain that the world might have been
made better, and we murmur and repine when our own lit-
tle plans are crossed or disappointed. But who are we that
presume to rise against God ? What wisdom is that which
ventures to condemn the counsel of the Holy One ? Who
is this that darkeneth counsel by words without knowledge ?
Let us learn the lesson of our ignorance, and where we can-
not understand, let us not be tempted to censure or repine.
It is enough that God does it. That word God is a guar-
antee that all is right.
LECTURE IX.
CREATION.
THE fact of creation is vital in Theology, as upon it de-
pends the question of the relation betwixt the world and
God, and even of the absoluteness and independence of the
Divine Being. There are but five conceiv-
po^Tser'"''"'''" ^ible hypotheses upon which the relations
of the finite and infinite can be adjusted.
The first is that of the Atheists, which denies the existence
of the infinite, and acknowledges the reality only of the
world ; the second is that of the Eleatics, which denies the
existence of the world, and admits only the reality of the
infinite ; the third is that of the Pantheists, who admit both,
but resolve them into unity by making them phenomenal
modifications of the same substsinae ; the fourth is that of
the Dualists, who recognize two eternal substances, mind and
matter, of which the one is essentially passive, the other
active ; and the fifth and last is that of a genuine Theism,
which makes God the creator of the world, and makes the
world a real thing, separate and distinct from God. We
may here discount the first two hypotheses
The first two dis- ^^ havius^ in our times no advocates who are
counted ; o
entitled to much consideration. But it is
clear that Dualism is inconsistent with the infinity and
absoluteness of the Supreme Being. If matter exist inde-
pendently of Him, His knowledge of its laws and proper-
ties has been acquired. He has had to learn them. His
power, too, like that of man, is conditioned by the nature
of the material upon which He has to work. Like ours it
206
Lect. IX.] CREATIOX. 207
is the handmaid of knowledge, and consists in obedience to
laws that He has discovered. The eternity of matter evi-
dently, then, reduces God to the category of the finite, the
limited, the conditioned. He ceases to be self-sufficient.
He ceases, in other words, to be God. He may be a skil-
ful workman, an admirable contriver, a wonderful mechanic,
but all in consequence of acquired knowledge. He is a man
on a large scale. Dualism, therefore, is disguised Atheism.
Hence creation is invested with so much importance in the
Scriptures. God is everywdiere presented in them as the
Creator of the w^orld, and not as the skilful architect of
nature. This hypothesis of Dualism may,
also the fourth. it t .it
consequently, be discounted as essentially
Atheistic. The only scheme inconsistent with creation
which remains is that of Pantheism. This is the prevail-
ing tendency of modern philosophy. If
PanthcTstic!' ' °^°^ ^^ wc admit both the finite and the infinite, it
is clear that they must either be the same
or different. There is no medium. The Pantheist affirms
that they are the same ; the Theist that they are different.
The Pantheist resolves the finite into a phenomenon of the
infinite ; it is its mode of appearing or of manifestation.
The Theist affirms that it is a different thing— a real sub-
stance, separate and distinct from the eternal and infinite
substance. The natural impressions of the mind are in
favour of Theism. It is only the difficulties which are en-
countered in the problem of Creation that have driven ■
modern speculation into Pantheism, as it drove the ancient
philosophers into Dualism.
The fundamental postulate of Pantheism is that creation
is impossible — that it is self-contradictory
Fundamental postu- i i i -r» on' •^ -t/
late of Pantheism. aud absui'd. Bccauseof the impossibility
of creation, and only because of it, has the
hypothesis been invented wdiich seems most naturally to
account for the facts of consciousness in default of creation.
If now this postulate of the Pantheist is rashly assumed,
if it can be shown that creation involves no contradiction
208 CREATION. [Lect. IX.
and terminates in no absurdity, then it must be conceived
as established. If speculation cannot refute it, as the most
natural and consistent scheme it must be admitted. The
question, therefore, which vre have to resolve is simply
whether creation is possible. Let us examine the process
by which the Pantheist reaches a negative answer.
1. Creation, it is said, involves the notion of making
„ ,,. „ „ ,, somethino; out of nothino;. It makes that
Outline of Panthe- & o
istic objections to ere- to be wliicli had uo being before. Nothing
is therefore a material upon which one
works — a subject about which an agency is employed. Now
this is self-contradictory. To be a material or subject of
operation is already to be something. The maxim is self-
evident that out of nothing nothing can be made. But if
we look to our notion of poioer, Ave shall see that it excludes
the notion of creation. We know power from its effects, and
all effects with which we are acquainted are mere changes in
existing objects. To produce without a pre-existing mate-
rial, to work without something to work upon, is an anomaly
which no experience either of what passes within or without
us justifies us in asserting. In fact, we can attach no mean-
ing to the words.
2. The second objection is drawn from the nature of God
as implying plenitude of being. He is the sum-total of
reality. As the fullness of being He must be one — He must
exclude all other realities. If you admit the existence of
another real being, separate and distinct from God, you
might conceive that being added to God, and then God is
not the all. As far forth as the other being has reality, God
is wanting in omnitude of being. The all must be one, per-
fect and complete. Nothing can be added to it, nothing
taken from it. Hence real existence admits no distinction
of plurality and difference.
3. A third objection is drawn from the will of God. If
creation be supposed, God created either necessarily or freely.
If necessarily, then the world would seem to be part of Him-
self. There was no foreign impulse to determine His will,
Lect. IX.] CREATION. 209
and a necessity ab intra would seem to terminate upon His
own being. Again, if the world be admitted as separate and
distinct from God, a necessitating influence ad extra would
be a determination of the Divine being inconsistent with Plis
all-sufficiency and His unconditional absoluteness. It is the
same as to condition Him from without.
But if tliis difficulty were obviated, we are perplexed to
understand how the will of God can be determined to the
contingent, the finite, the imperfect. If the world be a free
product, its being limited and conditioned would make the
limited and conditioned both objects of the Divine knowledge
and of the Divine will, either of which would seem to imply
an imperfection. We cannot understand how God can will
anything but the infinite and eternal.
Further, if the will of God be eternal, the world must be
eternal, or an interval has elapsed betwixt the will and the
execution. That interval implies succession, consequently
change, and consequently a denial of- God's eternity. The
will and its execution must co-exist. If the will existed only
when creation began, then there was something new in God.
Hence the world must be eternal. Besides, all duration is
the same. There is no reason why creation should have
taken place when it did, rather than earlier or later. No
reason for preference can be found in the duration. There-
fore, to select one point of time rather than another, when
the claims of all time were exactly equal, is to attribute to
God an arbitrary proceeding, a will without wisdom. Hence
creation must be eternal. On the same ground it must be
infinite in space. All the parts of space are equal. No
motive can be conceived for selecting one part rather than
another, and to avoid an empty choice we must project cre-
ation in the whole void.
Again, if God has freely created the world. He desired it.
Will without motive is inconceivable. Upon this supposition
we have two difficulties : (1.) That an infinitely perfect and
blessed being should desire the imperfect and limited. This
seems to us to be a degradation — a letting Himself down
Vol. I.— 14
210 CREATION. [Lect. IX.
from the heights of His felicity. (2.) If the world be not
eternal, and yet has been an object of Divine desire, that de-
sire, having been eternal, is a confession in God of eternal
want. Hence, He is not all-sufficient.
Further still, the world has been created either perfect
or imperfect. If perfect, it has fullness of being in itself,
and there is no need for God. If imperfect, all the difficulties
connected with a world beginning in time, limited in space,
conditioned in being, emerge.
4. To these difficulties must be added those which spring
from the existence of evil, of positive disorder, crime and
misery in the world. These evils seem to be utterly incon-
sistent either with the benevolence or the omnipotence of
God. He could either have prevented them or He could
not. If He could have done it and refused. He is not abso-
lutely good ; if He would have done it but could not. He is
not all-powerful. In either case He ceases to be God.
This is the brief outline of the arguments against the
possibility of creation, as they are very clearly and felici-
tously stated by Jules Simon in his spirited little book on
natural religion.^
Of these four classes of arguments this general criticism
may be made, that they labour under the
Capital vice of all 'j. ^ ' r ±± ±' ^ i • 'xi •
these arguments. Capital vicc of attcmptuig to bmig withm
the forms of the understanding what tran-
scends the capacity of thought. They assume the infinite,
the unconditioned, the absolutely perfect, as a thing about
which we are as competent to speculate as the facts of expe-
rience. • They bring it into the relations and under the
conditions of our faculties of knowledge without being con-
scious that the very circumstance of subjecting it to these
limitations destroys its nature. It is the infinite no longer
if it is comprehended within the narrow sj^here of human
cogitation. What is apprehended as the infinite and rea-
soned upon as the infinite is a tissue of negations ; which, the
human mind accepting as positive elements of consciousness,
1 Chapter iii.
Lect. IX.] CREATION. 211
becomes involved in an endless series of contradictions.
Hence such absurdities are not arguments. They are only
puzzles or logical riddles. They prove
They are liut puz- j.1 • i j. j.i • j. p ^
zies or logical riddles, nothing but the niipoteucy of reason, and
the incompetency of philosophy to trans-
cend with its logical forms the sphere of experience. It
cannot be too strenuously insisted on that the infinite is
believed, not known — that as existing it is a necessary
affirmation of intelligence, a thing which we cannot but
accept. But when we undertake to represent the object of
this faith, we can only do it by recurring to the conditions
under which it is awakened, and by divesting what is posi-
tively given of all limitations. This negation of limitations
puts the object beyond the grasp of the understanding, and
we are guilty of a gross paralogism when we reduce it to
the forms and categories of our human thought. We may
reason about it, but we cannot reason from it. Now in the
question of creation the great difficulty is the coexistence of
finite and infinite, the one and the many, the perfect and
the imperfect. In attempting to adjust the relations be-
twixt them, we imperceptibly take for granted that we know
the positive properties and attributes of the infinite, as we
know the positive properties and attributes of the finite,
whereas we know the infinite only as the negation of the
finite. These negations wx preposterously make positive.
We confound, in other words, a non-positing of the infinite
with a real positing, and setting out with a fundamental
blunder, it is no wonder that every step should plunge us in
deeper darkness. He that reasons upon no as if it were
yes, must not be sm^prised at the perplexity of his conclusions.
A detailed consideration of the difficulties alleged against
the notion of creation will show that even
in this point of view it will not suffer in
comparison with Pantheism, or any other hypothesis touch-
ing; the nature and oria!;in of the world.
1. The objection that the idea of creation is self-contra-
dictory and absurd, proceeds upon a double misconception.
212 CREATION. [Lect. IX.
It first assumes that nothing is a positive subject of operation
— a real pre-existing material upon which
First objection based ± o i.
on a double miscon- powcr is exertcd. It takcs for granted
"^^ '°°' that the preposition ex in the philosophic
axiom ex nihilo nihil fit, represents the material cause. This
is a gross mistake. Nothing is simj)ly the term from which
existence begins. The meaning is, that something now is
where there was nothing before ; that something, in other
words, has begun to be. Creation is an energy of God, an
effect of the Divine omnipotence, produced without the con-
currence of any other principle. His power as infinite is
without limits. It is, therefore, not restricted, like that of
the creature, to the modification of a pre-existing material ;
it not only changes, but makes its objects. There is no
more contradiction in the notion of power as giving being
than there is in the notion of power as changing being.
Both may be incomprehensible, but neither is absurd. The
second error is, that the notion of power is determined to
only one class of effects. It is true, experience presents
us with no instances of power but those produced through
the medium of motion. But the concept may be separated
in thought from any specific form in w hich it is realized ;
it is simply that Avhich produces effects without reference to
their nature or the conditions under which it is exerted.
Hence, creation as an effect is as clearly an instance of power
as motion. It is, indeed, the highest exemplification of it.
To say that God wills and a world follows, requires no other
simple idea to understand it than is involved in the asser-
tion, I will and my arm moves. The mode in which the
power operates is different, but the idea of power is the
same. In neither case do we understand the mode of ope-
ration. Because one is a matter of daily experience we
confound familiarity with knowledge, and think we under-
stand it when we do not. What power is in itself we are
unable to conceive. It is a mystery in every form of its
exhibition, and as we cannot grasp it in itself, it is perfectly
preposterous to limit it to one class of effects. There is con-
Lect. IX.] CREATION. 213
sequently mystery, but no absurdity, no self-contradiction,
in saying that the worlds were made by the power of God.
2. To the second objection, which makes creation contra-
dict the plenitude of the Divine Being, it may be replied
that the creature has no reality which it does not derive
from God. Though separate and distinct from Him, it is
not independent of Him. His will is the basis of all the
reality it contains. Lot that will be withdrawn, and it be-
comes nothing. Hence the whole sum of its being was in
Him virtually and potentially before it existed, and creation,
therefore, has neither added anything to Him nor to the
amount of positive reality in the universe. God alone is
equal in the sum of being to God plus the universe. But
if this answer should not solve the diffi-
The second objec- 1j.*j. i j_j.1j.1j. j.1'
tion retorted. culty, it may bc retorted that pantheism en-
counters it in another and still more objec-
tionable form. The world is a phenomenon of God, a mod-
ification of His being. The phenomenon has some reality,
it has some kind of existence ; otherwise nothing could be
predicated of it. Now the appearance of the phenomenon
either adds its own being to that of God, and then He was
not absolutely perfect before ; or it does not, and then there
is some reality which cannot be affirmed of Him. The dif-
ficulty presses the Pantheist as sorely as the Theist, unless
the Pantheist is prepared to maintain that His phenomenal
modifications are pure nothings. The difficulty, in truth, is
one which lies against every hypothesis which recognizes the
All-perfect as one and simple and complete. To deduce the
manifold and plural from the one and simple, to exjilain their
coexistence without destroying unity, is a problem which the
understanding cannot solve, whether the manifold and plural
be that of thought, of phenomenon, or of finite substance.
"We have not the data for even apprehending the real nature
of the problem — it embraces terms which transcend the
limits of human speculation. The fundamental error is in
taking for granted that we know the absolute in itself. The
very fact that the difficulty attaches to all systems, shows
214 CREATION. [Lect. IX.
that it is grounded in the impotency of human reason, and
not in the nature of the things themselves, if we had the
faculties to seize them in their essential reality.
3. In relation to the difficulty arising from the knowledge
and Avill of God, it must first be remarked
DifiBcuIties from i ■ t i i t • i •
knowledge and will of that tliis, like tlic preceding, IS not obvi-
Sntheil'.""'*''' "'' ated by adopting the scheme of the Pan-
theists. On the contrary, it assumes in
that scheme the appearance of a series of positive contradic-
tions. The limited, contingent, imperfect is made a part of
God ; it pertains to the very essence of the Divine nature.
God does not realize the fullness of His own being without
those phenomenal modifications of weakness and imperfection
which it is supposed to be incredible that He should create.
He can possess them in Himself, and yet be infinite ; but
He cannot make them, as substances separate from Himself,
without ceasing to be God. Betwixt the two propositions,
God creates the finite and God is the finite, there is no com-
parison as to the difficulties that they respectively involve.
One is encumbered with perplexities, the other with absurd-
ities. The real difference, in this matter, between the Theist
and the Pantheist is, that one refers all weakness and im-
perfection to a creature that is not God ; the other places
them in God himself. But, in the next place, we must
remember that we are incapable of conceiv-
It transcends our , r> tn- • i i i i
powers to comprehend ing the iiaturc 01 JDivinc knowlcdgc or the
^=;:r::r operation of the Divine wm. What God's
consciousness is, how subject and object in
Him are related, how He knows, we are unable even to con-
jecture. We can think of His knowledge only in the terms
of human consciousness. We distinguish the subject and
object. Now if the object of Divine knowledge be Himself,
it is certainly infinite, and there is no difficulty ; — if Him-
self, the infinite, virtually and potentially contains the finite —
that, as included in Himself, must fall within the sphere of
His consciousness, considered as infinite. There is no more
difficulty in God's knowing the finite than there is in the
Lect, IX.] CEEATION. 215
existence of the finite, whatever form it take, whether of
substance or phenomenon. The knowledge of the infinite
inckides all that the infinite can produce, whether as modifi-
cation or real being. The difficulty, therefore, subsides into
that of the possibility of the finite, as fact.
In regard to the will of God, it is evident that He Him-
self must be the beginning and the end of all His determi-
nations. He must act from Himself and for Himself. We
cannot conceive that the finite has been chosen for its own
sake — that the will of God terminates upon it as the last
end. Such a procedure would indeed be a degradation.
Grounds upun which ^u* it is possiblc that there may be in the
we can conceive God finite, as au objcct of the Diviuc will, rela-
might choose to create. . ,.„. i-i- •/••
tions to the infinite which justify its crea-
tion as a transcendent proof of wisdom and goodness. It
may be that these very perfections have determined the pro-
duction of the universe of creatures, and therefore that the
finite is willed only on account of the infinite. It may be,
too, that a goodness which delights to communicate itself,
and creates worlds that it might floAV out upon them in holi-
ness and joy, as it exists in an infinite being may be com-
patible with the most perfect self-sufficiency and self-beati-
tude and blessedness. God is not rendered more holy and
more blessed in making creatures to behold His glory and
taste His love, but it may be that a nature perfectly blessed
may freely choose to impart bounties. It may be that infi-
nite goodness has nothing approximating to selfishness. We
cannot reason from mere metaphysical grounds in relation
to a moral being. The question turns here upon higher
principles than the mere balancing of the amounts of entity
or substance. The true end of the creation, and therefore
the true motive of the Divine will, must be sought in a
higher and nobler sphere than that of mere being. The
difficulties which emerge to speculation in one sphere dis-
appear before morality in another.
The will of God as eternal does not by any means involve
an eternal creation. It implies an eternal decree to create —
216 CREATION. - [Lect. IX.
„, , , , thatis, an eternal decree to beo;in time. The
■ The decree to create ' &
and its execution not execution of a decrec may not be co-exist-
co-existeut. . ■, . f, . -, ■, .
ent with its lormation, and yet the inter-
val imply no change. Otherwise there could be no succes-
sion of events at all. The argument goes the whole length
of affirming that all things must be simultaneous, or they
are not the objects of the Divine will. As to the notion
that all the parts of duration and space are equal, that
there is no motive for choosing between tliem, and that
consequently creation must be unlimited in both respects, — it
proceeds upon the assumption that time and space are real
things, and not the logical conditions of existence. To
those who deny them any reality, there is no difficulty ; to
those who regard them as real, the difficulty arises, but it
may be resolved into the incomprehensibility which attaches
to the nature of the Divine will.
4. The fourth class of objections drawn from the exist-
Objections to crea- ^ucc of cvil is Icss formidable upon the
tion from the exist- scheiiie of Theisiii than that of Pantheism.
enoeof evil not dimiu- ^-^ -, t. ■• . /.
ished, but aggravated, God, accordiiig to the partisaiis of creation,
by Pantheism. -^ ^^^ ^^^ subject of cvil ; it cxists Separate
and apart from Him. The Pantheist lodges it in His own
nature. He is, if not evil, yet far from being the absolutely
good. The truth is. Pantheism is obliged to repudiate all
moral distinctions. Right and wrong are reduced to the
contrasts of nature out of which is evolved universal har-
mony. The bad is as necessary as the good. The propor-
tions of the universe equally demand both. If evil appears
as disorder, it is only from our partial view of it. If we
could take in the whole scene of things, we should perceive
that the perfection of the wdiole would suffer without it.
In this broad contradiction to the dictates of our moral
nature we see that Pantheism not only removes no difficul-
ties in the notion of creation, but that it introduces absurd-
ities and paradoxes which defy the possibility of unsophis-
ticated assent. It annihilates man's highest distinction,
prostrates his noblest hopes and chills his warmest aspira-
Lect. IX.] CREATION. 217
tions. He has no real being — he is only a shadow projected
for a moment upon the surface of the infinite, soon to vanish
and disappear for ever. He is to be absorbed in the all-com-
prehending substance. His individual, personal conscious-
ness must perish ; immortality is a more stupendous con-
tradiction than creation. Shadows we are, shadows we
pursue ; as shadows we are cheated, and as shadows we
must finally be dissolved. These are the propositions which
are so plain, so simple, so comprehensible that we are in-
vited to exchange for them the doctrine of a real existence,
a real destiny, a real immortality, a real heaven or hell ; — so
obvious that to find these we must be willing; to lose our-
selves.
The Pantheistic hypothesis rests upon the assumption that
the world has no substantive reality, or that it is not a sep-
arate and distinct thing. The metaphysical subtleties by
which this paradoxical scheme has been supported have all
originated from inattention to the limits of human know-
ledge, and from a desire to know what
thrown by the deiiv- trausccuds tlic rcacli of our facultics. The
eranees of conscious- ^j.^^ proccdurc of pliilosopliy is to iuquirc
what are the delivcances of consciousness,
to accept these as ultimate principl 'S, and to regulate our
conclusions by these data. If we take this method, the con-
troversy can soon be brought to a close.
1. Consciousness unequivocally avers that the world has
The first is that the ^ real, scparatc, substautive being. It is
world has a real, sep- the uuivcrsal faith of thc racc. Panthe-
ism, the highest form of idealism, is a
speculation of the schools, and can never be carried out into
practical life. It is a species of skepticism w'hich we may
persuade ourselves to adopt as a conclusion of philosophy,
but which we can never realize as a fact of experience. In
every case of external perception we are conscious of two
things — of ourselves as percipient subjects, of the external
world as a perceived object. We know them both, and we
know them both as real existences. They stand in contrast
218 CREATION. [Lect. IX.
to each other, and their distinction in the act of perception
is but the reflection of their distinction in reality of being.
They are both cognized under that intrinsic law of exist-
ence by which alone we recognize a substance. Conscious-
ness, therefore, reveals matter as substance, mind as sub-
stance, and each as distinct from and contrasted with the
other. To repudiate the testimony of consciousness is to
repudiate the possibility of knowledge ; it is to annihilate
all intelligence. The universality of this conviction proves
it to be natural ; the impossibility of divesting ourselves of
it as a practical conviction confirms the inference. Either,
then, consciousness is false, and all knowledge impossible,
or mind and matter are real, distinct, separate, substan-
tive beings.
2. Subject and object, mind and matter, as revealed in
consciousness, though real substances, are limited, condi-
tioned, dependent. They recipi'ocally condition each other.
They are bounded by time and space. The world presents an
aspect of mutability, a successive influence
The second is, that n i ff j i i • i i
the world is finite. ^* causc aud eticct, a coustaut interchange
of action and reaction. Its history is a his-
tory of vicissitudes. The world is finite. This is as clearly
the testimony of consciousness as that the world exists. It has
no principle in it that resists succession and change. On the
contrary, it is bound to time, which necessarily implies both.
3. These two facts, that the world exists and that the
world is finite, imply another, that the world
From these two pro- , ■, , . . • , i i
ceeda the third, that UlUSt liaVC bCgUU. A SUCCCSSIOU WltUOUt
the world had a begin- beffiuuiug is a coutradictiou in terms. It
ning. . .
is equivalent to eternal time. A being of
whose existence time is the law cannot be eternal. But
time is the law of all finite existence ; therefore, none can
be eternal. Or, to put the argument in another form : an
infinite series of finite things is a contradiction. According
to the hypothesis, everything in the series had a beginning,
but the series itself had none — that is, what is true of all
the parts is not true of the whole. A chain without a first
Leot. IX.] CREATION. 219
link is impossible, but a first link annihilates the notion of
eternal being. The world therefore had a beginning.
4. Having reached this point, we are led to an inevitable
disjunction. If it had a beginning, it began spontaneously —
that is, had an absolute commencement, or it sprang from a
cause. An absolute commencement is not only inconceiv-
able, but contradictory to that great law
The fourth is, it had c • i if i*it ij^
g^^^^^gg 01 intelligence which demands tor every
new appearance a cause. The world, there-
fore, must have been caused, but a cause which begins exist-
ence, creates. The world, therefore, must have been created.
In this argument we have done nothing but reprockice the
facts of consciousness, and unfold explicitly what they im-
plicitly contain. They give us a real world, subject to the
law of time, which must have begun, and must therefore have
had a creator.
This deduction is so simple and natural that it may seem
strange that the reality of creation has ever been called in
question. The wonder will disappear when we call to mind
what the history of philosophy so abund-
Speculation has ever .i -n ^ x ^1 x j_t j. l I*
tended to contradict autly illustrates, that the tendency of
the facts of conscious- spcculatiou lias cver been to explain the
uess.
incomprehensible, and thus to lose itself in
contradictions to the most palpable deliverances of conscious-
ness. Instead of looking into consciousness, and accepting its
primitive utterances as ultimate and supreme, tliey have been
turned into propositions to be proved; and as, from the
nature of the case, no proof could be given, and as their
denial would involve intelligence in a war upon itself, the
result has been the doubt in relation to matters which would
have been perfectly obvious if speculation had not obscured
them. Hence the denial of an external world ; of personal
identity ; of the immortality of the soul ; of moral distinc-
tions ; of the being of God. These are all fundamental ele-
ments of reason — a part of the natural faith of mankind ;
and, practically, nature has always asserted them in defiance
of the sophistries of a perverse philosophy.
220 CREATION. [Lect. IX.
For ages, philosophers, instead of interpreting aright the
fact of consciousness in external perception, laid it down as
a first principle that the object known was diiferent from the
object perceived. This crotchet, accepted without examina-
tion and transmitted in different forms, was never questioned
until it brought forth the fruit of universal skepticism. In
the same way, the principle that out of nothing nothing can
be made — true only in relation to nothing as efficient cause —
has been universally applied to nothing as material cause,
or terminus a quo, and has not only excluded the possibility
of creations, but contains in its bosom the seeds of absolute
atheism. As, in the one case, the testimony of nature was
silenced by a dogma, so in the other ; and as, in the one case,
nature made reprisals by plunging the understanding in
hopeless darkness, so in the other it inflicts the yet greater
curse of leaving us without a God.
5. There is still another step which we are authorized to
mv. «fti • ti f fi . take. As the finite is limited to time, and
The nitn is, that the '
Creator is eternal and aS timC bcgiuS witll the finite, tllC bciug
who creates must be independent of time.
That the first creature should have been made by a finite
being, is equivalent to saying that time was before it began.
It is, therefore, a contradiction in terms to attribute all be-
ginning to the begun. The Creator there-
God only can create, ,1,11 rri
lore must be eternal antl necessary. Ine
first act of creation is the sole prerogative of such a being.
But are we authorized to say that no creature can, under
any circumstances, create ? Are we authorized to say that
no new beings can now begin from the agency of others who
have also begun ? There is evidently a difference between
the first beginning and any subsequent commencements. It
does not follow that because creation in the first instance is
limited to God, that therefore it must always be restricted to
Him. But there is another aspect in which this conclusion
presents itself as little less than self-evident.
or annihilate. -i m ,
To create and to annihilate are expres-
sions of the same kind of power — they are both equally ex-
Lect. IX.] CREATION. 221
pressions of omnipotence ; that is, they are expressions of
power unlimited and unconditioned. To annihilate, so far
from implying subjection to any conditions of actions, de-
stroys them all. It removes time, empties space, abolishes
substance, and leaves nothing to be conditioned. This,
surely, is inconsistent with the notion of the finite. The
power to abolish all conditions is the power to be infinite.
But creation is just the reversed view of annihilation. Cre-
ation makes the transition from nothing to something ; an-
nihilation makes the transition from something to nothing.
They are correlated as altitude and depth. Now if the power
to annihilate be contradictory to the notion of a creature, the
same must be true of the power to create. Divines have
illustrated the infinitude of power involved in creation by
representing the distance betwixt something and nothing as
infinite. They are contradictory opposites, and no being
can bridge the abyss which separates them but the infinite
God.
All finite power is limited to obedience to the laws of
nature. It is conditioned by the properties and attributes
of the substances upon which it operates. These substances
must be given as a pre-existing material, and the creature
can then work within the limits of the capabilities of the
subject. This limitation to the properties and laws of exist-
ing substances seems to be the characteristic distinction of
finite agency. Hence, all that it achieves is to arrange, com-
bine, change, modify. It produces new effects only by ad-
justments, which bring into i^lay, in new forms, the forces of
nature. Beyond these conditions it can never pass. Hence,
creation as an unconditioned exercise of power ; as requiring
neither material, instrument, nor laws; as transcending
change, modifications, or adjustments of existing things, is
the sole prerogative of God. It is His to create as it is His
to destroy. The principle is vital in the-
This principle is i ti' i. i l j. xi
vital iu theology, ^^^SJ- I^ crcaturcs could create, the uni-
verse would not be, or might not be, a
revelation of God, These heavens and this earth, our own
222 CREATION. [Lect. IX.
bodies and souls, might have been the products of being as
dependent as ourselves. The great decisive proof of revela-
and fundamental in ^lon, involvcd in the idea of miraculous
the evidences of Chris- powcr as the exclusivc prerogative of God,
would be swept away. A miracle would
cease to be the infallible credential of a Divine Messenger.
Revealed and Natural Religion would be put in equal jeop-
ardy. But the truth is so obvious that creative j50wer be-
longs only to God that it has commanded the testimony of
the race, with a few partial exceptions, and that in forms of
the strongest assurance. The very fact that philosophers
have denied the possibility of creation is a pregnant proof
that they regarded it as involving a power even transcending
that of God. The few who have ventured to suggest that a
creature might create have affirmed, at the same time, that
he could create only as the instrument of God ; and even in
that case very few have been willing to say that the power
could be habitual and resident in it. It may, therefore, be
taken as the universal faith of mankind that creation cannot
be the work of a creature. It is the prerogative of God, and
of God alone.
LECTURE X.
IIAN.
/CALVIN has very properly remarked that true wisdom
^ essentially consists in the knowledge of God and the
knowledge of ourselves. Each is indispensable to the other.
All the positive notions which we frame of the attributes of
God are derived from the properties of our own souls, and
without some just apprehension of our own nature, capaci-
ties and destiny the conception of religion becomes unintel-
ligible. We must know ourselves in order to know aught
else aright.
That man is the centre in which, so far as this lower world
is concerned, all the lines of creation con-
Man a microcosm. i i • i
verge and meet, that he is the crowning
glory of God's sublunary workmanship, is evident alike
from the peculiarities of his being and from the inspired
history of his production. He unites in himself the two
great divisions of the creature — persons and things ; he is
at once subject and object, mind and matter, nature and
spirit. He has elements which work under the blind and
necessitating influence of law — which enter into the chain of
causes and effects extending through all the impersonal uni-
verse ; he has other elements which mark the intelligent
and responsible agent, which separate him from the whole
sphere of mechanical agencies, and stamp him with the
dignity and the high prerogative of intelligence and free-
dom. All the forms of life which are distributed among
other creatures are concentrated in him. He has the growth
and assimilating properties of the jilant, the motion and
223
224 MAN. [Lect. X.
spontaneous properties of the animal, and to these he adds
the sublimer endowments of personality and reason. He
is, therefore, a representation, a miniature embodiment of
all other creatures. He is the kosmos upon a small scale;
tlie whole creation finds its counterpart in him ; he contains
the fullness of created being. The history of his creation
completely accords with this account of his position. He
was the last of God's works, and the Almighty proceeded
to his formation with a solemnity of counsel that indicated
the place he was destined to occupy in the 'scale of being.
" Let us make man," is a formula of consultation employed
in the production of no other creature. Then, earth and
heaven are laid under tribute to furnish the materials. His
body is curiously and Avondrously "wrought from the clay,
and life is infused into him from the breath of the Almighty.
He became a living soul. We are not to suppose that the
process of forming the body was completed, and that then
the endowment of reason was imparted. There was no in-
terval between the organization of the one and the infusion
of the other. They w^ere simultaneous operations. Man
became a living soul in the very process of receiving the
body so wonderfully and beautifully ]jade.
As thus deliberately made, thus strangely mingling heaven
and earth, he is fitted to occupy a place in which he shall
represent God to the creatures and the creatures to God.
He is fitted to collect all those traces of Divine wisdom
and goodness ^vhich are so conspicuous in the works of the
Divine Hand, and to render to the Supreme Architect, as
the high priest of nature, the tribute of praise which the
creatures can reflect, but cannot express. Hence he is des-
tined to exercise dominion over them. He becomes their
lord. Through him and for him they accomplish the end
of their being — they are for him as he is for God.^
But it is necessary to take a more detailed view of those
excellencies wdiich give to man his dignity and pre-eminence.
"VVe shall consider, first, those peculiarities which distinguish
1 Kurtz, Bib. and Ast., p. 152.
Lect. X.] MAN. 225
him as man, and without which lie could
Threefold division .-i iiii 'xxi
of the subject. ^^* "^ regarded as belongmg to the species.
We shall then consider his condition
when he came from the hands of his Maker ; and, thirdly,
the destiny which he was required to achieve.
I. His distinguishing characteristics as man may be
summed up in the attributes of reason and
person ^^^''"*'"^ ^ * of will, or intelligence and freedom. Or
the whole may be expressed in the single
term person. All other terrestrial creatures are things.
They live in the sphere of blind impulses and successive
impressions. Their spontaneity is a mere force, and their
consciousness is only a continued series of perceptions or
sensations, without any distinct affirmation of a self or re-
flective contrast of subject and object. Brutes do not know ;
they only feel. They are conscious of this or that impres-
sion, but they are not conscious of themselves. They can
never say I or Thou. Now in order that sense and the
phenomena of sense may yield knowledge, there must be a
principle which reduces all these perceptions and sensations
to a conscious unity. We must recognize them as ours, as
belonging to us, and we must recognize them as proceeding
from objects which are not ourselves. But in addition to
this, there must be conceptions which constitute the forms
into which all individual experiences are cast and under
which they are arranged. These forms or categories or con-
cepts generalize the singular, unite the manifold, and make
experience the parent of a fixed and abiding knowledge.
These concepts or categories or regulative principles of rea-
son are the indispensable conditions of intelligence ; there
can be no thought without them. Judgment can only real-
ize itself in and through them. Take away such notions as
those of unity, of plurality, of difference, identity, equality,
cause, uniformity, and it would be impossible to compare
our individual impressions or to attain to the conceijtion of
general laws. All knowledge is just the application of the
primitive concepts of the understanding to the materials of
Vol. I.— 15
226 MAN. [Lect. X.
sense or consciousness. When we pass beyond the sphere
of exj)erience, and demonstrate the existence of the super-
sensible, it is by the aid of primitive beliefs which consti-
tute the very substratum of intelligence. Now these primi-
tive concepts, whether they exist as faith or as mere regula-
tive forms of thought, are the essence of reason. They make
knowledge and experience to be possible. By these man
knows, and by these he extends his knowledge beyond the
sphere of sense. He draws the distinction betwixt truth
and falsehood. This is the first office of reason. The word
truth, the word error or fuheliood, would be altogether
unmeanino; to the brute. But reason also draws the line
between right and wrong, between a duty and a crime.
Reason, in the form of a conscience, gives us the concepts of
rectitude, of obligation, of merit and demerit. It prescribes
a law to the will, to the impulses, the appetites and all our
springs of action, and constitutes man a moral and responsi-
ble creature. He has a will which is capable of being influ-
enced by the declarations of reason, and which, as it acts in
obedience to reason, elevates our impulses into a higher
sphere, and gives them a dignity to which the appetites of an
animal can lay no claim. By virtue of the joint possession
of reason and will man is able to love and hate. The brute
can do neither. Love is not mere desire ; it is not blind
attachment or headstrong passion ; it is founded in the
perception and the embrace of the good. It is will deter-
mined by intelligence. It is, therefore, a rational principle.
Brutes cannot hate ; they may have ferocity and violence,
but they have no malice. That is a will perverted from
reason, divorced from intelligence and enslaved to selfish-
ness. So all the passions — pride, envy, charity, compassion
as a principle — are conditioned upon the possession of reason
and will. These attributes, therefore, are
Reason and will ilis- x* i ^ i • ±_ rr^i i
ti..gui8h humanity, csseutial to humanity. They make man a
person. Through them he has rights, is
susceptible of society, recognizes truth and duty, and is an
intelligent, moral, responsible being, and not a thing.
Lect. X.] MAN. 227
These attributes involve the existence of a principle in
man which cannot be resolved into any modifications of
matter. They involve the substantive ex-
and involve a soul in . . /. ■• r^\^ t , • , • i , • ,
man. isteucc 01 a soul. llie distinction betwixt
soul and body turns upon the conscious
difference of their respective attributes. We know sub-
stance only in and through its properties, and where the
properties are contradictory ojjposites we are compelled to
infer that the substances cannot be the same. Thought and
extension have no points in common. Matter is essentially
divisible, consciousness essentially indivisible. The same
reasoning will prove this soul to be naturally immortal —
that is, incapable of destruction by any natural causes. The
simplicity of its being precludes dissolution, and that is the
only form of destruction with which we are acquainted.
God, it is true, may annihilate the soul ; it has no life in
itself. But we have no reason to believe that anything
which has ever been called into being will ever cease to be,
and whatever God has rendered incapable of discerption,
we are to infer that He designs shall always exist in the
same form.
It has been debated in the schools whether the three-fold
life of man, sensitive, animal and rational, is the result of
the same spiritual substance in its union with the body, or
whether each is the manifestation of a different immaterial
principle. We are certainly not to multiply causes beyond
necessity. The higher forms of creation seem to take up
into themselves the principles of the lower. The life of the
vegetable is taken up into the life of the animal, as a fuller
expansion of the principle of life ; and so reason in union
with the body contains the life of the animal. The same
soul may manifest itself under different conditions in different
forms ; it may have a higher and a lower sphere. The ques-
tion, however, belongs to physiology rather than religion.
Whatever answer we give to it, the essential proj^erties of
man remain still the same.
228 MAN. [Lect. X.
i„>mortaiity yindi- The immortaliiy of the soul, apart from
catea apart from the positlve teaching of Scripture, may be
vindicated upon the following grounds :
1. It is the natural and spontaneous sentiment of man-
kind. It has never been denied except by philosophers, and
that on speculative grounds. It is the universal sentiment
of the race.
2. It follows from the simplicity of the soul — the indi-
visible unity of consciousness.
3. It flows from the sense of responsibility, which is
alwaysva prospective feeling.
4. It flows from the nature of knowledge and from the
nature of virtue. (The Socratic argument.)
5. From the insufficiency of the speculative grounds on
which the contrary hyj)othesis is maintained — That death
will destroy us ; that our identity is lost when a portion of
our being is gone.
6. The 071US probandi is on the other side.
II. Having considered the essential properties of man, we
come now to inquire into the condition in
Was man created an t_*i.t_ r j.ii i ^i,-/^
infant or in maturity? ^^ich hc camc from the hauds of his Cre-
ator. Was he introduced into the w^orld in
the maturity of his jDOwers, with habits of knowledge and
virtue and language, or w^as he framed in an infantile state,
simply with capacities of acquiring knowledge, virtue and
language, but destitute of any actual possession of any of
them ?
This question becomes important in consequence of the
efforts of Pelagians to escape from the doc-
thewLT^"^" "^'^ trine of original sin, and the distinctions
of the Papists in consequence of which
some loop-hole is left for the doctrine of free-will. The
theory is, that man was created in puris
In puris naluralihus. i • i i • i
naturahbus — that is, he Avas created in the
possession of all those attributes and properties which dis-
tinguish him as a species, and without which he could not
be man, but destitute of all the habits and accomplishments
Lect. X.] MAN. 229
which perfect and adorn his nature. He had sense, reason
and freedom of will, but these existed in the form of capa-
cities, and not of developed energies. It is particularly
maintained that he had no holy habits ; the Pelagians affirm-
ing that all holiness had to be the acquirement of his own
free-will, and that he was framed indifferent to rectitude or
sin ; the Papists maintaining that holiness was superadded
to him as a supernatural endowment. It belongs" not to the
sphere of nature, but to the higher sphere of grace. In
either case, original sin is reduced to very small proportions.
Upon the Pelagian scheme it is totally denied ; we are all
born as blank in relation to character as Adam was made.
Upon the Popish hypothesis, it is rather a loss of something
above nature than a corruption of nature itself. Holiness
was a garment in which Adam was clothed after his creation,
but was no part of the furniture that belonged to him as a
creature. Original sin is the removal of the garment and
tlie reduction of the race to its primitive nudity. The differ-
ence, according to Bellarmin, betwixt Adam in Eden and
his descendants is the difference betwixt a clothed man and
a stripped man. Now, in opposition to this theory, reason
and the Scriptures concur in teaching that the first man
must have been created in comparative maturity, with his
faculties expanded by knowledge, his will charged with rec-
titude, and his whole nature in unison with his moral and
personal relations. He was not an infant, but a man. His
mind was not a blank, but a sheet well inscribed with Di-
vine instructions. He was created in a state that harmonized
at once with all his duties, and enabled him to fulfil his
high vocation as the representative of God to the creatures
and of the creatures to God. He was in actual possession
of knowledge, righteousness and true holiness.
1. The hypothesis that man was created an infant in mind
Adam not created an ^anuot be Carried out without the most
infant, either in mind yiolcnt and incredible suppositions. It
or in body. , . p . , ,
postulates a series ot miracles, protracted
through years of his existence, out of keeping with the whole
230 MAN. [Lect. X.
analogy of Divine Providence. Man's body was either fully
developed, or that also was the body of an infant. If it
were fully developed, then it had the strength and comjjact-
ness of maturity and growth. Now an infant mind in a
matured body can consist with the preservation of life only
hy a constant miracle. The infant knows nothing of the
properties of matter ; has not yet learned to judge of distance
by the eye, or to determine the magnitude, hardness and
solidity of bodies by the eye. It cannot calculate the di-
rection of sounds by the ear, and it knows nothing of their
significancy. It is a stranger to its own strength. It has
no discernment of the qualities of food and poison. It would
have to learn the use of its senses — to acquire by slow expe-
rience all those cognitions which we now acquire in our early
years, and which have become so habitual that we mistake
them for immediate and original perceptions. In this con-
dition of helj)less ignorance it Avould run against the hardest
obstacles ; be liable to pitch down the steepest precipices ;
mistake poison for food ; and expose itself without appre-
hension to the greatest dangers. The life of such a being
could not be preserved for a single day without a perjoetual
miracle. Its matured body would be a curse to it. The in-
congruity of such a constitution is sufficient to stamp it with
incredibility. But if we suppose that the body of the first
man was that of an infant, then we have to j)Ostulate a mi-
raculous guardianship through the whole period of its being,
from the first moment of creation until it has reached maturity
of knowledge. God would have to be to it a nursing mother
and a protecting father. It would have to be miraculously
fed, miraculously nursed, miraculously guarded, until it ac-
quired the habits and exj)erience necessary to enable it to
take care of itself. In the present order of providence, in-
fant minds are put in infant bodies ; and the body is not
allowed to reach the power of self-motion until the mind has
acquired the skill to direct it. We are prevented from
walking until we have sense enough to walk with some
safety. We are put under the guardianship of parents and
Lect. X.] MAN. 231
friendS; and their experience supplies our deficiencies until
we have laid in a stock of our OM^n. The matured body
always implies the matured mind. It is clear therefore, from
the nature of the case and from the analogy of providence,
that if Adam were created in maturity of body, he must also
have been created in maturity of mind. But maturity of
mind consists in habits of knowledge. It is knowledge
which makes mind grow and expand. There is no difficulty
in supposing that the first man was created with the know-
ledge resident in him that we acquire by slow exjjcrience.
When he first looked upon the world he had the use of
senses, as we learn it, and he thus derived, at once, all those
impressions which we deduce by long habits of association.
To this extent he must have had knowledge, or he could
hardly have lived an hour.
2. Incredible as the supposition is of a pure nature with-
A,]a,n not created ^^^^ ^^^^itS of kuOwlcdgC, it is UOt SO absUrd
injiifiient to holiness as tlic suppositlou of a purc moral nature
without habits of righteousness. There is.
no middle betwixt sin and holiness. Every moral being
must be either holy or sinful ; there is no such state as that
of indifference. The will is, from the very nature of the
case, under formal obligation to coincide with the moral law.
There is no moment of time when this obligation does not
hold. It must, therefore, in order that the man may not be
guilty, incline to that law, so that, in all concrete cases, it
shall choose the right. Hence, to say that man had simply
the capacity to become holy or sinful, but that at his creation
he was neither, is to say that there was a time, an interval
of his being, when he was under no moral obligation, and
therefore an interval of his existence when he had neither
reason nor will ; that is, it is a plain self-contradiction. To
be indifferent to rectitude is itself sin. Hence, it is clear that
man must have had determinate moral habits of some sort,
and could not be produced in purls naturalibus. An infant
now has a determinate moral character. It may not actually
have sinned in specific voluntary acts, but its will is im-
232 MAN. [Lect. X.
bued with the law of sin, and as soon as it wills it wills
wrong.
3. The Scripture testimonies upon this subject may be
reduced to two heads, direct and indirect —
of'scHpTure.'"*""'' ^hosc which explicitly state what the con-
dition of man really was, and those which
obviously imply it. Let us consider the indirect first :
(1.) Man is represented as in possession of language.
Now language without thought is impossi-
inttTerJ^ctiof "' blc. It bccomcs ncccssary in the higher
spheres of thought, so that all inference
beyond particulars is conditioned upon its existence. Adam
had language in its most difl&cult and complicated relations.
His words were not merely proper names, or expressive of
single, individual phenomena. They were generic terms,
and implied the distribution of the objects of creation into
corresponding classes. " And Adam gave names to all cat-
tle, and to the fowl of the air and to every beast of the field."
To suppose that he appropriated a name to each individual
as its own distinctive title is simply preposterous. His
vocabulary would have to be boundless and his memory
equally marvellous. The plain meaning is, that he knew
them and named them as genera and species. The notion
of an infant conducting such a process is fit only for those
who have not yet ceased to be infants themselves.
(2.) In the next place. Eve was evidently framed in full
maturity as a woman. She was recognized
Eve created a ma- rAl ± Hj. l ±\
ture woman. "^7 Adam at ouce as a nt and worthy com-
panion. Now the argument from this cir-
cumstance is twofold : If Eve were created in such matu-
rity as to be a suitable helj) for man, why not Adam have
been created in corresponding perfection? But Eve was
created on the same day with Adam. He must, therefore,
have marvellously developed in a few hours if he could so
soon acquire language, learn the distribution of animals and
come to a sense of his own need of society. If Eve had
been created in the infancy of either mind or body, and he
Lect. X.] MAN. 233
had been mature, she would have been a burden and not a
companion. If he had been still in the ignorance and im-
becility of infancy, he would not have known that he wanted
an associate. Hence, on either supposition the narrative
becomes contradictory and absurd. But admit the maturity
of Adam as to mind and body, and the whole story becomes
simple and consistent. No one, in fact, can read the account
of the creation of the first pair without being struck with
the impression that they are treated from the very first as
beings who have the use of their reason, and who are fully
at home in their new circumstances and relations. They
understand the scene in which they are placed. They are
not children, but adults — endowed not with capacities only,
but with the knowledge that enlarges and exercises them.
(3.) The command to the first pair, " to be fruitful and
„, . , multiply, and replenish the earth and sub-
They received a r J ? i
commission involving duc it, and liavc domiuiou over the fish of
the sea and over the fowl of the air, and
over every living thing that moveth upon the earth," be-
comes absolutely ludicrous if conceived as addressed to in-
fants or children. It implies a complicated and extensive
knowledge — a knowledge of the creatures and a knowledge
of God, and a knowledge of themselves — as the indispensable
condition of understanding, much more of fulfilling, the
Divine mandate. All finite power is exerted through knoAV-
ledge, and as the dominion of man was to be the dominion
of intelligence and reason, it implied an apprehension of
the nature and relations of the objects to which it extended.
These three circumstances — that man is represented as in
possession of language and the knowledge which language
necessarily symbolizes ; that he felt his need of companion-
ship on the very day of his creation and received a help
suited to his wants ; and that he received a commission in-
volving a very high degree of intelligence in order to con-
vey any meaning to his mind — are grounds from which we
may confidently conclude that man was not created in a
state of pure nature ; that he was something more than a
Adam
savage.
234 MAN. [Lect. X.
realization of the logical essence of the sjoecies. He must
have had the accidents which though logically separable
can never be separated in every degree from his nature.
(4.) The general tenor of the narrative contradicts, too,
the notion that in his primitive condition
he was a savage, rude and uncivilized, de-
voted to sensual indulgences and ignorant
of a higher end. The knowledge of the creatures which he
possessed, enabling him to classify and distinguish them,
far transcends in its extent and accuracy the rough and pal-
pable discriminations of the savage. His relish of compan-
ionship shows a development of social ties which is of the
very essence of refined life. And his commission to multi-
ply and replenish the earth, and to make nature the obedient
minister of his will, implies a state of mind exactly the
reverse of that which delights in war and destruction, and
in which the only monuments of jDOwer that are prized are
monuments of ruin. The command implies a spirit of love
to the species and of regard to the other creatures of God
totally incompatible with the fierce and vindictive passions
that characterize savage life. Adam, in the picture of
Moses, was no barbarian. He is the loving father of the
posterity contained in his loins, the tender and aifcctionate
husband, and the considerate master of this lower world.
His mission is to bless and not to blast, to promote and
not destroy the happiness of his subjects. Tliese are the
impressions which the narrative makes apart from any
express and positive declarations as to the state and
condition of man. This is their general and pervading
import.
4. But evidently as these considerations refute the notion
of an infantile or savage commencement
These testimonies /> , i ,^ , /v> • x j_
not definite as to of the racc, thcy are not sufficient to give
Adam's knowledge or ^^g precise aud definite information in rela-
holiness. ^
tion to the condition of the first man.
They show him to have been intelligent, refined and civil-
ized, but they do not reveal to us the extent of his know-
Lect. X.] MAN. 235
ledge, nor the degree of perfection which as a moral being
he enjoyed.
(1.) Upon the first point the Scriptures are nowhere ex-
upon the first point pli^'^*' Thcj Icavc US in the dark as to
the Scriptures are uot tJic amouut of natural kuowledgc — that is,
the amount of knowledge in relation to the
objects and laws of the universe — which he possessed. It
was substantially what every man who reaches maturity
must acquire from experience. The naming of the whole
animal creation would seem to intimate that it was much
more. It is useless to speculate without data, and M'here we
have only hints we should not push our conclusions beyond
them. AYe should avoid the extreme of considering Adam
as endowed with faculties which intuitively penetrated into
the whole scheme of the universe, and laid the treasures of
all human science at his feet, while we insist upon the ma-
turity of reason which must have pertained to him. The
Scholastics erred in attributing to him too much ; the Socin-
ians and many modern divines have equally erred in attrib-
uting to him too little.
(2.) But in reference to his moral condition the Scriptures
are very explicit. They have left no room
but upon the second n i i , xx- • -i' < ,
very explicit. ^^r douot. His primitive state is repre-
sented as a state of integrity, in which every
part of his constitution was adapted to the end for which
he was created. This is what is meant when it is said that
he was made upright. As the end of his creation was moral,
he must have possessed the knowledge and the dispositions
which were necessary to the attainment of it. As the moral
law bound him from the first pulsation of his life, that law
must have been impressed upon his nature, and his first acts
of consciousness must have been in conformity with its spirit.
It must have been written upon his heart ; it must have
formed an original element of his being. That this was the
case is articulately taught in all those passages which repre-
sent him as bearing in his primitive condition " the image of
God." The proper explication of this phrase will explain
236 MAN. [Lect. X.
the perfection of his moral state. A slight
hastwo'sTnfrs° " examination will show that it is used in a
looser or stricter sense. In a looser sense
it indicates those spiritual proj^erties which belong to man
as a person — the faculties of intelligence, conscience and
will. But a close inspection will show that even in the
passages in which the phrase is thus loosely taken there lies
at the foundation a tacit reference to the other and stricter
meaning. For example, in Gen. ix. 6 : " Whoso sheddeth
man's blood, by man shall his blood be shed ; for in the
image of God made He man ;" the argument manifestly
turns upon the moral nature of man, the rights which con-
sequently accrue to him, and the perfection which he is pre-
cluded from attaining by prcmatui'e death. So James ex-
poses the wickedness of cursing our fellow-men because they
are made after the similitude of God — that is, moral perfec-
tion is their destiny, that to which they should aspire, and
of which they are capable. The reason that the phrase is
transferred to our spiritual and personal nature apart from
any direct implication of positive holiness, is that this nature
is the indispensable condition of holiness ; it is the subject
in which that must inhere. Hence it has been called the
natural or fundamental image of God ; it is the condition
on which alone man can realize that image. But the strict
The strict and prop- ^ud propcr acccptatiou of the phrase is
er sense is holiness, holiucss — holiucss of uaturc, or habitual
manifested in know- it t • • i i f
ledge and rigiiteous- holincss, as contradistiuguished irom spe-
''®^^' cific exercises or acts. The decisive pas-
sages are Eph. iv. 23, 24 ; Col, iii. 10. From these pas-
sages we learn that the image of God consists generally in
true holiness, and that this holiness, as the universal spirit
or temper of the man, manifests itself in knowledge and
righteousness. It is that state of mind which })roduces
these results. To define it more accurately we must ascer-
tain the meaning of the terms knowledge and righteousness,
as liere used by the apostle. Here we are at no loss. It is
the knowledge of God which results in faith, love and true
Lect. X.] MAN. 237
religion. It is, in other words, a spiritual perception of His
beauty, excellence and glory. Adam, as en-
i .^? /n 1 "^ dowed with this knowledge, looked abroad
knowledge of Uou, o ?
upon the creation and saw what science
with all its discoveries so often fails to discern — the traces
of the Divine glory. He saw God in all above, beneath,
around. Nature was a vast mirror, reflecting the Divine
beauty, and as he saw he loved and adored. God to him was
everywhere present ; the whole universe was full of his name.
It was written upon the starry vault, the extended plain, the
lofty mountain, the boundless sea ; upon every living thing,
from the reptile that creeps upon the ground or the tiny in-
sect that flutters in the breeze, to the huge leviathan or his
own noble frame and nobler soul. The first light of day that
beamed upon his eyes was accompanied with a richer light that
radiated from his soul, and clothed all nature in the garb of
Divine beauty and loveliness. He knew God with a spiritual
discernment as a being to be loved, feared, trusted, worsliipped.
This was holiness as it irradiates the understanding:. This
knowledge of God in the creature is the perfection of know-
ledge. Science, until it reaches this point, does but fumble.
It misses the very life of true knowledge ; it is only a learned
and pompous ignorance.
But this habit of spiritual discernment was accompanied
with righteousness or rectitude of disposition
and also this rectitude. . ^ i . ^ .
— that IS, a state of soul m conformity with
the requisitions of the Divine law — a propensity to universal
obedience. The law was the bent of his being. As soon as
the concrete occasions should present themselves, he had that
within him which would at once reveal and incline to the
right. The intuitive perception and the prompt disposition
manifested his holiness, and induced all forms of actual right-
eousness which his circumstances and relations demanded.
This, then, was the primitive condition of^
The primitive con- » t tt i • j^i • p r^ -i
dition of the first man. Adam. He was made in the niiage of God
— as being an upright creature, with reason
enlightened in the spiritual knowledge of God as that know-
238 MAN. [Lect. X.
ledge was mediated through the creatures, with a will prone
to obey the dictates of reason thus enlightened and therefore
in accordance with the spirit of the Divine law. He knew
his relations to God, his relations to his wife, his relations to
his children and his relations to the world ; and knew them
with that spiritual apprehension which converted his know-
ledge into one continued act of religion.
That true holiness is the strict and proper sense of the
image of God, appears from the contrast
sonai^anrspii-itulfnT bctwlxt thc iuiagc of God aud that of the
tnre, but not the image Pevil. If the posscssiou of a pcrsoual,
spiritual nature were the image of God, the
Devil and his angels would bear it. But their image is, in
the Scriptures, made directly contradictory to the image of
God. Hence, that image must consist in those moral per-
fections which Satan has lost, and which man, since the fall,
acquires only by a new creation.
The holiness which man possessed at his creation was
In what sense the natural— uot in the logical sense that it per-
hoiiness of Adam was taiucd to liis csseuce as man, or was a prop-
natural. . i i r- • i • i
erty inseparable irom it, but m the sense
that it coexisted as a habit with that nature. Man was not
first created and then holiness infused, but holiness was con-
created with him. He was holy as soon as he began to be.
Hence it is not scriptural, with the Papists, to make it a
supernatural gift, something superadded to nature by grace.
It was no more of grace than creation itself was of grace. It
was the inheritance of his nature — the birth-right of his being.
It was the state in which all his faculties received their form.
5. We have now considered the distinguishing character-
istics of man, and the condition in which he was when he
came from the hands of his Creator. "VVe have seen that he
was neither an infant nor a savage, but a man — in the full
maturity of his powers, endowed with knowledge, righteous-
ness and holiness, and prepared to enter at once upon the
career assigned him as a moral and responsible creature. As
long as he retained his integrity, he enjoyed the blessedness
Lect. X.] MAN. 239
which springs from the harmony of a soul proportioned and
balanced in all its powers, and from the consciousness of the
favour of God and the exercise of communion with Him.
. J , , ,. , But it remains to be added, in order to com-
Aclam 8 holiness nat- '
uiai, but not in<\ofect- pletc tlic picturc of mau's primitive estate,
that his holiness, though natural, was not
indefectible. He was liable to fall. That man, as a creature,
was necessarily mutable, in the sense that he was capable of
indefinite improvement — of passing from one degree of ex-
pansion to another — is easily understood ; but that a holy
being should be capable of a change from the good to the
bad — that he should be able to reverse the uprightness of his
make, to disorder his whole inward constitution, to derange
its proportions and the regulative principles of its actions — is
one of the most difficult propositions that we encounter in
the sphere of theology. Hoav could sin enter where all was
right ? If the understanding rejoiced in truth, the will in
rectitude, and the affections in the truly beautiful and good,
how could error, impurity and deformity find a lodgment
within the soul ? What was to suggest the thought of any-
thing so monstrous and unnatural ? It is clear that there
must have been some defect in the moral state of man at his
creation, in consequence of which he was liable to fill — some
defect in consequence of which he might be deceived, taking
falsehood for truth, and confounding the colours of good and
evil. When we speak of a defect, we do
What was the defect ? ,
not intend to convey the notion that any-
thing Avas wanting to quali^^ man for his destiny ; but that
whatever the difference is betwixt a state of confirmed holi-
ness and a state of untried holiness, that difference was the
secret of the possibility of sin ; and the absence of what is
implied in confirmation is a defect. It was something which
man had to supply by the exercise of his own will in a course
of uniform obedience to God. It is certain that no creatures,
either angels or men, have been created in immutable integ-
rity. Sin has entered into both worlds, and it is equally
clear that there is a great difference betwixt beings in whom
240 MAN. [Lect. X.
holiness has become, as it is with God, a necessity of nature,
and beings who are yet caj^able of being blinded with error
and seduced into transgression. But are we able to say pre-
cisely what this difference is ? Are we able
A problem to be, -j^xi ii Ijt i
gjji^gjj to point out how the understanding can be
deceived and the will perverted in the case
of any being that possesses a sound moral and intellectual
constitution ? This problem, which may be called the psy-
chological possibility of sin, is confessedly one of great diffi-
culty. The solutions which have been attempted are un-
satisfactory ; either as denying some of the
Unsatisfactory solu- x* l j^ j. i' j_i j^ i x*
tions of it. essential lacts oi the case ; or postulating
principles which are contradictory to con-
sciousness; or reducing the first sin to an insignificance
utterly incompatible with the Divine providence in relation
to it.
(1.) The Pelagian has no difficulty, because man at his
creation had no character. His will was
indifferent to good or evil ; he could choose
the one as readily as the other. Upon this scheme there is
really no problem to be solved. But the scheme itself con-
tradicts one of the essential facts in the case. It contradicts
the fact that man was made in the image of God ; that holi-
ness was a constitutional endowment ; that the same grace
Avhich made him a creature made him upright.
(2.) The Papist — that is, one school of theology among the
Papists — finds in the blindness of our im-
pulses, which it calls concupiscence, a suffi-
cient explanation of the difficulty. Our impulses in them-
selves possess no moral character ; they have a natural tend-
ency to excesses and irregularities ; the mere existence of
these irregular desires is not sin, and therefore not inconsistent
with integrity of make. And yet they may prove stronger
than reason; they may bewitch the understanding by soph-
istry, and cajole the will by false appearances of good, and
thus seduce man into sin. Reason, indeed, is no security
against them in a state of innocence without supernatural
Lect. X.] MAN. 241
grace. This theory labours under the fatal defect of denying
that to be sin which the Scriptures affirm to be sin. Our
impulses are not destitute of moral character when they be-
come irregular or excessive. They are as much under law
as any other part of our nature. The very terms irregular
and excessive imply as much ; and a constitution, therefore,
is not sound which generates passions and appetites incon-
sistent with the supreme end of the individual. Paul makes
concupiscence to be not only sin itself, but the fruitful mother
of sin. Of course, if we give the mother, under whatever
specious name, a residence in man's nature, we need not be
surprised that she is soon surrounded with the children. To
say that our impulses have no moral character is to contradict
all human consciousness. Our desires, our appetites, our
hopes, our fears, all have a determinate relation to the will,
which brings them within the sphere of moral responsibility,
and makes them the real exponent of a man's character.
We measure our approbation of others more by these passive
impressions than by the acts which are the immediate pro-
ducts of will.
(3.) A theory akin to this, but modifying its most offensive
feature, is that of Bishop Butler, so ably
Bishop Butler's theory. ,.. , ,, ,.
and ingeniously and modestly presented in
the Analogy of Religion. It proceeds from the same prin-
ciple of the blindness of impulse ; that is, that all our simple
emotions are excited, independently of the will, by the pres-
ence, real or ideal, of their proper objects. There are quali-
ties in things which cannot be contemplated Avithout awa-
kening these feelings. The eye affects the heart. The ap-
prehension of danger has a natural tendency to generate
dread ; the prospect of good elicits hope ; the sight of misery
produces pity ; and the contemplation of meanness and filth
produces disgust. The emotion is awakened without the in-
tervention of the will, without the deliberation of the under-
standing or the verdict of reason. The mere apprehension
of the object does the work. Now, Butler does not postulate
that in a sound state of the mind any impulses tending to
Vol. I.— 16
242 MAN. [Lect. X.
sin could exist ; lie does not lodge in us a concupiscence, in
its natural promptings, contradictory to reason and to con-
science, and here he avoids the Papal extravagance. In a
sound state of the mind our j)assive impressions coincide
with rectitude, but still they are not elicited by a conscious-
ness of rectitude. ISTo act of intelligent thought precedes
them, and as thus excited, without any previous estimate of
the value of their objects, they are blind ; and here is a
defect in our nature, which, though not sin itself, may open
the door for sin. The security against this defect is the
forming of a habit of never yielding to an impulse, or per-
mitting it to influence the will without reflection. The
danger of the impulse is that we may act without thought ;
the security is a habit, formed by a course of vigilance, of
never acting Avithout thought. But it may be asked. If the
impulses coincide with rectitude, what danger is there for
betraying us into sin? None, if man's determinations
always centred only upon wdiat is essentially right. If
nothing were ever presented to his choice but what was in-
trinsically evil or intrinsically good, there is no danger of
his passive impressions misleading him. But things indif-
ferent, neither good nor evil in themselves, may be rendered
subjects of positive command. They are suited in their own
nature to excite our emotions. These emotions are not sinful
in themselves, as their objects are not sinful in themselves.
Under the influence of these emotions the will may be in-
clined to the unlawful indulgence, the understanding may be
tempted to plead for it, and thus sin and error be introduced
from the impulses of man coming in collision with positive
commands in relation to things inherently indifferent. This
is a brief outline of the psychological explanation of that
great master of thought, in a work which will live as long
as sound philosophy has votaries.
There are some circumstances in the biblical narrative of
the temptation of our first parents that seem to coincide with
this account. The prohibition which constituted the test of
man's obedience did not relate to a malum in se; the eating
Lect. X.] MAN. 243
or abstaining from a given fruit was in itself indifferent, and
only brought into the moral sphere by the accidental cir-
cumstance of a positive command. That fruit had the same
tendency to provoke appetite as any other fruit in the gar-
den, and accordingly Eve is represented as arrested by its
promising appearance as food and its fitness to make one
wise. " And when the woman saw that the tree was good
for food, and that it was pleasant to the eyes, and a tree to
be desired to make one wise, she took of the fruit thereof,
and did eat, and gave also unto her husband with her, and
he did eat."
But plausible as this hypothesis is, it is exposed to objec-
tions which are not easily resolved.
In the first place, it accounts only for the sin of Eve. It
might be said that Adam was seduced bv
Two objections to it. , , , *'
the passive impression of love to his wife,
had not the apostle told us that the man was not deceived.
It is remarkable that when the guilty pair were summoned
before their Judge, the woman puts in the plea that she had
been beguiled, she had been cheated and taken in, but the
man ventures on no such allegation. He simply says :
" The woman whom thou gavest to be with me, she gave me
of the tree and I did eat."
Again, this theory diminishes the malignity of the first
sin. It becomes an act of inadvertence or inattention. It
was an error incident to a suspension of vigilance, and spring-
ing from principles which constituted a part of human nature.
To suppose that man was merely taken in, and did not mean
to transgress the law of God, that he sinned ignorantly and
by involuntary mistake, is to make a representation which
every moral understanding will instantly pronounce to fall
far short of the intense rebellion which the Scriptures uni-
formly ascribe to the first sin of the first man. It was a
fiilling away from God; a deliberate renunciation of the
claims of the Creator ; a revolt from God to the creature,
which involved a complete inversion of the moral destiny
of man. We cannot avoid the feeling that if Butler's ex-
244 MAN. [Lect. X,
planation is the whole of the matter, our first parents were
deserving of pity rather than severe reprobation — their
offence was weakness and not deliberate guilt.
The common explanation in all the orthodox creeds is,
that the true ground of the solution is to
Orthodox aolution. i • i ^ i mi -nr
be sought m the nature oi the will. Man
is represented as having fallen because he was left to the
freedom of his own will. His transgression was voluntary,
and as voluntary had to be deliberate. His sin was done
on principle. It was not an accident, but a serious, solemn
and deliberate rejection of the Most High as his God and
portion. But this, it will be seen, is not a solution of the
problem, but the statement in another form of the fact to be
explained. The only approach which it makes to a genuine
solution is in indicating the sphere in which the solution
must be sought — the sphere of the will. There must be
something in freedom before it has become necessity of
nature out of which the possibility of sin can arise. We
must, therefore, turn our attention to this point, and ascer-
tain, if we can, what is the difference between freedom
as necessity and freedom as the beginning of a moral
career.
Freedom as necessity of nature is the highest perfection
of a creature. It is the end and aim of
sif "^ornatiire "'^'^^^ ^^^ moral culturc. When a being has the
principles of rectitude so thoroughly in-
wrought into the whole texture of the soul, when it is so
thoroughly pervaded by their presence and power, as that
they constitute the life of all thought and of all determina-
tion, holiness stands in the most inseparable relation to it in
which it can be conceived to stand to a creature. This is to
be pre-eminently like God, who is perfect truth and perfect
righteousness. This entire subjection to the law of God, in
which it becomes so completely identified with ourselves
that we cannot think or act in contradiction to it, is the
ideal of freedom which the Scriptures propose to us as our
inheritance in Christ. This is eternal life. Now, at the
Lect. X.] MAN. 245
commencement of a moral career, our upright constitution
has not been completely identified with our
Freedom not yet de- Tj. i -j. i j. ' 'j. i.
liberateiy chosen. personality, bccausc It has not, m its ten-
dencies and disj)Ositions, been taken up by
our wills and deliberately chosen and adopted. It is the
determination of the will which fixes our natural disposi-
tions as principles. When they are reviewed by the under-
standing and deliberately chosen by the will, they then be-
come ours in a nearer and closer sense ; they are reflectively
approved, reflectively endorsed, and through that energy by
which acts generate a habit they become fixed elements of
our life. If such an exercise of reflection and such an act
of will must supervene in order to impregnate our person-
ality with holiness and to convert native dispositions into
settled principles, it is evident that there must be in the
primitive condition of a moral being occasions in which it
stands face to face with its own nature and destiny, and on
which it must determine whether the bent of that nature
shall be followed and its true normal development promoted,
or whether it shall choose against nature another course and
reverse its proper destiny. If the will has to decide the
case, the issue must be made. Good and evil must stand
in actual contrast, and there must be postulated under these
circumstances a power — wilful, heady, perverse, yet a real
power — to resist truth and duty. God gives man a constitu-
tion that points to Himself as the supreme good. He places
before him the nature and consequences of evil as the con-
trast of the good. If man chooses the good, he fixes it in
his very person ; it becomes so grounded in the will that
the will can never swerve from it. If he chooses the evil,
he also grounds that in the will ; it becomes a part of his
very person ; he becomes a slave, and can never more, by
any power in himself, will the good or attain to it.
This I take to be the sense of the great body of the Re-
Tiiis the doctrine of formed thcologiaus, and of all the Reformed
Calvin, of our Confes- Confessious that havc expressly embraced
sion and of Turrettin, , t • , Ti • i r^ -i • ^
the subject, it is what (Jalvin means by
246 MAN. [Lect. X.
" an indifferent and mutable will," wliicli he attributes to
man in his state of infancy. It is what the Westminster
Confession means when it affirms that man had originally
" freedom and power to will and to do that which is good
and well pleasing to God, but yet mutably, so that he might
fall from it." Turrettin^ resolves the first sin into the
" mutability and liberty of man." " The j^roximate and
proper cause of sin, therefore," says he, " is to be sought
only in the free-will of man, who suffered himself to be
deceived by the devil, and at the instigation of Satan
freely revolted from God." Howe has articulately discussed
these views.
This account of the matter is fundamentally different
and fundamentally dif- f^'O^ ^^^ PclagiaU hypothcsls of the Uat-
ferent from the Peia- ural indiffcrcuce of the will to the distinc-
tions of right and wrong. On the other
hand, it recognizes the law of God as the normal jjrinciple
of the will ; it maintains, farther, that the spontaneous actions
of man, all his impulses, desires and primitive volitions,
were in conformity with that law. His spontaneity was all
right. It was reflectively that the will renounced its law,
changed its own tendencies, made out and out a new deter-
mination. The reflective man, when the ground or root of
action was to be himself, perverted the spontaneous man
whose ground of action was in God. The will did not first
make a character, but change a character ; did not first give
man a moral disposition, but perverted the dispositions
which God had given. By this theory we preserve the
Scripture testimony concerning man's possession of the im-
age of God, and harmonize the malignity which the sacred
writers everywhere ascribe to the first sin of the first man.
To unfold the psychological process which led to such a
perversion of his nature is perhaps impossible ; we are not
sufficiently acquainted with the mystery of the will. All
that we can say is, that it possessed this power of arbitrary
self-determination, in defiance of reason, conscience and
^ Locus ix., Quest. 7.
Lect. X.] MAN. 247
nature, as an essential element of its being. We have the
traces of the same power in arbitrary resistance to our own
reason and conscience in many events of our present fallen
condition. We have lost all holiness, but there are often
cases in the ordinary sphere of our activity where our de-
terminations seem to be obstinately wilful and capricious.
They seem made only to assert our own intense egoism.
But whatever explanation may be given of the possibility
of sin, we know that it now exists, and that the seeds of it
were not implanted in the nature of man as he came from
the hands of God. It is no normal development of his facul-
ties or life. He has introduced it, and therefore we are com-
pelled to say that his primitive condition, though holy and
happy, was mutable. He was not established in his integrity.
His noble accomplishments were contingent.
III. Having now considered the essential elements of
humanity, and the condition in which the
The end of ruau's /> , i i •< • i • •
gj.^a^tio„ nrst man was created, it remams to inquire
w^hat was the immediate end of his creation,
and what the relation in which, as a moral creature, he stood
to God. His chief end was evidently to give glory to God.
He was to learn more and more of God from the Divine
works, and the administration of that great scheme of pro-
vidence which was beginning to unfold itself before him.
He was to render to the Almighty in his own name, and in
the name of all the creatures over whom he had been consti-
tuted the head, the tribute of adoration and gratitude which
the Divine goodness demanded. He was the high priest of
nature ; and every mute tiling, every dumb beast, every
lifeless plant, the majestic heavens, the verdant earth, the
rolling sea, mountains, cataracts and plains — every province
of being in which he saw the traces of the Divine hand —
were to find their tongue in him and through him to pour
into the ears of the Most High their ceaseless song of praise.
They spoke to him, and he was to repeat their language to
the Great Supreme. He stood as the head of an immense
family of worshippers. Creation was a vast temple. Every
248 MAN. [Lect. X.
living and lifeless thing brought its offerings to the altar,
and man was to present the grateful oblation to the Maker
and Preserver of them all. It was a noble, a sublime posi-
tion. To know was to love, and to love was to enjoy.
The relation in which he stood to God may be more ac-
Man's relation to curately defined as that of a servant, and
God was that of a the law of liis life as obedieucc. Obedience,
servant. , „ ^ n • • i i
as expressive oi perfect coniormity with the
will of God, comprehends the whole scope of his existence.
This obedience involved the preservation of the image of
God ; the culture of his moral faculties by reflection, con-
templation and the reflective adoption, as principles of his
will, of his natural holiness ; and a prompt performance of
whatever duties pertained to his circumstances or were es-
pecially enjoined by God. The will of a servant must co-
incide with the will of his master ; in this his faithfulness
consists. Man's will was to make the will of God its su-
preme and only law. But it pertains to the condition of a
servant that his continuance in favour depends on the con-
tinuance of his obedience, and that his expectations from
his master are measured by his faithfulness. This, then,
was man's estate. He was a creature ; a servant under the
moral law as the rule and guide of his obedience ; bound to
glorify God in perfect conformity with its requisitions, and
authorized to expect the continuance of his present happiness
in the sense of God's approbation as long as he persevered
in the way of faithfulness. He had no evil to apprehend,
either to his body or his mind, from within or from with-
out. As long as he was faithful to his Master, he had a
right to expect that his Master would protect him and bless
him. There could be no death while there was no sin. But
the servant must obey from himself. As a servant, man
could never look to any interposition of God that should
destroy the contingency of his holiness. His probation, in
that aspect, must be commensurate with his immortality.
There could never come a period in which lie could have
any claim upon God to render liis integrity indefectible, or
Lect. X.] MAN. 249
to draw him into any closer relations with himself. What-
ever arrangements might be made with a reference to these
ends must spring from the pure benevolence of the Creator ;
they must be the offspring of grace and not of debt. Man
must always stand or fall by his own obedience in the exer-
cise of his own free-will. Through the law of habit a con-
stant course of obedience would constantly diminish the
dangers of transgression, but the possibility would always
remain ; and whatever security man might compass through
the energy of will in fixing the type of character, he must
always stand in that relation to God which measures his ex-
pectations by his service.
That the destiny of man, considered simply as a creature,
was obedience in the relation of a servant is evident from
the very nature of moral government as revealed in the
structure of our own consciences.
FREEDOM OF THE WILL.
[This is one of the most difficult questions in the whole compass of
Metai^hysical Philosophy or Christian Theology. Its inherent difficulties
have been aggravated by the ambiguities of language. All the terms
which are introduced into the discussion have been so abusively employed
that it is hard to fix clearly and precisely the points at issue, or to deter-
mine the exact ground which we or others actually maintain. We im-
pose upon ourselves, as well as upon others, by the looseness of our term-
inology. Liberty, necessity, contingency, possibility, are all used in various
senses, are applied in different relations, and without the utmost caution
we are likely to embarrass ourselves by a latent confusion of these differ-
ent significations.
Necessity is used metaphysically to express that the opposite of which
involves a contradiction ; naturally, to express the connection betwixt an
effect and a cause, an antecedent and a consequent ; and morally, in the
twofold sense of obligation or duty, and the connection betwixt motive
and volition. Liberty is used in relation to the absence of liindrance and
restraint in the execution of our plans and purposes, and refers exclusively
to the power of acting ; or, to denote mere spontaneity — the mere activities
and energies of our inner being according to their essential constitution ;
or, to the exclusion of a cause apart from itself in determining the decisions
of the will. Contingency is used in the sense of the undesigned or acci-
dental ; and, in the sense that another reality was at the same time produ-
cible by the same cause. The possible, again, is the metaphysical non-
existence of contradiction, or the contingent in the sense last explained.
250 MAN. [Lect. X.
These instances of ambiguity of language are sufficient to illustrate the
nature of the difficulties upon this point.
The will is indispensable to moral agency. A being without a will
cannot be the subject of rewards and punishments. Where there is no
will there is no responsibility. In investigating, therefore, the freedom
of the will, the conditions which a just exposition must fulfil are these:
1. Freedom as a confirmed state of holiness — an inward necessity of
holiness, in which the perfection of every moral being consists, must be
grounded .and ex^jlained. Any account of the will which leaves the per-
manent states of heart of holy beings without moral significance ; which
deprives character and rooted habits of moral value ; which attaches
importance only to individual acts, and acts considered apart from their
expression of inward and controlling principles, is radically defective.
2. Any account of the will which does not ground our sense of guilt,
our convictions of ill-desert, and which does not show that these convic-
tions are no lie, but the truth, is also defective. I must show that my sin
is mine — that it finds its root and principle in me.
3. Hence, a just account of the will must show that God is not the
author of sin. To say that He is its author is to destroy its character —
it ceases to be sin altogether.
4. A just account of the will must also solve the problem of the inabil-
ity, and yet of the responsibility, of the sinner — that he cannot, and yet he
ought, and justly dies for not doing what he confessedly cannot do.
The fulfilling of these conditions is indispensable to a broad-sided, ade-
quate exposition of the will. To leave out any of them is to take partial
and one-sided views.
1. Tried by this standard, the theory of Arminians and Pelagians is
seen to be essentially defective. Two forms of the theory — indifierence
and equilibrium. Miiller, ii., 17, 21.
(1.) These theories contradict an established holiness, and deny any
moral character to the decisions of the will — they are mere caprice.
(2.) They do not account for character at all — they put morality in
single acts.
(3.) They deny the sinner's helplessness and even sinfulness — the sin-
ner is as free as the saint, the devil as the angel.
2. The theory of Edwards breaks down.
(1.) It does not explain guilt; it does not rid God of being the author
of sin.
(2.) It does not explain the moral value attached to character.
(3.) This theory explains self-expression, but not self-determination.
Now, a just view must show how we first determine and then habitually
express ourselves. In these determinations is found the moral significance
of these expressions. Otherwise my nature would be no more than the
nature of a plant. Will supposes conscience and intelligence — these
minister to it ; the moral law — this is its standard.
3. There are two states in which man is found — a servant and a son.
Lect. X.] MAN. 251
The peculiarity of the servant is that his holiness is not confirmed. It
exists rather as impulse than habit, and the law speaks rather with author-
ity— sense of duty. Now, the province of the will was to determine —
that is, to root and ground these principles as a fixed nature. There was
power to do so. When so determined, a holy necessity would have
risen as the perfection of our being.
There was also the possibility of determining otherwise — a power of
pervei'ting our nature, of determining it in another direction. The power,
therefore, of determining itself in one or the other direction is the free-
dom of a servant preparing to become a son, and the whole of moral cul-
ture lies in the transition.
This theory explains all the phenomena, and has the additional advan-
tage of setting in a clear light the grace of regeneration.
In the moral sphere, and especially in relation to single acts, this free-
dom is now seen in man. It is neither necessity nor a contempt of the
principle of law.]
LECTURE XI.
MORAL GOVERNMENT.
IN order to appreciate aright the dispensation under which
man was placed, soon after his creation, in the garden of
Eden, it is necessary to have a clear conception —
I. Of the essential principles of moral government;
II. Of what is implied in the relation of a servant.
I. Moral government is a government in which the moral •^
law is the rule of obedience. This is obvious
The first essential of n .i ..i .i i-i-i* t^- ' i i
a moral government. ^^^^^ ^hc Cpithct by whlch it IS distinguished.
But the moral law is the rule of obedience
under every dispensation of religion. It expresses those
eternal distinctions of right and wrong upon which all
spiritual excellence depends ; and which God cannot disre-
gard without renouncing the perfections of His own nature.
Every believer under the Gospel aims at conformity Avith
that law, and feels that his character is defective and his sal-
vation incomplete until it has pervaded his Avhole soul, and
moulded every power and faculty in harmony witli its spirit.
The characteristic principle of a moral government, there-
fore, is the principle upon which rewards
The second essential. ,. ., -, ,^.
and punishments are distributed. I hat
principle is distributive justice. When men are rewarded
and punished in precise proportion to their merits and de- ''
merits, then the government is strictly and properly moral.
The notions of justice, and of merit and demerit, are
]>rimitive cognitions of our moral nature,
tiou indicated.*'''* "^ or of that practical understanding by which
we discriminate betwixt a duty and a crime.
252
Lect. XL] MORAL GOVERNMENT. 253
Conscience, in one single, indivisible operation, gives us cog-
nitions which can be logically separated and distinguished.
There is first the perception of right, which
reo cognitions |^ represented in terms of intellio-ence
given by conscience ; 1 to
and defined as an act of the understanding.
There is next the sense of duty, the feeling of obligation,
which seems to partake of the nature of the emotions and to
be properly defined by tei^ms of sensibility. Then there is
the conviction of merit or demerit, according as the rule has
been observed or neglected, which seems to be the practical
conclusion of a judge in applying the law to a concrete in-
stance. It is the sentence which the mind passes upon itself
according to the nature of its works ; and yet in its simplest
manifestation in consciousness it is a feeling — a sense that
such and such acts or dispositions deserve well, such other
acts and dispositions deserve ill. It is that phenomenon of
conscience which connects happiness with right and misery
with wrong. It is the root of the whole conception of justice.
Without this primitive conviction there could be no notion
of punishment and no notion of reward. Pain and pleasure
receive their moral significance exclusively from that senti-
ment of good and ill desert which connects them ,with con-
duct as judicial consequences.
Though conscience is thus resolvable into three logical
logically distinguish- coguitioiis wliich are casily distinguished in
able, yet fundament- tcrius, tlicy are all fundamentally one and
ally the same. - ^p,, . f • -i i
the same. Ihe perception oi right, the
sense of duty, and the conviction of good and ill desert are
precisely the same cognition reflectively surveyed from dif-
ferent points ; or, rather, they are different forms of express-
ing one and the same original deliverance of conscience.
There is not first an intellectual act, which, in the way of
speculation, pronounces a thing to be right ; then an emo-
tional sanction, which, in the way of feeling, instigates to
obedience; and then a judicial sentence consequent uj^on the
course actually pursued. There are not three separate and
successive states of mind, which reciprocally condition and
254 MORAL GOVERNMENT. [Lect. XI.
depend upon each other. Tliere is but a single act of con-
sciousness, and in that single act these logical discriminations
are held in perfect unity. To say that a thing is right is to
say that it involves obligation and merit ; to say that it is a
matter of obligation is to say that it is right. Obligation
has no meaning apart from rectitude, and rectitude has no
meaning apart from obligation and merit. The perception
of right is not a speculative apprehension ; it is not the
affirmation that something is. It is the apprehension which,
in its very nature, implies the peculiar feeling which we call
a sense of duty — it is the apprehension that something ought
to be. The cognition of the right and the feeling of duty
are the same ; the feeling of duty is the very form, the very
essence of the cognition. Hence, rectitude is an intuition of
our moral understanding, which can be explained by nothing
simpler than itself. You might as well undertake to define
red or blue to a man born blind, or loud or loiv to a man
born deaf, as to represent right to a man whose conscience
■ , PA had never given him the sense of duty or
The sense of good & .'
and ill desert a prim- the couviction of merit. It is a primitive
itive notion. . , , r- i • i i • ■
notion, capable ot being resolved into no-
thing else. The events of experience furnish the occasions
upon which the notion is developed ; it manifests itself
through the sense of duty, and through the praises or censures
which we bestow upon our own conduct or upon the actions
of others. When reflection analyzes the grounds of these
judgments and elicits the principles which, in every instance,
determine and regulate them, we then compass the funda-
mental principles of morals in the form of abstract proposi-
tions. We then have the rules which we can subsequently
apply reflectively and by design.
From this analysis it is clear that merit and right are in-
separably united — that demerit and wrong
Merit and right, •Till j. l rp,
demerit and wrong, ai'c as ludissohibly connectccl. liie man
bound indissoiuMy by ^^j^^ j^gg 'i^^ ^^ j^^ ^^ j^g rewarded, the
a moral tie. o o '
man who does wrong ought to be pun-
ished; this is the form in which the radical notion of justice
LecT. XI.] MORAL GOVERNMENT. 255
first expresses itself in the human soul. Its language is,
that happiness is due to virtue as a matter of right, and
misery is due to sin as a matter of right. This connection
by a moral tie defines the notions of reward and punish-
_, . , ■ ■ , ment. Now, a government which distrib-
TIus moral principle ' o
constitutes a govern- ^tes plcasurc aud paiii cxclusivcly in the
nient moral. „ i i • i i •
way ol rewards and punishments, and in
precise proportion to the good or ill desert of the agents, is a
moral government. That was the government under which
man from the moment of his creation necessarily came as a
moral creature. In the image of God he had the law writ-
ten uj^on his heart which constituted the rule and measure
of his obedience ; and in the sense of duty he had the supreme
authority of that law grounded as a first principle in the
very structure of his conscience ; and in the conviction of
good and ill desert he had engraved upon his soul that im-
perishable notion of justice which, if not sufficient to pro-
tect from the foul wrong of apostasy, would for ever justify
God to his own conscience for the penal retributions which
doomed him to misery and death. God interwove into the
very elements of his being the essential articles of the dis-
pensation under Avhich he was placed as a creature. He
found himself, as soon as he began to be a subject to law,
a servant to his master. This relation was stamped upon
his conscience.
When we proceed more narrowly to examine the import
of the conviction of good and ill desert,
hopeTSlV """' ^ve find that it resolves itself into the expec-
tation of favour from the Supreme Ruler,
or the apprehension of His displeasure. It expresses itself
in the language of hope or fear. There is a still more re-
markable phenomenon ; the sense of guilt or the sense of
demerit is found to obliterate all the claims of past right-
eousness. One sin brings the soul into
bnt condemns the ^^^^^.j-ncss and tciTor. If mau had obeyed
righteous for one sin. J
for years and then in an evil hour had been
tempted into an act of disloyalty, that one act would have
256 MORAL GOVERNMENT. [Lect. XI.
changed his whole relations to the lawgiver and have effaced
the entire merits of his past life. There is no compromise
in merit. Obedience must be complete or
Imperfect obedience >, ^ n'j_ i j^i j_-j.
pyjj it loses all its value; the very moment it
fails all is over. There is no such thing in
a strictly moral government as a balancing of the good and
bad, as weighing them in scales together, and dealing with
the agent according to the preponderance. Obedience is
merit, disobedience is demerit, and obedience ceases Avhen-
ever disobedience begins. Perfect moral government keeps
a creature under probation until it has sinned. Then its
relations are changed. It becomes bound to misery by
the eternal law of justice, and can never be received into
favour until the claims of that law are cancelled. The rea-
son is very obvious why a single transgression cancels a
whole career of virtue. The law can ex-
The creature's whole , ,■•• i, f i t t i
immortality, one life. ^^t llOtlling DUt pcrtcct ObCcllCnCe, aucl aS
the creature is one, its whole life is one, and
a departure in any period of its life mars the perfection of
its obedience, and makes it morally null. A line may be
straight for a great distance, and yet if it has a single crook
in it at any part of its course, it ceases to be a straight line.
Perfect obedience is that alone which is obedience at all, and
the very moment the perfection is lost everything entitled
to reward is lost. All merit vanishes for ever. The reward
which moral government postulates is the continuance of
the Divine favour through the period of obedience — noth-
ing more, nothing less. There must be no unhappiness,
there must be no want, no pain while there is no transgres-
sion. The very language of the law as written upon the
heart is, Do and live, for while you do you shall live. The
infliction of pain upon a perfectly holy being seems to con-
tradict the deepest instincts of our moral nature, for such a
being is necessarily contemplated as the fit subject of re-
wards, and as having a claim for exemption from all that is
evil. I have no hesitation in saying that it would be unjust
that the righteous should die, and equally unjust that the
Lect. XI.] MOEAL GOVEENMENT. 257
wicked should live. It is no more consistent with God's
character to exclude the upright from His favour than to
receive the wicked into favour. He might just as easily
bless the sinner as curse the saint. The law of distributive
justice equally forbids both.
There is another feature of pure moral government that
deserves to be particularly noticed, and that is, that it may
deal with men exclusively as individuals,
Kepresentation not , ii • i • -r-< i
a uecessary principle aucl not collectively as a spccics. Jiiach
of pure moral govern. ^-^^^^^ may bc rcquircd to stand or fall for
ment. _ •' '■
himself alone. There is no principle of
justice which necessitates the complication of others in our
guilt or obedience. On the other hand, there is no princi-
ple of justice which precludes it. In our social constitution,
and the unity of race which includes in one blood all the
descendants of Adam, a foundation is laid for these arrange-
ments of goodness which shall modify our individual inde-
pendence and render possible the participation of others in
our own personal merit or demerit. But this is not abso-
lutely necessary. The principle of representation might
have been ignored, and no one could comjjlain that any in- /
justice had been done him. This principle, therefore, can-
not be regarded as an essential element of moral government
in itself considered. If Adam, in the light merely of a
moral subject, had retained his integrity and had begotten
children, their perpetuity in holiness might have been wholly
independent of his. They would have run their own moral
career ; their relations to their father and the rest of the
species would only have been the occasions of complicated
and interesting duties, in the discharge of which each was to
give account solely for himself. Under these circumstances,
none would have been benefited but by their own obedience,
none injured except by their own transgression ; that is, none
would have been directly rewarded or directly punished.
Indirect aids in maintaining their uprightness all would
have received from the good, and injury in the way of temp-
tations to disobedience all would have received from the bad.
Vol. I.— 17
258 MORAL GOVERNMENT. [Lect. XI.
We have now briefly enumerated the essential elements
of a proper moral governmeut. It is one
Recapitulation. . i • i i
in which the moral law is the rule of obe-
dience, in which distributive justice is the principle of the
disj)ensations of rewards and punishments. We have traced
this principle to its root in human nature, have found it in
the primitive sense of good and ill desert, have seen that it
secures favour to the righteous only during the terra of his
obedience, and that the very moment he transgresses it binds
him over to the penal visitations of guilt; that it pronounces
nothing to be obedience which is not perfect, and that as the
life of the man is one, it must cover the whole of his im-
mortality or fail entirely' and for ever.
Under a purely -^-i- , , ,
moral government the -tieuce hc caii iicvcr Under mcrc moral
creature never safe p;overninent bc excmpt from the possi-
from falling. '^^ _ '^ ^
bility of falling. He can never be ren-
dered absolutely and immutably safe.
II. Having thus defined the nature of a pure moral gov-
ernment, let us next consider a little more distinctly what
is involved in the relation of a servant.
It is contrasted in the Scriptures with the relation of a son,
and when we have obtained a clear conception of the dis-
tinguishing peculiarities of adoption into the fomily of God,
we shall perceive in what respects the condition of a ser-
„. , ,.„ , vant is huinl)ler and less glorious. Xow,
First difference be- o J
twixt a servant and a [n the CaSC of tllC SOU, the grOUud of llis
expectation from God is not his own merit,
but tlie measureless fullness of the Divine benevolence. God
deals Avith him not upon the principle of simple justice, but
according to the riches of the glory of His grace. The ques-
tion is, not what he deserves, but what God's goodness shall
prompt Him to communicate.
From this peculiarity arises another : tlie access to God
is less full and free in the case of a serv-
Socond difference. i . i « mi • i
ant than m that of a son. I here is not the
same richness of communion. There is not the same near-
ness, the same unreserved confidence. How this distance
Lect. XI.] MORAL GOVERNMENT. 259
realized itself in the instance of an obedient subject, how
God manifested His favour, and what was the real extent
of man's privilege in his primitive condition in relation to
his appearance before God — the precise peculiarities of his
subjective state — we are unable to represent. But we know
that there is this marked difference betwixt a servant and a
son. The condition of the saints nnder the Law is com-
pared to that of servants, and the reason assigned is that the
way of access to God was not so fully and distinctly revealed
as under the Gospel.
There is a further difference between the two states in re-
lation to the Law. To a servant it addresses
A further tlifference. . , r, -,..■,.-, r,
itself more distnictly m the way of com-
mand. Its requisitions are recognized as duties ; to the son
it is rather a life than a law, and its injunctions are privileges
rather than obligations. AVhatever may have been the spon-
taneous pleasure of the first man in obedience to the Law, his
exercises were acts of conscious obedience and performed in
the spirit of duty. Love gave him alacrity in all his acts ;
but it was a love Avhich consecrated duty, and which only
sweetened, without absorbing, the authority of law. The
same difference, as exhibited between the saints of the old
and new dispensations, is characterized respectively as the
spirit of bondage and the spirit of adoption. There was, of
course, nothing like slavish fear in the bosom of unfallen
Adam, and there was no irksome attention to his duties as a
grievous and revolting burden, but there was the operation
of conscience which adapted him to moral government, and
which kept constantly before his mind the ideas of merit and
demerit, the eternal rule of justice as the measure of his
hopes, and the hypothetical uncertainty which hung upon
his destiny. He could not have had that rich and glorious
freedom which belongs to the sons of God.
That the account which has been given of the essential
These views of moral priuciplos of moral government and of the
government and the g^cral rclatiou of a scrvaut is not a flmciful
relation ol servant, ~
scriptural. representation, but a just statement of the
260 MORAL GOVERNMENT. [Lect. XI.
attitude in which God and Adam stood to each other at
the commencement of man's existence, is easily collected
from the whole tenor and from many explicit passages
of Scripture. In the teachings of the Old and New Tes-
taments in relation to the economy of grace in the different
stages of its development, there is a constant allusion to those
great facts of moral government which underlie the whole
scheme. Whatever is presupposed as essential to Chris-
tianity in the relations of man to God under the Law, be-
longs to this subject ; and these presuppositions determine
the Scripture doctrine of what moral government actually is
and must be. Founded in immutable justice, its laws and
sanctions can never be set aside. Now, in explaining man's
condition as a sinner, and the truths which must be pre-
supposed in any scheme of justification, the essential relations
of man as a subject of law are clearly brought out. In the
Epistle to the Romans, Paul begins by a distinct enunciation
of the rule of distributive justice which we have seen is its
regulative principle : " Who will render to every man ac-
cording to his deeds ; to them who by jjatient continuance in
well-doing seek for glory and honour and immortality,
eternal life ; but unto them that are contentious and do not
obey the truth, but obey unrighteousness, indignation and
wrath, tribulation and anguish upon every soul of man that
doeth evil, of the Jew first, and also of the Gentile ; for
there is no respect of persons with God." ^ This passage is
very conclusive — it endorses almost everything that we have
endeavoured to set forth. First, the judgment of God is de-
termined by the actual merit or demerit of men. They will
be tried by their works. Those who have obeyed the law
shall be entitled to the rewards of their virtue, and those
who have transgressed must expect to receive the conse-
quences of their guilt. In the next place, the judgment is
personal and individual — it is to every man. There is a
distinction made by grace betwixt the Jew and the Gentile
— no such distinction is known to the law. Moral govern-
1 Eom. ii. 6-11.
Lect. XL] MORAL GOVERNMENT. 261
ment knows only the obedient and the disobedient. It is a
grave error to imagine that in this passage Paul's design was
to set forth the possibility to man, in his present circum-
stances, of justification by the Law. He means to imply no
such thing. On the contrary, his purpose was to evince,
from the principle here laid down, the futility of all such
hopes. To do this he signalizes the conditions of a legal
justification — perfect obedience, the ground on which the
reward is dispensed, and distributive justice; and from these
conditions proves the utter hopelessness of standing before
God in our own righteousness. It is by means of this prin-
ciple that he shuts up all under sin, and leaves no way of
escape but in the free mercy of God through Jesus Christ.
He points out to them what they must do if they would se-
cure favour by their works, and as the requirements are be-
yond their strength, it is evidently vain to place any reliance
upon the Law.
In EzekieP we have certain abstract propositions laid
down, which, whatever may have been their immediate scope
and significancy, as abstract propositions sustain all that we
have said : " Therefore, thou son of man, say unto the
children of thy people. The righteousness of the righteous
shall not deliver him in the day of his transgression. As
for the wickedness of the wicked, he shall not fall thereby
in the day that he turneth from his wickedness ; neither
shall the righteous be able to live for his righteousness in
the day that he sinneth." Here the intrinsic merit of obe-
dience and the intrinsic demerit of disobedience are broadly
asserted. It is affirmed that the value of righteousness ceases
with the first act of sin. In the day that the righteous man
sins he forfeits the right to life. But there seems also to be
maintained that the demerit of sin can be cancelled by sub-
sequent obedience, and that the sinner by penitence may put
himself again in the position of a righteous man. If this
were the meaning, the second proposition would be contra-
dictory to the first. The abstract proposition is, that a man
^ Cli. xxxiii. 12, seq.
262 MORAL GOVERNMENT. [Lect. XL
cau never perish considered as righteous, and that upon the
supposition of a sinner becoming really and truly righteous,
he would not be a fit subject for punishment. Such a change,
however, is impossible except under a system of grace, which
expiates guilt and renews and sanctifies the heart, and im-
putes to our obedience the merit which purchased the grace
wherein we stand. The general notion of the whole passage
is, that righteousness — true and real righteousness — is, in
itself, acceptable to God ; but that true righteousness is in-
consistent with the least sin. The soul that sinneth must
surely die. Hence, the prophet is far. from saying that a
sinner can repent by virtue of any provisions of the Law.
He only says what would be his condition and his j)rospects,
provided he could be found again in a state of righteousness ;
and the very necessity of repentance is a testimony that God
cannot communicate the sense of His love while the love of
evil continues to reign in the heart.
Moral government must be carefully distinguished from
Moral government, moral discipline. Thc ouly discipline which
how distinguished ^lic Law rccognizcs is the discij)line of growth.
from moral discipline. , . . - . -,
ihe servant may increase in knowledge and
ability, and with every step of his progress the circle of his
duties increases. But a process of education, by which habits
of holiness are formed and propensities to evil eradicated,
belongs to an economy under which sin can be pardoned,
and imperfect and sincere eiforts to obey accepted as perfect
obedience to the Law. Without provisions for expiation of
guilt and the communication of God's grace, a state of moral
discipline to a sinner is a palpable absurdity. The Law pun-
„, . ,, T , ishes, but never seeks to reform the criminal.
v\ hat the Law knows, '
and what it does not Jt puts him to dcath, but nevcr seeks to
know. 17 • 1
restore him to life. And punishment, apart
from grace, has no natural tendency to ameliorate — it only
hardens the heart. Conscience makes us desperate, but
never penitent. The Law knows nothing, therefore, of re-
pentance. Once a sinner, according to it, always and hope-
lessly a sinner. The line that has one crook can never be
Lect. XI.] MORAL GOVERNMENT. 263
made straight. The obedience that fails once fails in all.
The relation, too, of holiness to the favour of God shows
that no provision can be implied in the nature of the Law
for restoration to good.
Moral Discipline and Moral Government are distinguished :
1. As to their principle; the principle of discipline is love —
that of moral government is justice. 2. As to their end ;
the end of moral discipline is the improvement of the sub-
ject— the end of moral government is to maintain the
authority of law. 3. In their penalties ; sins in moral dis-
cipline are faults to be corrected — in moral government they
are crimes to be punished. One is the administration of a
father over his children — the other a dispensation of the
magistrate to subjects. 4. Righteousness in the one is a
qualification — in the other a right. The distinctions are so
broad and j^alpable that nothing but confusion can result
from treating them as essentially the same. Indeed, many
of the most ingenious hypotheses .invented to explain the
evil of the universe have plunged their authors into irre-
Discipiine is of tricvablc perplexities by the capital mistake
grace ; government is Qf confouudiug what SO obvioUsly bclouo; tO
of nature. ° ,,..,.
ditierent spheres. Moral discipline per-
tains to the kingdom of grace — moral government is the
essence of the kingdom of nature.
[In recasting this lecture, attend to the following suggestions :
I. Moral government distinguished — 1. By its rule. 2. By its principle,
distributive justice. 3. Perpetual innocence, its requirement. 4. Repent-
ance impossible. 5. Individual in its claims.
II. The relation of a servant. Bring out the idea that the law is
looked on more as an expression of will — its authority prominent. In the
case of a son, the prominent notion is that of imitation — imitators of God
as dear children.]
LECTUEE XII.
THE COVENANT OF WORKS.
HAVING considered the essential principles of moral
government, and what is involved in the relation of a
servant, we are prepared to understand and appreciate the
peculiar features of the dispensation under which man was
placed immediately after his creation. Though God in jus-
tice might have left man to the operation of a pure moral
government, conducted by the rule of distributive justice,
and might have for ever retained him in the attitude of a ser-
vant, yet the Divine goodness seems to have contemplated
from the very beginning a nearer and tenderer relationship,
and a destiny of inconceivably greater dignity and glory
than mere justice would or could have awarded. It was
always God's purpose to turn the servant
into a son. What sonship implies it is
impossible for us adequately to conceive.
The Apostle John declares in reference to the sonship of the
saints, " It doth not yet appear what we shall be, but when
He shall appear we shall be like Him, for we shall see Him
as He is." The ground of a son's right to the blessings he
enjoys is the love of the father, and the principle on which
he possesses it is that of inheritance and not of debt. To
be a subject in whom God may express the infinite goodness
of His own nature, to be an heir of Him who is fullness
of joy and at whose right hand there are pleasures for ever-
more, is certainly to be exalted to the highest excellence of
which a creature can be possessed. Then, a son has un-
limited access to his father's presence. His communion
264
The servant to be-
come a son.
Lect. xil] the covenant of works. 265
with him is full and rich and free. The conception of
such a purpose, so far transcending all the demands of jus-
tice, is a conspicuous display of the grace and goodness which
have characterized all the dispensations of God in relation
to our race. It was a great thing to be a man, endowed
with capacities of truth and knowledge and duty ; a great
thing to have been made susceptible of all the refined and
tender sensibilities which belong to our race — sensibilities
which convert the contemplation of the scenes of nature into
a feast, which drink beauty and joy and rapture from the
grand and sublime spectacles which greet us in the starry
canopy above us, the swelling mountains around us or the
majestic sea before us — sensibilities which convert the ties
of domestic life into charms, and make society in all its com-
plicated relations the minister of good ; it was a great thing
to have been created in the image of God, with a heart to
love and adore His great name and exemplify the holiness
of His character, to have been made immortal and capable
of an everlasting sense of the Divine favour — to have been
thus made a man, a holy man, an immortal man, with the
prospect of endless good, surely this w^as grace ; it was grace
upon grace ! Plato said that there were three things for
which he blessed God: 1. That he had been made a man,
and not a beast ; 2, that he had been born a Greek, and not
a barbarian ; and 3, that he had been permitted to live in
the age of Socrates. With how much more fervour should
the first man have celebrated the Divine goodness as he
walked forth upon the new creation in all its loveliness and
beauty, and was regaled on every hand with the tokens of
the Divine regard ! How must his heart have overflowed
as he sounded the mysterious depths of his own being, and
felt the grand and glorious capacities with which he was en-
dowed ! His first utterance must have been praise, his first
impulse to throw himself upon the ground and bless that
God who made him what he was. It was amazing good-
ness to have furnished him with all the blessings that
crowned his lot, considered merely as a servant. But what
266 THE COVENANT OF WORKS, [Lect. XII.
shall we say of the goodness that could not stop here — that
as it recognized in man the capacity of closer ties Avith itself,
yearned to take him to its bosom and pour upon him a
richer tide of glory and of joy than the cold relations of
law and justice could demand? Surely, our God is love;
creation shows it as well as the cross !
Grace in tUo first c< i /^ i • xi £ j_
covenant. ourcly, our (jrod IS gracc ; the nrst cove-
nant proves it as truly as the second !
In order that the change from the condition of a servant
to that of a son might take place, it was necessary that the
man should prove himself faithful in the first relation.
Adoption was to be a rcAvard of grace, but
Adoption of grace, .-n-i ,i tTj^ x
and yet a reward. s^ill it was to bc a rcward. It was not a
favour to be conferred in defiance of the
relations that naturally subsisted betwixt God and His
creature. Man was not to be arbitrarily promoted. His
dignity was to come as the fruit of his obedience. It was
much more than he deserved, much more than he could de-
serve. But in the plenitude of His own bounty, God pro-
posed to add this boon of adoption over and above all that
man was entitled to receive for his service if he should prove
faithful to his trust. The purpose, therefore, to adopt the
servant into the family and make him an heir, introduces an
imiiortant modification of tlie oeneral prin-
Probation limited as ■'^ ox
to time, and thus jus- ciplcs of uioral government in the limita-
tification introduced. . />,i -ip ^ j • 1j1'
tion 01 the period ot probation, and tins
limitation introduces a new feature in the Divine economy,
even that of justification. Under the original relations of
man to God, his probation was coextensive with his immor-
tality, and perpetual innocence was his only righteousness,
and was only a security of perpetual favour. No jxist obe-
dience could exempt from the jiossibility of a future fall.
Man's condition was necessarily precarious. To limit pro-
bation is to make a temporary obedience cover the whole
compass of immortality, to make it equivalent to what per-
petual innocence would have been, and thus, from the nature
of the case, render apostasy after the limitation had ex^^ired
Lect. XII.] THE COVENANT OF WORKS. 267
impossible. The veiy essence of justification is to produce
as its eifect indefectibility of holiness. If God chooses to
gather our whole being into a short probation, and to make
the obedience of that period equivalent to an immortality
spent as faithful servants, the supposition that after the
period was passed we could sin involves the monstrous idea
that there can be a perpetual right to God's favour on the
part of those who are destitute of His love — that men can
be at one and the same time the objects of the Divine com-
placency and disgust. The essential notion of justification
is, that obedience for a limited time shall place the subject
beyond the possibility of guilt. If he is faithful during the
stipulated period, he is safe for ever, he is confirmed immu-
tably in life. That this must be the case results from another
consideration. If God treats limited as perpetual obedience,
he must make limited secure perpetual obedience. Other-
wise His judgment will not be according to truth. Adop-
tion is grounded in justification. The state of a son in
which man is placed in such relations to God as to secure
him from the possibility of defection is founded upon that
limitation of obedience which gathers up the whole immor-
tality in its probationary character into a brief compass, and
then makes its real complexion depend upon the fidelity or
infidelity displayed in the trial. Adoption, in other words,
depends upon justification, and justification is unintelligible
without the contraction of the period of trial. The very
moment trial ceases the attitude of a servant ceases, a new
relation must necessarily supervene ; and God has consti-
tuted that new relation according to the riches of His grace.
These modifications of moral government are the offspring
of the Divine will. They do not flow from any necessary
principles of His nature or His government. They are the
Free acts of Gods ^cc acts of His bouuty. Heucc, the dis-
bounty, and matters pcnsatiou of rcligiou wliich thcy superin-
of pui-e revelation. . - „ .
duce must be a matter of pure revelation.
Adam could not have dreamed of it without special com-
munication with God. He never was, unless for a very
268 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lect. XII.
short time, under a mere system of natural religion. He
M'as placed at the beginning of his career under an economy
whicli looked far beyond the provisions of mere nature, and
at the very outset of his career was made the subject of
special Divine revelations.
This is a very important and a very striking thought.
Man's religion must ^au's rcligiou has always been conditioned
always be a revealed \,y revclatiou. That is uot a peculiarity
of the Christian system. It marks all
God's dealings with the race. The reason is obvious : His
goodness has always been greater than our deserts. Our
moral nature is adjusted to a scheme of pure justice, and
wdienever God's love prompts Him to outrun its demands,
our expectations must be determined by special revelation
of His purposes and plans. His free acts cannot be antici-
pated by any measure of reason or conscience. If known
at all, they have to be made known by Himself. To deny,
therefore, that our religion must be revealed, is to say that
God can never do more than our merits can exact ; it is to
limit and contract His goodness. Let His love be infinite,
and it is morally certain that He will entertain purposes
which we could not conjecture, and which He must impart
to us. The same love that transcends justice in the purj^ose
will transcend nature in the knowledge. What prompts
Him to do more than nature calls for, will prompt Him to
teach more than nature can discover. Hence, the religion
of Adam was really a revealed religion ; it was conditioned
by a dispensation introducing important modifications into
the general principles of moral government, the nature of
which, as purposes of the Divine mind, could not be ascer-
tained apart from His making of them known.
This dispensation is known as the Covenant of Works.
This covenant is a scheme for the justifica-
The Covenant of,. llj.' r l • ill
Works definid. ^^^^^ ^^^^'^ acloptiou ot uiau, aucl IS callccl a
coi'cnuni because tlie promise was suspended
upon a condition with which man was freely to comply. It
was not a covenant in the sense that man was at liberty to
Lect. XII.] THE COVENANT OF WORKS. ^ 2G9
decline its terms. He was under obligation to accept as a
servant whatever God might choose to propose. He had no
stipulations to make ; he was simply to receive what God
enjoined. It is also implied in the use of the word covenant
that the faith of God was pledged in case the condition were
fulfilled. Nothing sets in a stronger light the kindness and
condescension which have signalized all the dealings of the
Most High with our race than that the very first dispensa-
tion of religion under which man, still a servant, was placed
— than that the very words by which it is described should
seem to savour of a treaty u\ which parties met and stipulated.
And some have pushed the words so far as really to repre-
sent man as treating upon something of a footing of equality
with God. All such inferences should be carefully avoided.
The covenant was essentially a conditioned
The two essential • l • l • xl • /■ i •
tjjjy promise, winch man, ni the exercise oi his
own free-will, might secure or forfeit. The
essential things, therefore, in it are the condition and the
promise.
Before proceeding, however, to consider these, it is well to
notice another modification of moral govern-
Limitationof prolia- ,i • -i .i i. •,,• />,i • -i n
tiou as to the persons, ^cut bcsidcs thc limitation of the period of
probation introduced into this economy ;
and that is, the limitation as to the persons put on trial.
We have seen that simple justice deals with men as individ-
uals. Each man stands or falls accordinp- to his own inteo--
o o
rity. But in the covenant of works one stood for all.
Adam represented all that were to be descended from him
by ordinary generation. They were tried in him. Had he
stood, they would have been justified through his righteous-
ness, and adopted into God's family as sons. As he sinned,
they sinned in him and fell with him in his first transgression,
and thus became outcasts and aliens. The provision by
which Adam was made a public person, and
A provision of pure .. , -i •j.-T'Ii-
goodness. ^^^t treated as a private individual, is as
much a provision of pure goodness as any
other provision of the whole scheme. If he had maintained
270 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lect. XII.
his integrity, and avc had inherited life and glory through
his obedienee, none would ever have dreamed that there was
aught of hardship or cruelty in the scheme by which our
happiness had been to us so cheaply secured. The difference
of result makes no difference in the nature of the principle.
But those who object do not bear in mind that the hnv which
made Adam our head and representative is the law by virtue
of which alone, so far as we know, the happiness of any man
can be secured. Without the principle of representation it
is possible that the whole race might have perished and
perished for ever. Each man, as the species successively
came into existence, would have been placed under the law
of distributive justice. His safety, therefore, would have
been for ever contingent. It is possible that if the first man,
with all his advantages, abused his liberty and fell, each of
his descendants might imitate his example and fall also. It
is possible, therefore, that the whole race might have been
involved in guilt and ruin. Some might have stood longer
than others, but what is any measure of time to immortality?
Who shall say that, in the boundless progress of their
immortal being, one by one, all may not have sinned ? It
is certainly possible and probable that this would have been
the ease. It is certain that nniltitudes would have abused
their freedom and perished. But to sin under such circum-
stances is to sin hopelessly. There can be no redeemer if
each man is to be treated exclusively as an individual. If
we cannot sin in another, we cannot be re-
No salvation witli- i i i .i ^r- .1 • • i /•
out representation. dccmcd by auothcr. U tlic principle of
representation is to be excluded from God's
government, salvation to the guilty must also be excluded.
Under this princi])le multitudes are in fact saved, when with-
out it all might have been lost. Hence, it is clearly a pro-
vision of grace — it was introduced for our good ; for our
safety, our happiness, and not as a snare or a eui'se. God
seems to have had an eye to it when He constituted our
species a race connected by unity of blood, and not a collec-
tion of individuals belonging to the same class, simply be-
Lect. xii.] the covenant of works. 271
cause they possess the same logical properties. He made
Adam the root, because He designed to make
s^Zt:tT- hnn the head; the father, because He de-
signed to make him the representative of all
mankind. The generic constitution evidently looks to the
federal relation. We are one by birth, because we were des-
tined to be one by covenant. In all the instances in which
God has appointed that one should federally represent others,
there has been some natural tie — especially the tie of blood
— between the head and the members. There is no case in
which the appointment has been arbitrary. It is always the
parent who stands for his children ; the king who stands for
his subjects. There is, therefore, a significancy in this pecu-
liarity of our species. The angels have no blood connection,
and, so far as we know, the principle of representation has no
place in the Divine economy with reference to them. We
are not competent to say that a logical unity of species, even
where there is no tie of race, may not be an adequate foun-
dation for federal headship ; we cannot say that the govern-
ment of God over angels must necessarily have contemplated
them exclusively as individuals, because they are not de-
scended one from another, and have not the unity of a com-
mon stock. We do not know sufficiently the essential
grounds and conditions of the representative relation to pro-
nounce dogmatically that it can never be instituted, where
the same circumstances do not obtain whicli are found in
the case of man. It may be that a common blood is indis-
pensable— that there is something in this natural unity which
so identifies the moral interests of the race as to render it
extremely proper that the branches should be determined by
the root, the destiny of the children by the fortunes of the
father. This may be so, but we have no positive data for
saying that it must be so. All we know is, that natural de-
scent determines representation in reference to man — that
our being one blood is the ground of our being treated as
one man, in the person of our first father. He represented
all who descend from him by the ordinary law of the propa-
272 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lect. XII.
gation of the species. He was the whole of his posterity
inchulcd in his loins, who would have been introduced into
the world in the ordinary way had not sin entered. An
extraordinary descendant, introduced into the world apart
from that law, and forming no part of the race according to
its original destination, would not be represented. He was
not in the root ; he was not i)roperly in the loins of Adam ;
he was not one who would have been born if the species had
followed its normal development. Hence, representation is
confined to the descendants who spring from Adam according
to the established law of propagation ; and these sustain to
him the double relation of children to a parent, and of mem-
bers to a covenant head. He stood for them in the first dis-
pensation of religion. They were tried in his person. The
whole species was considered as contained in him. He was
not only a man, but Man, and the state in which they find
themselves must be traced directly to his disastrous agency.
The natural tie is the ground of the federal tie ; we were
represented by our father because we were really and truly
in the loins of our father. This modification of the principles
of moral government, by which all were included in one and
probation limited to a single individual, is no less remark-
able than that which concentres an immortality of trial Into
the space of a brief period. The ruling
Representation of j j^-^j^ induCcd thc modification WaS
grace.
grace ; and however the principle has been
perverted by man, and made the instrument of Involving
the race In ruin, it has been revealed in Its real significancy
by God, who has made it the Instrument of peopling heaven
with innumerable myriads of souls who might have been
hopelessly lost had not His government over us admitted
the possibility of laying help upon One who was mighty and
able to save. In redemption, God illustrated It according
to its true scope and in its genuine spirit. It was engrafted
upon the economy of man's religion, that men might speedily
achieve a destiny of incalculable glory, or, failing in the trial,
might yet be rescued from complete and universal perdition.
Lect. xil] the covenant of works. 273
It must not be forgotten that although blood, or anity of
race, is the ground of federal representation, yet federal rep-
resentation is the ground of either benefit or injury from the
success or failure of our head. Had Adam stood, we should
all have been justified and confirmed in glory by the impu-
tation of his obedience; that imputation
Imputation proceeds ill 11* Tj_i
from the federal tie, ^ould havc procccdcd immediately upon
the federal and not upon the natural unity.
Had not Adam been appointed to represent us, the mere cir-
cumstance that he was our first parent would not have in-
volved us in the legal consequences of his sin, nor would it
have entitled us to the legal rewards of his righteousness.
His fall is ours, because in the covenant we were included
in him. Without this federal relation we should have been
born in the same relations to God in which he was created.
His character would have affected us only in the way of ex-
ample, education and influence ; but not in the way of im-
putation. It is not by the law of propagation, or the prin-
ciple that like begets like, that we are born sinners. Sin
does not belong to the essence of man — it is a separable acci-
dent ; and as propagation determines the species and not its
accidents, it could never shape our character. Our blood
relation to Adam would only settle the fact that we must be
men, and not beasts or plants ; it would not determine
whether we should be holy or sinful men. That would de-
pend upon the state in which it was fit that God should in-
troduce us into a state of personal probation. That would
be determined by the same law which determined the cha-
racter of Adam when he came from the hands of his Maker
— a law which renders it absolutely necessary that we should
be endowed with all the habits and dispositions that qualify
us for the destiny we are appointed to work out. The
natural tie determines only who are represented ; the federal
tie actually causes them to be represented. We sinned in
Adam, and fell with him in his first transgression, because
the covenant was made with him for us, and not because
we have sprung from his loins. Still, our being sprung
Vol. I.— 18
274 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lkct. XII,
from his loins is the ground of our being represented by
him.
If natural descent regulated the transmission of character,
then no reason can be given why the chil-
and not from the nat- ^ i?'a.lll j.!,!^ ii
^j.^1 dren oi samts should not be born holy.
They are themselves new creatures, and why
are not their descendants born after this type? To say that
they generate as men, and not as saints, is to give up the
question, for to generate simply as man is to generate with-
out character. To say that they must generate according to
their first type as sinners is to give up the question in an-
other form, for the first type of Adam was holiness. Sin
was a superinduced state, and if he had to generate accord-
ing to his first type, all would have been born holy.
These two modifications of moral government — the limit-
ation of probation as to time, and the limitation of proba-
tion as to jjersons, have introduced two
Two all-pervading • • i i • i i t
principles. pmiciples wliich pcrvadc every dispensa-
tion of religion to our race — the princijile
of justification and the principle of imputation. They are
the very key-notes both of the legal and evangelical cove-
nants. Strike them away from the economy of God toward
man, and the whole Bible would be stripped of all its signi-
ficancy. They are principles grounded in grace, sjiringing
from the free and spontaneous goodness of God — purposes of
kindness of which nature and reason gave no prophecy nor
hint, and therefore necessitating that the religion pervaded
and conditioned by them must be supernaturally revealed.
They imply a covenant, and in the very natui*e of the case
a covenant is not an inference of reason.
I. We have already seen that the dispensation of religion,
commonly called the Covenant of Works, as founded in a
goodness and contemplating a reward which nature could
not have anticipated, necessarily implies the
The condition of the • , ,• n -i ,• rn^ !•,•
covenaut positive. intervention of revelation. The condition
of the covenant brings out another pecu-
liarity which is incidental to a revealed system, and which
Lect. XII.] THE COVENANT OP WORKS. 275
is equally removed from the suggestions of human reason.
I allude to the distinction betwixt moral and positive duties.
The prohibition which God gave to the first pair in the gar-
den of Eden was not grounded in essential rectitude, but in
sovereign command. In itself considered, the fruit of the
forbidden tree was no more inconsistent with the image of
God in man than the fruit of any other tree in the garden.
It was a sin to eat of it, not because the thing was inhe-
rently wrong, but because it was expressly forbidden.
The distinction betwixt the two classes of duties has
Butler on the differ- hardly becu rcsolvcd by Bishop Butler
ence betwixt moral -^vith liis usual prccisiou. Hc malvos the
aud i)ositive duties. -\'/>o t • i •
diiierence to Jie in the cn-cumstance that
in the one case we see, and in the other we do not see, the
reason of the command. " Moral precepts," he remarks,
" are precepts the reason of which we see ; positive pre-
cepts are precepts the reasons of which we do not see.
Moral duties arise out of the nature of the case itself prior
to external command. Positive duties do not arise out of
the nature of the case, but from external . command, nor
would they be duties at all were it not for such command
received from Him whose creatures and subjects we are."
And yet Bishop Butler admits that the positive duty, in so
far as it is imposed by an authority which we are morally
bound to obey, is in that respect to be considered as moral.
But that is simply saying that considered as a duty at all it
is moral. We see the only reason which makes it obligatory
upon us, and consequently, according to the distinction in
question, it takes its place among the moral and not among
the positive j)recepts — that is, the distinction annihilates
itself. It admits in one breath that there are duties which
as duties may be regarded as positive, and in the very next
affirms that as duties they are not positive.
The real difference is grounded in the relation of the
thing commanded to the Divine nature.
The real difference. i i •
When the thing commanded springs from
the holiness of God, or the essential rectitude of the Divine
276 THE COVENAXT OF WORKS. [Lect. XII.
Being, the precept is moral ; when the tiling commanded
springs from the free decisions of the Divine will, or the
free determinations of Divine wisdom, the precept is posi-
tive. The moral could not have been otherwise than com-
manded; the positive might not have been commanded.
The moral is eternal and necessary right ; the positive in-
stituted and mutable law. The moral is written upon the
conscience of every responsible being ; the positive is made
known by express revelation. The moral is the image of
God's holiness ; the positive is the offspring of the Divine
will. One is essential ; the other made right. The imme-
diate ground of obligation in respect to both is the same —
the supreme authority of God. The positive, in so far as
the form of duty is concerned, is moral ; in so far as the
matter is concerned it is arbitrary. The moral obligation
in respect to one is as perfect and complete as in respect to
the other. We are as much bound to obey God enjoining
the indifferent, and thus making it cease to be indifferent,
as when He enjoins the eternal rules of rectitude.
In case of a collision between the moral and positive.
Bishop Butler gives the preference to the
Butler on the prefer- i ii-i itijI
ence of the moral. moral, ou a grouud wliich cau hardly stand
examination, to wit : that we can perceive
a "reason for the preference and none against it" — that is,
because in the one case we see the reason of the command,
and in the other we do not. But although we do not see
the reason why the thing is commanded, we do see the rea-
son why it is obligatory. We do not see why God has
selected this rather than any other positive institution, but,
being selected, we do see the reason why Ave are bound to
respect it. The will of God is the highest formal ground
of obligation, and when that will is known to us, nothing
can be added to make the duty more perfect. The posi-
tive, therefore, is as completely binding, creates as com-
plete a moral obligation, as the moral, and hence no reason
for preference can be found in the formal autliority of the
precepts. The true reason is unquestionably the one which
Lect. xil] the covenant of works. 277
he next assigns, " that positive institutions are means to a
moral end, and the end must be acknowledged more excel-
lent than the means." This relation proceeds from the
very nature of the case — the positive, as decrees of wisdom
are subsidiary to the ends of holiness. They are the crea-
tures of a will regulated necessarily by right, and subordi-
nating every contingent determination to essential and eter-
nal good. God's nature determines His will. What, there-
fore, contradicts essential rectitude ceases to be the will
of God. The command foils Avhenever the contradiction
emerges. There is consequently no conflict of duties — the
positive is ipso facto repealed. To assert otherwise is to
assert that God can annihilate the moral; that He can
make virtue to be vice and vice to be virtue, truth to be a
crime and a lie to be duty ; that He can deny Himself.
Under a dispensation which was to try the fidelity of man
Peculiar fitness of ^f ^ scrvaut preparatory to his introduc-
the positive as the tiou iuto a higher statc, there was a pecu-
liar fitness in making the matter of the
trial turn upon positive observances. This species of pre-
cept brings the will of the master to bear distinctly, in its
naked character as will, upon the will of the subject. The
whole issue resolves itself into a question of authority. The
case is simply. Which shall be the supreme, the will of man
or the will of God ? The whole doctrine of sin and holi-
ness in their last determinations is found precisely here.
Sin is essentially selfishness, as we shall see hereafter ; holi-
ness in a creature is the complete submergence of his will in
the will of his Maker. " I have a right to be and do as I
please," is the language of sin. " The will of God should
alone be done," is the language of obedience. The very
core of moral distinctions, the central principle upon which
men are determined to be either sinful or holy, is brought
out into trial under circumstances which make it certain
that it shall be a trial purely without foreign and extra-
neous influences, an unmixed trial of its supremacy in man,
by making the question of his destiny turn immediately upon
278 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lect. XII.
a positive command. The very depths of his moral nature
were sounded and explored in that command. We can con-
ceive of no mode of probation better suited to the end in
view. We have seen already the relation in which the will
must stand to our moral dispositions and habits in order to
make them personal and reflective principles ; to translate
the^n from the sphere of tendencies and instincts into that of
intelligent, conscious, voluntary activity. The end to be at-
tained is that the finite creature shall make God its supreme
end ; the will of God its supreme law ; the glory of God its
highest good. To attain this end the creature must renounce
its own self as a law, and determine its will only by the will
of God. The degree to which it renounces self-will and em-
braces the Divine will determines the degree in which it is
conformed, consciously and reflectively, to the moral law.
If, therefore, the main question is that of the relation of the
finite to the infinite will, it ought to be so stated as to rule
out all secondary and collateral issues. God's will must
come into contact with man's, nakedly and exclusively, as
will. The command must seem to be arbitrary — no reason
in the nature of the thing presented. The case will then
test man's faith in God, and his readiness to follow Him
with implicit confidence, simply and exclusively because He
is God. There is, consequently, the profoundest wisdom in
the Divine dispensation which made the trial of the first
pair turn upon a positive command. It brought their wills
face to face with the will of God ; it asked the question. Who
should reign ? It made no side issues ; it put at once upon
test the fundamental principle upon which alone their native
purity could be made the ingredients — the fixed contents of
their will.
Hence, the tree in relation to which the prohibition was
Why the tree of the givcu, aud which constitutes the expressed
knowledge of good and couditiou of thc covcuaut, is Called The
evil, so called. i' i i 77 r 7 t -i -xt i
tree of the knowledge oj good and evil. JNlan s
conduct in regard to that tree was to determine whether he
should choose the good or the evil ; whether the type of cha-
Lect. XII.] THE COVENANT OF WORKS. 279
racter which he should permanently acquire through the
exercise of his will should be holy or sinful. The know-
ledge spoken of is that practical knowledge which consists in
determinations of the will, and not the speculative appre-
hension or intelligent discernment of moral distinctions.
Man already knew the right and the wrong ; the law of God
was written upon his heart, and the whole constitution of his
nature was in unison with the essential and immutable dis-
tinctions of the true and the good. But as he was mutable,
as that mutability lay in his will, and as his will had to
decide whether he should preserve or lose the image of God
in which he was created, that which was to determine what
his choice should be might well be called his means of
knowing, in the sense of cleaving to or einbracing, good or
evil. The tree was simj)ly the instrument of trying the hu-
man will ; and if, instead of the knowledge of good and
evil, you call it the tree of the choice of good and evil, you
will have what I take to be the precise import of the in-
spired appellation. Knowledge is often put for the practical
determinations of the Avill. Our moral nature is called a
practical understanding, and its decisions may therefore be
properly represented in terms of knowledge.
This explanation is so natural, so obviously in harmony
with the whole design of the prohibition,
This view overturns t i i i i , • , i . i
sundry iiypotheses. ^ud SO Completely accordaut with the usus
loquendi of the Sacred Scriptures, that one
is at a loss to conjecture how commentators could have per-
plexed themselves so grievously as some have done in rela-
tion to tlie nature and functions of the tree. The difficulty
has arisen, in most cases, from not perceiving the fitness of
a positive precept as the immediate matter of man's trial.
Hence, the Mosaic account has appeared unreasonable and
absurd, and various hypotheses have been invented to bring
it within the sphere of our notions of propriety. One finds
in the whole description of the paradisaical state a figure to
illustrate the operations of sense and reason. Another finds
in the nature of the two prominent trees of the garden, and
280 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lect. XII.
the effects of their fruit upon man's physical constitution, the
ground of the prohibition in the one case
The effects of the 1j1 •• -ji ji TjI
fruit not physical. ^ncl the pcrmissiou in the other, and the
origin of their peculiar names. We are
gravely told that the tree of life bore healthful and nutritious
fruit, and Avas specially calculated to immortalize the frame ;
it was a tree of life, because it secured and perpetuated life.
The tree of the knowledge of good and evil, on the other
hand, was " a hurtful, poisonous tree ;" ^ and the prohibition
in regard to it was only a salutary premonition of danger
proceeding from the apprehension of God that Adam, if left
to himself, might poison his system. The import of the
command was simply. Do not poison thyself. It was called
the tree of the knowledge of good and evil, because it Avas a
means of teaching man prudence : " If he ate of the fruit of
the tree, it would be to his hurt ; and by the evil he would
suffer, he would become wise and learn in future to be more
circumspect." Others, again — and in this opinion the Dutch
divines of the Federalist school generally
This tree uot a sa- i j_i • ^ j_ i
crament. concur — regard this tree as a sacramental
symbol. The notion which they mean to
convey may be right enough, but the language is altogether
inappropriate. A sacramental symbol is at once a sign and
a seal. Of what was this tree a sign ? Not of the prohibi-
tion. It was the very matter of the prohibition — the thing
itself, and not a representative. Not of the moral law or
the principle of universal obedience. That whole principle
was involved in the issue of man's conduct in relation to the
tree. It was not a putative, but a real guilt ; not a symbol-
ical, but a real sin that he would commit in eating of the
forbidden fruit. The entire law, in that which determines
its formal character as law or an expression of the Divine
will, was itself broken in the contempt of the Divine autho-
rity, which the eating of the fruit involved. Hence, we can-
not, without a violent catachresis, make that sacramental and
symbolical which signified and scaled nothing but itself.
^ Knapp, i., p. 385.
Lect. XII.] THE COVENANT OF WORKS. 281
The prohibition did not represent, but was itself, the condi-
tion of the first dispensation of religion. What those who
adopt this view mean to condemn by making the tree sym-
bolical is the preposterous notion, fit only for Socinians and
Rationalists, that this tree was the sole condition of the cove-
nant ; so that man might have violated the moral law, and
yet if he abstained from this fruit he could not have been
subject to death : death was an evil specifically annexed to
this prohibition and to nothing else.
It is obvious, however, from what has already been said,
that the positive can neither supersede nor
The positive, how- , , , , _,, ,
ever, cannot supersede repeal tlic moral law. lliat law was writ-
the moral, written up- ^^j-^ ™qj^ ^]-^g }^gj^^,f ^^-^^ Jj.g obligation COuld
on the heart. j- ^ o
no more be revoked than the nature of
man destroyed or the holiness of God expunged. That
law, in the conviction of good and ill desert with which it
was attended in the conscience, contained moreover an ex-
plicit promise to obedience and an explicit threat to disobe-
dience. Hence, there needed no revelation to communicate
in relation to it what man knew already, and knew from the
constitution of his own mind. The only thing in regard to
which supernatural teaching was required was the positive
precept and the penalty under which it was enforced. That
It was added to the ^as placed ou the same footing of author-
morai,aiKi man placed jty with tlic moral law by thc express will
under a twofold law. n r^ -i mi «> r> i •
ot (jrod. ihe eiiect of this revelation was
to make the ^vhole law under which man was placed two-
fold, and to render it necessary that he should obey both in
order that his obedience might be perfect. The positive
was added to the moral, not substituted in the place of it,
and enforced under the same sanction ; and to fail in either
was to fail in both. The import of the positive command
is, that over and above those eternal rules of right which
spring from the necessary relations betwixt God and the
creature, and which were already fully revealed in the very
structure of the moral understanding, there was now im-
posed upon man by external revelation a jjositive prccejit to
282 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lect. XII.
which the same penalty was attached which conscience con-
nected with the moral law. His obligations were enlarged,
and not contracted. This resnlts from the very nature of
the case. Had man sinned by falsehood, malice, cruelty, or
any other breach of the law written upon his heart, the
The question of couscquences would have been the same as
man's allegiance more ^\^qqq ^yhich followed thc Catlug of the for-
speedily and fully de- _ _ . i • n
termiiied through the bidden fruit. But tlic qucstiou of his alle-
^°^'*'^®' giance to God could evidently be brought
more speedily to a crisis by the intervention of a positive
command. The issue would be brought on by the natural
apj)etite and desires of the flesh, and will be arrayed face to
face with will by the collision which harmless lust superin-
duced with command. In this way the question could be
raised in the human soul whether the formal principle of
obligation to the whole moral law should be supremely re-
spected or not. Hence, the positive is all that appears in
the narrative, not because it was all that was real in the
covenant, but because it was all that needed revelation to
teach it, and because it was the only point in relation to
which the question of obedience was likely to come to an
issue ; it was the only point in which a real trial of man's
fidelity was likely to be made. Hence, the condition of the
covenant must not be restricted to the positive command.
It was the whole law under which man
undeTtheTwIoi^'itw.'' was placcd, uioral and positive— the whole
rule of duty, whether internally or exter-
nally made known.
That the moral law was enjoined upon him under the
same sanction as the positive precept we know, not only
from the testimony of conscience, but from the express
teachings of Scripture in other parts of the
t£Zr """""' sacred volume. Paul, in the Epistle to
the Romans, makes the merit of righteous-
ness and the demerit of sin the fundamental doctrine of
moral government. What those gain who perfectly obey is
life ; what those incur Avho disobey is death ; and, what is
Lect. Xir.] THE COVENANT OF WORKS. 283
remarkable, he represents the heathen as knowing that those
who flagrantly transgress the moral law are worthy of death.
The wages of sin, he assures us — and sin is the transgression
of any law of God — the wages of sin is death. The whole
scheme of redemption proceeds upon this postulate. The
law as law, and without reference to the distinction of posi-
tive and moral, is and must be enforced by a penal sanction,
or it degenerates into mere advice. There is another con-
sideration which is decisive, and which I do not remember
ever to have seen presented, and that is
the moral law tho that UulcSS the moral law, through the con-
positive precept couW viction of good and ill desert, had con-
have had no forco. " _ ■'
nected favour with obedience, and death
with disobedience, the sanction of the positive precept must
have been wholly unintelligible. It could not have been a
moral motive. It could only have addressed itself to our
hopes and fears, and operated upon us as caresses and kicks
operate uj)on a brute. But the feeling that he who dis-
obeyed ought to die, that there was a ground in justice and
in right for his being accursed, could not have arisen un-
less there were previously in the soul the formal notion of
justice. Moral obligation, as contradistinguished from mere
inducement, could not have been conceived. But given the
primitive cognition of justice, and of moral obligation as
involving the notion of merit and demerit, and then the
case is plain. The will of God creates the j^ositive duty ;
that will lays a moral ground for obedience ; transgression,
therefore, becomes morally a crime, and the conscience nat-
urally connects it with death as its just and righteous retri-
bution. Hence, the obligation and authority of the moral
law are presupposed in order that the obligation and author-
ity of the positive might be understood. Man cannot be
dealt with as a moral being by positive precepts without
taking for granted the presence and power of these primi-
tive cognitions, upon which the very essence of the moral
depends.
The importance of accurate notions in relation to what
284 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lect. XII.
was the condition of the Covenant of Works depends upon this,
that our opinions on this point materially
Importance of this t/i .• • ji • •
discussiuu. moclity our notions concerning tlie primi-
tive condition of man. If the positive pre-
cept were the sole condition of the threatening, then either —
(1) we must suppose that man was in a state of comparative
infancy, and that God was leading him by a process of sen-
sible discipline to the expansion and growth of his moral
and intellectual nature — was training him, as a father trains
a child, to just notions of truth and virtue, and with conde-
scending kindness accommodated his instructions, in the
selection of striking analogies from the sphere of sense, to
his tender capacities ; which is to deny that man was under
a moral government in its Srtrict and proper acceptation,
because that supposes that he is fully competent to obey,
that he has all the necessary furniture of knowledge, habits
and strength which the law presupposes, and that he appre-
hends thoroughly his true posture and relations — or, (2) we
must assume with Warburton that death was not so much a
penalty as a failure to attain a supernatural good, and that
the only effect of disobedience was to remand him to his
original condition. All such incongruities are completely
obviated by the explanation which has been given. The
tree was a test of man's obedience ; it concentrated his pro-
bation upon a single point, and implicitly contained the
whole moral law.
II. The next and most important point is the promise
which was to crown the successful trial of
covetr"'"°'"" the pair. Everything depends upon the
nature of that promise. If it Avere nothing
more, as some have maintained from the silence of the his-
torian, than the general expectation of impunity, and of the
continuance of his present state of favour during the period
of his innocence, man certainly gained nothing by his transfer
to the garden of Eden but the enlargement of his duties by
the addition of a positive command. The dispensation was
one of restraint rather than of liberty ; an abridgment of his
Lect. XII.] THE COVENANT OF WORKS. 285
privileges rather than the concession of new advantages. It
is true that Moses says nothing directly of
direcuyr^-cungif » promisc ; he givcs no intimation of the
nature of the reward which was proposed
to fidelity, nor does he even affirm that one was proposed ;
but the whole tenor of the narrative bears upon its face
that God was meditating the good of his creature; and that
the restrictions which he imposed looked to blessings of
which these restrictions were a very cheap condition. There
was not only, in no proper sense, a covenant, but there was
no modification of the period of trial involved in the notion
of moral government — there was no limitation to the extent
of man's probation — unless there was some special promise
annexed to the peculiarities of his present circumstances. It
does not follow, moreover, that because the promise is not
recorded in the brief history of the transaction, therefore the
promise did not exist. It may be implied from the nature
of the case, or it may be articulately stated in other portions
of the sacred volume. The omission here may be supplied
by other texts, and by what we are taught concerning the
import of the Divine dispensations toward man. Unless
The scripturea must ^^^ Scripturcs directly or indirectly autlien-
arbitiate, and they do ticatc a promisc, wc are not to presume
teach us ou this sub-
ject, both iiKiirectiy that a promisc was made. What is not
and positively. Contained in positive declarations, or de-
duced by necessary inference, we are not to receive as the
word of God. Now I maintain that the Scriptures, indi-
rectly, teach us that there must have been a promise, and
positively declare what the promise was. I am willing to
admit that nothing can be inferred from the threatening.
We cannot deduce one contrary from another. The sole
promise involved in a threat is impunity as long as the
threatening is respected.
1. But it is morally certain that a peculiar promise of
some sort must have been given, dependent upon a limited
obedience, from the circumstance that Adam was made the
representative of the race. He could not have been treated
286 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lect. XII.
as a public person and yet placed under the law of perpetual
, innocence. To supi)Ose this were to sup-
The promise argued i i i
from Adam's headship, posc the moustrous auomaly that his
descendants might have successively come
into being, and yet without being justified have been exempt
from the possibility of sin, or in case of sin have been ex-
empt from the penalty of transgression. If there were no
limit to his probation, he could never be justified ; they,
therefore, could never be justified through him. The moral
condition of both would be contingent and precarious. But
as they were on trial only in him, they must be either pre-
served from sin by special grace, or in case of sin be pre-
served from the imputation of guilt. That moral agents
should exist in circumstances of this sort is utterly prepos-
terous.^ Hence, the constitution which made Adam a rep-
resentative, and which put the race on trial in him, contains
on the face of it a limitation of probation. There was a
period when the scene should be closed, and when his des-
tiny and that of his descendants should be determined either
for sin or holiness. Before they were born it was to be set-
tled, and settled by him, under what law they should be born,
whether that of righteousness or death. Every passage of
Scripture which teaches that Adam was a
fureT"* " "'' ''"'" P^^blic person, and that his posterity sinned
in him and fell with him in his first trans-
gression, teaches by necessary implication that the probation
was designed to be definite, and that there was the same op-
portunity of securing justification as of incurring condemna-
tion. There is a beautiful harmony in the whole scheme
of God, and, whether in nature or in grace, you cannot strike
out a part without destroying the symmetry of the whole.
I cannot forbear to notice, too, that those who account for
the propagation of sin ui)on the law of generation alone
cannot upon their theory infer any provision for justifica-
tion in the Adamic economy from the universal prevalence
of sin and death. If men are not condemned in Adam,
1 See Eldgely, vol. i., p. 317.
Lect. XII.] THE COVENANT OF WORKS. 287
but only inlierit liis nature by the law of descent, tliere is
no reason to postulate a constitution in which they might
have been justified through him, and there is no reason to
infer that he or any of his race had in his state of innocence
the prospect of ever being confirmed in holiness. But upon
the hypothesis of representation the possibility of justifica-
tion is an inevitable inference.
2. It is besides expressly declared that the law was
ordained unto life. Obedience is through-
More Scripture teach- jji O'j • T iii
i„gg out the bcnptures as indissolubly associ-
ated with life as disobedience is associated
with death. " If thou wilt enter into life, keep the com-
mandments."^ "Who will render to every man according
to his deeds ; to them who by patient continuance in well-
doing seek for glory and honour and immortality, eternal
life." ^ This passage is decisive, as its design is evidently to
show the nature of the disj^ensation under which man was
placed in innocency as preparatory to a just apprehension of
the provisions of the Gospel. The promise of eternal life
is no part of the law as such ; it is peculiar to it by virtue
of the limited probation upon which man was placed. The
law of creation was life during the j)eriod of obedience, and
eternal life could only be the reward of eternal obedience.
But the law as modified by grace was patient continuance in
well-doing for a season, and then everlasting security and
bliss. This was the law under which all men were placed
in Adam ; this the promise explicitly announced to them as
the incentive to fidelity. " And the commandment which
was ordained to life I found to be unto death."' "For
what the law could not do, in that it Avas weak through the
flesh, God sending his own Son in the likeness of sinful
flesh, and for sin, condemned sin in the flesh, that the right-
eousness of the law might be fulfilled in us who walk not
after the flesh, but after the Spirit."^ This passage teaches
unequivocally that the law proposed a scheme of justifica-
1 Matt. xix. 17. 2 Eom. ii. 6, 7.
* Kom. vii. 10. * Kom. viii. 3, 4.
•288 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lect. XII.
tion — a scheme by virtue of which men could be reputed not
merely innocent, but righteous, and that the reason why
eternal life has not been secured by it is not the inadequacy
of its own promise, but the failure of man to comply with
the condition. No candid mind can weigh these texts with-
out being impressed with the conviction that Paul views
man as having been placed in a state in which he might
have secured everlasting life by a temporary obedience.
The law contemplated man as under a promise, to which the
preservation of his innocence for a given period would have
entitled him ; and this j^romise necessarily implies the possi-
bility of justification. Hence, we are fully warranted, not-
withstanding the silence of Moses, in saying that the essen-
tial principles of moral government were so modified by the
goodness of God as to render it possible for man to pass from
a servant to a son, from labour to an indefectible inheritance.
3. But the text last quoted gives us a third argument,
which is even more conclusive still ; and tliat is, that the
work of redemption has only achieved for us the same
blessings — the same in kind, however they may differ in
degree — which the law previously proposed as the reward of
obedience. Christ has done for us what the law was ordained
Thepromisetbrough ^0 do, but failed to do ouly through the
Christ the same with fiiult of uiau. Whatcvcr, therefore, Christ
the promise to Adam. , i i a i • i i • i
has purchased, Aclam might have gamed.
The life which Christ bestows was in the reach of Adam ;
the glory which Christ imparts was accessible to our first
head and representative. AVhatever Christ has procured for
us, he has procured under the provisions of the law which
conditioned human religion in Eden. The principles of the
dispensation then and there enacted have not been changed;
they have only been carried out and fulfilled. From the
nature of the dispensation under which the second Adam
was placed, we may learn that which pertained to the first;
and the result of the comparison will be the confirmation of
every doctrine we have stated in relation to our first father's
posture. First, Christ was a public person ; so was Adam.
Lect. XII.] THE COVENANT OF WORKS. 289
Each represented his seed. Secondly, Christ's probation was
limited ; it was confined to the period of his humiliation.
Adam's, to preserve the analogy, must have been limited
also. Thirdly, Christ had the promise of justification to
life as the reward of his temporary obedience ; the same
must have been the case with Adam. Hence, through the
work of Christ, and the relations of that work to the law,
we are explicitly taught that eternal life was, and must have
been, the promise of the Covenant of Works.
4. As the promise through Christ is essentially the same
as the promise to Adam, we are prepared, in the next place,
to consider what the life is that was promised. The term in
Scripture not only indicates existence, but
The life promised i.i i. i} ^^ ^ ' 'j_ ' • j.
was eternal. ^Iso the property of well-bemg ; it is exist-
ence in a state of happiness. Eternal life
is the same as eternal well-being or happiness. As long as
man's happiness was contingent, he was not in a state of
life, in that high and emphatic sense which redemption se-
cures. Innocence is the condition of life, but it is not life
itself. There are two things which belong to life. First,
It implies a change of inward state or character. Secondly,
A change of outward state or relation. In relation to Adam,
the inward change would have consisted in removing the
mutability of his will. If he had kept the law, he would
have been rendered indefectible in holiness by an influence
of Divine grace moulding his habits so completely into his
will that he never could have departed from the good
pleasure of God, He would have attained, by the blessing
of God, in the way of reward to his obedience, that moral
necessity which is the noblest freedom and which constitutes
the highest perfection of a rational creature. His security
would not have been the result of habit. No course of obe-
dience, however protracted and however it might be con-
stantly diminishing the danger of transgression, would ever
have rendered man invulnerable to sin. The mortal point,
like the heel of Achilles, would always be found in muta-
bility of will. A probationary state necessarily implies the
Vol. I.— 19
290 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lpxt. XIT,
possibility of defection anJ the relations of the will to the
law in such a state are essentially different from its relations
in a state of justification. This great benefit, therefore, a
will immutably determined to the good, would have charac-
terized the life of the first man if he had been faithful to his
trust.
The second element is a change of relation. He would
have been adopted as a son, and no longer under the law as
a servant. Whatever of joy, privilege, blessedness and glory
are implied in this relation was held out to Adam as a mo-
tive to fidelity. Confirmed in holiness ; admitted into the
closest communion with God ; treated as a child ; honoured
as an heir ; what more could God have done for him ? This
was life, eternal life ; and this life in both its elements would
have accrued from his justification. Temporary obedience,
being accepted as perpetual innocence, would have secured
perpetual innocence ; and probation being closed by a full
compliance with the conditions — which is justification — would
have rendered man a fit subject for receiving, as he was able
to bear it, from the infinite fullness of God. To sum up all
in a single word, the promise to Adam was eternal life ; and
eternal life includes the notions of indefectible holiness and
of adoption, w'hicli are inseparably linked together.
From this exposition of the promise we need have no
difficulty as to what the Scriptures teach in relation to the
tree of life. It is very idle to suppose that it received its
title from any property that it had to perpetuate existence
or to prevent the incursion of disease. It
The tree of life -was a i i i • i r* ii
seal of ti.e promise. was merely a symbol or memorial of the
promise — a token to man, constantly re-
minding him through his senses of what great things God
had prepared for him. It is perhaps because this tree was
the exponent of the promise that Moses has not expressly
recorded it. Some have inferred from the precautions taken
to prevent man from eating of its fruit after his defection
that it had some innate virtue to stay the tide of death.
"We should rather infer that these precautions were solemn
Lect. XIL] the covenant of works. 291
signs that he had forfeited all right to the blessing it sym-
bolized. He was not allowed to approach the tree because
he had lost that from which the tree derived its significancy
and importance. To have allowed him to touch the sign
might have been construed into the assumption that he
might yet compass the reality. In conformity with this ex-
planation are all the subsequent allusions in the sacred vol-
ume. " To him that overcometh will I give to eat of the
tree of life which is in the midst of the paradise of God."^
" Blessed are they that do his commandments, that they may
have a right to the tree of life." ^ The tree of life is here
evidently a figure of eternal glory.
I cannot close this consideration of the promise of the
Covenant without calling your attention to the ingenious
and paradoxical theory which Warburton
critidled"^ °" ^ ^"^^'^ ^^^^ P^^^ fortli in liis Divine Legation of
Moses. He admits the distinction which
I have elsewhere drawn between man's natural state under
moral government and the supernatural state in which he
was placed in the garden. He lays down the essential prin-
ciples of moral government with sufficient accuracy, except
that he represents repentance as a natural atonement for our
violations of the moral law. But he errs grievously in the
low estimate which he puts upon the character and qualifi-
cations of man in his primitive condition. He degrades the
image of God to the mere possession of the attribute of rea-
son, and contends that immortality is no part of our native
inheritance. Man was when he came from the hands of
God a subject of law, and rewardable and punishable for his
actions ; but rewards and punishments were equally tempo-
rary. Nature contained no hope of immortality. The
design of the revealed dispensation was to give man the
prospect of endless existence, to exempt him from the pos-
sibility of death. As immortality was a free gift, it was fit
that it should be suspended upon an arbitrary condition.
Man's disobedience only remanded him to his original con-
1 Eev. ii. 7. ^ Kev. xxii. 14.
292 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lect. XII.
dition of mortality. He had forfeited his being. He was
put back where he was before, under a pure system of moral
government. Christ restored to us what we lost in Adam,
mere immortality. His sacrifice was an arbitrary appoint-
ment by which God was pleased to communicate the gift a
second time, and faith in Him is an arbitrary condition on
which the possession is suspended to us. The peculiarity
of this theory is, that the supernatural does not modify the
natural, but is co-ordinate with it. Moral government goes
on as it would go on without the supernatural ; the super-
natural is only an expedient by which the subject of this
government is rendered immortal. Of course, after wliat
has already been said, it would be worse than idle to attempt
an articulate refutation of a scheme which only excites your
wonder that a man of genius and learning should have
adopted it, elaborately expounded it and persuaded himself,
and tried to persuade his readers, that he had found the key
to unlock all the mysteries of Christianity. Paradox was
the bane of Warburton's life. But he occasionally devel-
ops principles which throw light upon the dispensations
of God. Unfortunately, he develops them only to mis-
apply them.
III. The last thing to be considered in relation to the
Covenant of Works is the penalty annexed
obedieifco'!'^ ^ ° '^' 'to disobedieucc. That is contained in the
threatening, " in the day thou eatest thereof,
thou shalt surely die." What was really the death that was
denounced has been a question variously answered, according
to the views entertained by different expositors of the artic-
ulate doctrines of the Gospel with respect to sin and redemp-
tion. The type of a man's theological opinions can be readily
determined by the estimate which he puts upon the judicial
consequences of the first sin. Warburton makes the death
of the covenant to be nothing more than
Warburton's theory. ■,...■,
the remanding of man to his original con-
dition of mortality. He was created subject to the law of
dissolution. His existence was destined under the appoint-
Lect. XII.] THE COVENANT OF WORKS. 293
ment of nature to a total extinction. The covenant proposed
to exalt him to a state of immortality. Had he kept the
injunction to abstain from the forbidden fruit, he would
have been endowed with the prerogative of an endless exist-
ence. His failure only placed him where he was before.
There was properly neither fall nor apostasy; there was
simply the missing of a proffered boon. Others, again,
anxious to evade the proof of original sin
derived from the sufferings and death of
infants, exclude the dissolution of the body and temporal
diseases from the death of the covenant. These they make
the original appointments of nature, and not the penal visit-
ations of transgression. They suppose that men would have
suffered and died whether they had sinned or not. Others,
again, anxious to mitigate the malio-nitv of
still anotber. . i ^ • i i n • n ^
Sin, and to do away with the doctrine of the
endless punishment of the wicked, have resolved the whole
punishment of man into the death of the body and the evils
which precede and accompany it. In all these cases it is
clear that theologio prejudice is the real father of the different
theories advanced, and that none of them are drawn from a
candid and disjiassionate comparison of the teachings of the
word of God. Men have put their opinions into the Bible,
and have not extracted their doctrines from it ; they have
made rather than interpreted Scripture. The truth upon
this subject cannot be reached by the dissection of words and
phrases. Scripture must be compared with Scripture, and
the whole tenor of revelation in relation to sin and redemp-
tion must be caipfully studied, in order that any just concep-
tion may be formed of the real significancy of that portentous
word, death. The result of such an examination will be,
that it is a generic term expressing the idea
The true view of the n • -ji j_ ^ j^ -^ /•
p^.jjj^uy of misery, without respect to its form or
kind, judicially inflicted. Any and every
pain, considered as a penal visitation, is death. As life is
not simply existence, but well-being, so death, its opposite,
is not the nesration of existence, but the negation of all the
294 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lect. XII.
pleasure of existence. As to live, in Scripture phrase, is to
be happy, so to die is to be miserable. But is all misery or all
pain penal in its origin ? If so, the question as to the ex-
tent of the penalty can be easily settled. Now, I maintain
that under a just and righteous government there can be no
suffering without guilt. The innocent are entitled to the
Divine favour, and to the bliss which results from it, as long
as they maintain their integrity. Those who most strenu-
ously deny that the creature, in any strict and proper sense,
can merit, yet as strenuously maintain that it is inconsistent
with justice to visit the sinless with pain. If they have no
right to a reward over and above the pleasure of existence
in the state in which they were created, the equity of God
forbids that a being given in goodness should be made a
burden. The form in which the notion of justice is first
manifested in the conscience is through the conviction of
good and ill desert, connecting well-being with well-doing,
and misery with guilt. A discipline of virtue through evil
suj)poses a dispensation of grace in consequence of which sin
has been pardoned, and offences come to be considered as
faults to be corrected, and not as crimes to be punished ; it
supposes at the same time the presence of evil as of a thing
to be removed and abolished. Moral discipline, in this as-
pect, is possible only to pardoned sinners. But a discipline
through evil where no sin has entered, a discipline through
suffering where there has been no crime to be corrected, is
contradictory to every just notion of righteous retribution.
Hence, we have no hesitation in saying that all misery, all
pain, all suffering, all that interferes with the comfort and
satisfaction of existence, all that is contradictory to well-
being, is penal in its origin. Not a pang would ever have
been felt, not a sigh would ever have been heaved, not a
groan would ever have been uttered, not a tear would ever
have been shed, if sin had not invaded the race. All phy-
sical evil is penal ; all misery is penal ; all
It includes all pain. . . ^ . . . ,
pain IS death. Hence, to niquire into the
extent of the penalty is simply to inquire into the extent of
Lect. XII.] THE COVENANT OF WORKS. 295
the miseiy to which man has rendered himself subject by
his apostasy from God. As lie would have been free from
all evil by the preservation of his integrity, so every calamity
that he experiences must be referred, for its ultimate ground,
to the guilt of the first sin. The condition in which he now
finds himself is the condition to which his sin reduced him,
and in this condition we read the true interjiretation of the
threat, " In the day thou eatest thereof, thou shalt surely
die." What man became that day, or the change which
took place in his state and prospects, is the death that was
denounced.
1. There was a change in the habits and dispositions of
his soul. He lost the image of God. His
Death spiritual.
nature took the type of the evil that he
chose. His character became permanently and hoj^elessly
corrupt. The very point to be settled by his probation was
the fixed impression of his moral character. To choose the
good was to become immutably holy and happy ; to choose
the evil was to become hopelessly corrupt and miserable.
The bondage of sin was the necessary consequence of the
choice of sin. He at once lost all power to will or to choose
what was acceptable to God. This loss of the image of
God, or of the principle of holiness, is commonly styled
spiritual death, as being the death of the soul in respect to
what truly constitutes its life. It has been made a question
how Adam could all at once have been deprived of those
spiritual perceptions and concreated propensities to good
which he inherited as the birth-right of his being. It has
been asked how a single sin could all at once have depraved
the entire constitution and perverted the whole current of
his nature. If we were left to conjecture and speculation,
we might suppose that as a habit is not likely to be formed
from a single act, the principle of rectitude would still re-
main, though weakened in its power, and by vigorous and
systematic efforts might recover from the shock which to
some extent had disordered the moral constitution. Bishop
Butler speaks with hesitation in relation to the degree of
296 THE COVENANT OP WORKS. [Lect. XII.
injury wlilcli might be expected to accrue from the first full
overt act of irregularity, though he has no backwai'dness iu
regard to the natural results of a confirmed habit. Each
sin has not only a tendency to propagate itself, but to de-
range the order of the moral constitution ; but as the propa-
gation of itself in the formation of specific habits is ob-
viously gradual, it would seem that the general derange-
ment would also be progressive. The difficulty is created
by overlooking the circumstance of a judicial condemnation,
and not properly discriminating betwixt holiness and moral-
ity. We are to bear in mind that as we are under a penal
sanction as well as possessed of a moral constitution, sin has
judicial consequences which must enter into the estimate of
the extent of injury sustained by the inner man. We must
further recollect that as holiness, which is the foundation of
the virtuous principle, the life of all merely moral habits,
the keystone of the arch which maintains an upright na-
ture in its integrity, consists essentially in union with God,
whatever offends Him must destroy it. This is precisely
what every sin does ; it provokes His curse, breaks the har-
mony of the soul with Him, and removes that which is the
fundamental principle of all true excellence. His moral
habits may remain as tendencies to so many specific forms
of action materially right, but the respect to God has gone.
Spiritual life breathes only in the smile of God ; the mo-
ment that He frowns in anger death invades the soul. It
is the judicial consequence of sin, and hence every sin, like
a puncture of the heart, is fatal to spiritual life. Hence,
the universal dominion of sin is a part of the curse — its
reign is hopeless in so far as human strength is concerned.
One sin entails the everlasting necessity of sin. The law,
as we have seen, knows no repentance.
2. Besides spiritual death, the penalty of the law includes
all those afflictions and sufferings of the
Dentil temporal. i • /. i . i . .
present life which terminate in the disso-
lution of the body. The fatigue and pain connected wdth
labour or the fulfilment of any of our natural functions ;
Lect. XII.] THE COVENANT OF WORKS. 297
the diseases to which we are constantly exposed ; the wear
and tear of our physical frame ; the decrepitude of age ; the
vexations and disappointments of life ; the final separation
of the soul from the body, and the resolution of the body
into its original dust, — all these constitute what divines are
accustomed to denominate temporal death. To this must be
added the disorder which has taken place in external nature ;
the change in the temper and disposition of beasts; the
sterility of the earth ; its poisons ; the deadly exhalations of
the atmosphere, — all things which render the earth disagree-
able and trying as the abode of man are obviously included
in the curse.
3. Then there is a state of suffering, after the close of the
present life, in which first the soul, and
Dentil eternal
afterward both soul and body united, are
the subjects of visitations in which God expresses the in-
tensity of His hatred against sin. This last stage of pun-
ishment is called, pre-eminently-, the second death. The
Scriptures represent it by figures which impress us with an
aAvful idea of its horrors. It is a worm that never dies — a
lake that burns with fire and brimstone. "What the suffer-
ings of the lost actually are we are unable to conceive ; but
we know them to be terrific, because they are designed to
express the infinite opposition of God to sin, and because
they produced the unspeakable tragedy of Calvary. To
which must be added that they are as endless as the exist-
ence of the soul. This death is called eternal death. "When,
therefore, we speak of the penalty of the Covenant, we must
be understood to include the bondage to sin, the subjection
of man to all the evils of this life, and to the still greater
evils of the life to come — the whole of the misery which the
fall has brought upon the race. When it is said that these
evils are the penalty of the Covenant, it is not meant that
they all xesult directly from it, or that they were all visited
upon the person of the first transgressor. Adam did not
suffer every species of pain and calamity to which any of his
descendants have been exposed. But the meaning is, that
298 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lect. XII.
the first sin prepared the way for them all ; it introduced a
state of sin from which has resulted a general state of death.
All the ills that flesh is heir to are either the immediate or
remote consequences of the first transgression. The threat-
ening of death had reference to that whole fallen and miser-
able condition into which the race would be plunged by dis-
obedience.
IV. We have now seen the nature of the dispensation
under which man was placed in the garden of Eden. We
have considered the Condition, the Promise and the Penalty,
and have been struck with the goodness of God in His gra-
cious purpose to exalt the creature to a higher state, and to
make him an inheritor of richer blessings, than his natural
relations would authorize him to expect. He had an easy
work and a great reward. It remains to
Mau's conduct. .-,-,. -• -■ i. iii
consider his conduct under this remarkable
display of Divine benevolence. How long he stood we have
no means of conjecturing — not long enough to be the father
of a son. The circumstances connected with his fall are
briefly narrated by the historian, and the account which we
have may be called. The natural history of sin in relation to
our race.
1. In the first place, it is evident that the record contains
a true history of facts as they occurred, and
Jyl/fZ' '' ' "'" not an allegory setting forth the conflict of
the higher and lower principles of our na-
ture— of reason and sense ; nor yet an apologue, illustrating
the change from primitive simplicity to refinement, luxury
and corruption. The tree of tlie knowledge of good and
evil was adapted to the trial of man's integrity, and is pre-
cisely the kind of test which the nature of the case demanded.
The tree of life was a fit symbol of the promise by which
man was encouraged to obedience, and the threatening must
surely be taken in its literal sense. The narrative, more-
over, contains decisive evidence that sin did not originate
from any collision between appetite and reason ; it originated
Lect. xil] the covenant of works. 299
as inucli in the higher principles themselves as in the lower.
Our first mother Avas prompted by the desire of knowledge;
she saw that the tree was suited to make one Avise, as well as
fair to the eyes and attractive to the taste.
2. In the next place, w^e must recognize, in the serpent,
the presence of an evil spirit who under-
An evil spirit present. , i , , ^o r ± i. o •
took the oince ot a tempter, oin was
already in the universe. That he who is described by the
Saviour as a Liar and a Murderer from the beginning was
the real but disguised agent in the transaction, is obvious
from repeated allusions to the subject by the writers of the
New Testament.^ That this was the opinion of the Jews
before the time of Christ is apparent from the Book of Wis-
dom.^ The promise, too, that the seed of the woman should
bruise the serpent's head, has evidently a much higher sig-
nificaney than any literal application to the serpent-tribe
could give it. An ingenious effort to explain the malice of
the Devil has been given by Kurtz in his Bible and xlstro-
nomy.
3. The sin of man was deliberate. He had the case be-
fore him. It was not an instance of sud-
The sin was deliber- -\ • n •. nr\\ ^ •
^jg den infirmity. ilie case was argued out,
and judgment rendered upon the argument.
4. It involved a deliberate rejection of God as the good
of the soul — a deliberate rejection of the
It was the rejection i o /~i i j i t f ' i
pfQQ(j glory ot (jrod as tlie end ot existence.
Hence, it was unbelief, apostasy, pride.
5. It was a most aggravated sin — aggravated by the re-
lations of the person to God : by the na-
Aggravations of it. n i i •
ture 01 the act ; by its consequences.
V. The relations of man to the covenant since the fall.
1. He is condemned.
Fallen man's rela- rs tx i p /• -i n j1 •
tions to the covenant. 2. He has forfeited the promise.
3. Individually under the general princi-
ples of moral government.
1 See John viii. 44 ; 1 John iii. 8 ; Rev. xii. 9.
2 Chap. i. 13, 14 ; ii. 23, 24.
300 THE COVENANT OF WORKS. [Lect. XIL
THE FIKST SIN.
[There are three points to be considered —
I. What was the formal nature of the sin ?
II. How it was possible that a holy being could sin.
III. The consequences of this sin.
I. "What was the formal nature of the sin ? — that is, what was the root
of it? Was it pride? W\as it unbelief ?
1. It was a complicated sin ; it included in it the spirit of disobedience
to the whole law.
2. It was aggravated — (1) by the person; (2) by his relations to God;
(3) by the nature of the act ; (4) by its consequences.
3. The germ of it was estrangement from God, which is radically un-
belief. It was an apostasy, which in falling away from God set up the
creature as the good.
II. How could a holy being sin ?
1. W^e must not lower the account so as to remove difficulties. Many
make it the growth of an infant to maturity, having its powers quick-
ened by errors and mistakes.
2. Others make it allegorical, representing the conflict of sense and
reason. This is contradicted by the narrative. Intellect is prominent in
the cause of sin. Eve desired wisdom.
3. Others make it an apologue intended to illustrate the change from
primitive simplicity.
4. Others, as Knapp, make the thing venial, but degrade the meaning
to physical phenomena.
5. W^e must regard it as the natural history of sin — the manner in
which it was introduced into our world.
6. It is not enough to say that man was mutable ; that explains the pos-
sibility, but not the immediate cause of sin.
(1.) It was owing to temptation. Here explain the nature of temptation.
(2.) Desires might be excited, in themselves innocent, accidentally
wrong.
(3.) The general principle of virtue — Watch. Here was the first slip.
Desires produced inattention to the circumstances under which they
might be indulged ; here was a renunciation of the supreme authority
of God. Want of thought, want of reflection.
(4.) These desires, by dwelling upon the objects, engross the mind and
become inflamed. They become the good of the soul. Here was the
renunciation of God as the good. They prevail upon the will and the
act is consummated.
III. Consequences — immediate and remote.
1. Shame and remorse.
2. Loss of the image of God. This a penal visitation. Not the mere
force of habit.]
LECTUEE XIII.
ORIGINAL SIN.
IF, as we have previously seen, Adam in the Covenant of
Works was the representative of all his natural pos-
terity— that is, of all contemplated in the original idea of
the race, and descended from him by the ordinary law of
propagation — then the condemnation in which he was in-
volved pertains equally to them, and the subjective condi-
tion of depravity to which he was reduced by his transgres-
The phrase ori^r«aj ^iou must also bc fouud in them. They
Sin as used in its wide must bc at oucc guilty and corrupt. This
state of guilt and corruption, as that in
which they begin their individual personal existence, is by
one class of divines called Original Sin. The phrase in-
cludes both the imputation of the guilt of Adam's first sin,
and the inherent depravity which is consequent ifpon it.
In this wide sense it is probably used by the Westminster
Assembly of divines. The guilt is the
Westminster Assem- iif> • ii'j_j^ij_
biy of divines; Doud ot uuiou Dctwixt the trausgrcssion
of Adam and the moral condition in which
they are born. Others restrict the terms original sin exclu-
sively to the corruption in which men are born, though in
calling it sin they presuppose that it has
sMso '" '*^ ""'"^"'^ been created by guilt. They represent it
as a penal condition, but the j)rominent
idea is the moral features of the condition itself, and not
the cause by which it has been produced.
by Calvin and others. . . ....
There is consequently some ambiguity m
the phrase. The more common usage is unquestionably
301
302 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
that of Calvin, Turrettin and nearly all the Reformed
Confessions in which original sin and native depravity are
synonymous terms. The word was intro-
tnftrtt^rr duced by Augustin in his controversy with
the Pelagians. He wanted a term by
which he could at once represent the moral state, which is
antecedent to all voluntary exercises of the individual, which
conditions their character and determines the whole type of
the spiritual life — that state of sin or pravity in which each
descendant of Adam begins his personal history. He called
this state of native sin, original sin ; first, because our per-
sonal, individual existence begins in it. The species was
created holy in Adam, but since Adam every individual of
the species commences his temporal being in a state of cor-
ruption. Our origin is in sin. In the next place, he called
it original to indicate its close and intimate connection with
the first sin of the first man. Adam's transgression, as the
beginning and cause of all subsequent human aberrations,
was pre-eminently original sin — the original sin — and to
indicate its causal relation to all other sins it was called
peccatum originale originans. The depravity of nature
which resulted from it was called peccatum originale origina-
tum, and when the phrase original sin, without a qualifying
epithet) is used, it indicates the originated sin, and in the
word original points back to the first sin. In the third
place, he used the phrase to indicate that our inborn cor-
ruption was the origin or source of all our actual sins ; it
stood at the head of all the transgressions of our subse-
quent life.
No doubt, the most prominent idea suggested by the
phrase is, that as Adam's transgression stands at the head
of all human sins, begins and conditions the series, so the
In this lecture em- native depravity of each individual stands
ployed in the nar- ^t, the licad of all liis aberrations and de-
rower sense, but the . . , ,^ -i • i i
notion of guilt not ex- temiines the manilestations oi his whole
'''"'''"^" moral life. Adam's sin is absolutely origi-
nal to the species; native depravity relatively original
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN. 303
to each individual of the species. In the sense, then, of
that inherent corruption in which the descendants of Adam
begin their earthly career, I shall employ the term in the
present lecture. Still, the notion must not be lost sight of
that this inherent corruption could not be strictly and prop-
erly sin, unless it were grounded in guilt. If the species
had begun to be in the state in which each individual is
now born, no blame could have been attached to its irregu-
larities and deformity. If the idea of man as it lay in the
Divine mind had included the nature which we now find
cleaving to our being, that nature could not have been
chargeable with aught that deserved censure. Hence, the
notion of guilt underlies all the moral disapprobation which
w^e attach to our present natural condition. It is a penal
state — one into w^iich we have fallen, and not one in which
we were made. The moral history of the individual does
not begin with his own personal manifestation in time ; that
manifestation has evidently been determined by moral rela-
tions to God that have preceded it. Hence, the very term
sin applied to our present state carries with it the idea of
something anterior ; it announces it as an originated and not
The question, how ^s au Original condition. How there can
guilt can precede ex- bc guilt antecedently to the existence of
istence, must be met; i • i- • i i m i • i t
the individual — a guilt, too, which condi-
tions and fixes the very type of that existence — is a question
that must be answered, or it is impossible to vindicate origi-
nal sin in any other sense than that of misfortune or calam-
ity. If it is not grounded in the ill deserts of the creature,
but in the sovereign will and purpose of God, it loses all
moral significancy, and is reduced to the aesthetic category
of beauty and deformity, or the category of mere jihysical
contrasts. The question of guilt, therefore, must meet us
in the discussion of original sin. But as we shall be better
able to encounter it when we shall have
but it is romitted for • t i • i j. i j •
the present. considercd our inherent and native corrup-
tion, we remit the investigation of it to
the close of our present inquiry. It will come in as the
304 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
exjilanation of the state in which we actually find our-
selves to be.
I. Let us, then, take up the question of native depravity.
Original sin, as the What is the statc in which every man is
doctrine was taught boHi ? It is amaziug witli what perfect
by all the Reformers. , „ . ni a r^ o • ii
uniiormity all the early Coniessions, whether
Lutheran or Reformed, represented the teachings of the
word of God upon this subject. There is not a discordant
voice.
1. In the first jjlace, they unanimously represented this
corruption as the very mould of the moral
Sin was the mould i. n 'T'lii^il
of man's moral being, ^euig of cvery mdividual of the species.
It was prior to all voluntary agency; it
was prior to any and every manifestation of consciousness.
While Pelao;ians tauo;ht that the individual was created
without any moral character at all, and that the habits which
he exhibited were the results of his own voluntary acts, the
Reformers, following in the footstej)S of Paul and Augustin,
strenuously maintained that there was a generic and all-
comprehensive disposition which lay behind the will in all
the manifestations of individual life, and determined the di-
rection which it would always take in the great contrasts of
holiness and sin. There was a general habitude which lay
at the root of the will and of our whole spiritual being, and
which determined the general type which every act of choice
must bear. This corruption they represented as a nature in
the sense of an all-conditioning law — a sense which I have
already explained in unfolding the scriptural idea of holi-
ness. So strong was the language of Luther upon this point
that he has trodden closely upon the verge of Manichsean
forms of expression. He speaks of sin as pertaining to the
very substance, the very being, of the soul. He speaks of
it not merely as de natura, but as de essentia hominis, and
calls it peccaium substantiate or essentiale. His design, in
these strong expressions, is to point out the intimate connec-
tion in which sin stands to the very being of the individual.
It is not something Avhich he has acquired — something which
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN. 305
has invaded him in the development of his earthly life. It
is interwoven in the very texture of his soul — began with
the beginning of his faculties, and inseparably cleaves to them
in all their exercises. Sin is the law of his temporal exist-
ence. It is his nature in the same sense in which ferocity
is the nature of the tiger, cunning the nature of the serpent,
and coarseness the nature of the swine. It was an original
principle of motion within him, and not an accidental im-
pulse. When man sins, he expresses his inmost moral being.
He is so bound up in sin, the fibres of his soul are so inter-
tAvined with it, the springs of all his energies are so poisoned
by it, that he could as soon cease to be a man, by any power
in him, as cease to be a sinner. He lives and moves and
thinks and feels in sin. It was precisely in this sense of an
all-conditioning law of the moral life that sin was represented
as the natural state of fallen man, and this representation
contained a protest against every form of error which sought
to explain the irregularities of the individual by causes that
have sprung up since the commencement of his individual
existence. Sin and that existence were synchronous. Sin
was the mould, so to speak, in which the faculties of the soul
were run. The man and the sinner were twins from the
womb, or rather were one.
2. In the next place, this natural depravity was repre-
it was negative- rented in a twofold point of view, negative
destitution of every ^ud positivc. lu a negative aspect, it im-
plied the total destitution of all those habits
and dis^^ositions which constituted the glory of the first man.
and enabled him to reflect the image of God. Every prin-
ciple of holiness was lost. As a nature, it is an all-pervading
habit, and exists as an unit or does not exist at all. It must
be wholly lost or wholly retained. As a life, it either is or
is not. There is no intermediate condition ; a man is either
in life or death. This total destitution of holiness or spirit-
ual life was called a state of spiritual death ; and the Re-
formers, without a single exception, in the first stages of the
Reformation, exhibited the imbecility of man in his natural
Vol. I.— 20
30G ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIIT.
state in relation to anglit that was holy and divine, as abso-
lute and complete. There is no doctrine which they have
more strongly asserted or more vigorously maintained than
the hopeless bondage of the will. However Melancthon
afterwards modified his doctrine, no Reformer ever expressed
the inability of man in more exclusive and uncompromising
terms than himself, in the earlier editions of the symbols
prepared by his hand.
In its positive aspect, natural depravity included a posi-
and rositiv.-an ac- ^^^^c corruptiou ; tliat is, an active disposi-
tive teiukncy to all tiou to what was evil and inconsistent with
the perfections and holiness of God. It
resulted from the nature of man as an active being that if
he wei'c deprived of the principle of holiness, he must mani-
fest the opposite. His actions could not be indifferent ;
they must, as springing from a rational and accountable
being, liave a moral character of some sort, and if holiness
were precluded, nothing but sin remained. Hence, there
was a foundation for every species of evil. Tlic determinate
habits in different individuals might be very different ; some
might manifest a proclivity to one form of sin, and others to
another. One might give himself to low and degrading
lusts, and another might practice a more refined licentious-
ness. Some might become slaves to sense, and others slaves
to the subtler sins of the spirit. Accident and education
might determine the definite bias ; but all, without excep-
tion, would plunge into sin, would contract specific habits of
iniquity, and if left to themselves would steadily wax worse
and worse. A foundation was laid in every human heart
for every form of evil. The poison was there, though it
might ha repressed by circumstances. All the currents of
the human soul were in one general direction ; they were
from God and toward sin. There was not only nothing
good, but there was the germ of all evil ; the tendency was
to universal and complete apostasy.
The negative and positive aspects of original sin are ob-
viously only different sides of the same thing. The priva-
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN. 307
tion of righteousness is, as Calvin lias properly remarked, a
general aptitude for sin. The soul cannot
These but two sides • j_ • i j • i i 'j_ j.
of one thing. cxist lu a merely negative state ; it must
affirm something, and where it is precluded
from affirming God, it must affirm something that is not
God. Where its exercises are not determined by holy love,
they Avill be determined by a love that is not holy.
3. In the next place, natural depravity was represented as
universal and all-pervading. It extended
It was universal and -.i ii 4ni' i
all-pervading. ^^ ^'^^ whojc man. All his powers and
faculties of soul and body were brought
under its influence. It was not confined to one department
of his being — to the will, as contradistinguished from the
understanding, or to the understanding, as contradistin-
guished from the will ; it was not restricted to the lower ap-
petites, as contradistinguished from our higher principles of
action ; nor did it obtain in the heart alone, considered as
the seat of the affi^ctions. On the contrary, it was a disease
from which every organ suffered. As found in the under-
standing, it was called blindness of man, spiritual ignorance,
folly ; as found in the will, it was called rebellion, perverse-
ness, the spirit of disobedience ; as found in the affections, it
manifested itself as hardness of heart, or a total insensibility
to spiritual and Divine attractions. It perverted the imagi-
nation, and turned it into the instrument of lust and the
pander to low" and selfish indulgences. It not only affected
all the faculties, so as to produce a total disqualification for
any holy or spiritual exercise in any form, whether of cog-
nition or of choice, but it crippled and enervated these
faculties in their exercise within the sphere of truth and
morality. They were vitiated in relation to everything that
wore the image of truth, goodness and beauty.
Here a distinction was made. The fall did not divest
man of reason, conscience or taste. This
A distinction made. i i i i i •
would have been to convert him into
another species of being. As reason remained, he still had
the power of distinguishing betwixt truth and falsehood ;
308 ORIGIXAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
conscience still enabled liini to distinffuisli betwixt rio-ht and
wrong, betwixt a duty and a crime ; and taste enabled him
to perceive the contrasts in the sphere of the beautiful. The
extinction of his spiritual life destroyed the unity of action
which pervaded these faculties, and rendered the exercise of
them no longer expressions of holy dependence upon God.
The mere possession of them has no moral value ; it i& the
mode of using them — it is the principle in which their
activity is grounded — that makes them truly good. Now,
with the loss of the image of God, these faculties not only
lost their unity, but lost their original power. They became
diseased ; and hence the reason blunders in the sphere of
truth, the conscience errs in the sphere of right, and taste
stumbles in the sphere of beauty. This distinction Augustin
expressed by saying that the fall had de-
Augustin's language • -t ^ n i i r> j •
criticised. prived us 01 all supernatural perfections
and vitiated those that were natural. The
idea which he intended to convey is just, and has been very
ably elucidated by Calvin, but the phraseology is certainly
objectionable. The image of God in which man was created
was in no proper sense supernatural. On the contrary, as
we have already shown, it was the only condition jn which
it is conceivable that man could have come from the hands
of God. It was, therefore, his natural state. The form of
expression which Augustin ought to have adopted was that
of all holy endowments man was completely dispossessed,
and 4iis natural endowments were grievously injured.
The whole notion of original sin as a subjective state is
conveyed by a phrase w^hich, from the controversy with the
_, , , , , , Remonstrants, has become the o-eneral forra-
The phrase total ae- ' o
praviiy. Three senses ula for tlic cxjircssion of the doctriuc ; that
phrase is iotal depravity. The epithet total
is employed in a double sense — (1.) to indicate the entire
absence of spiritual life, the total destitution of holiness ;
(2.) in the next place, to indicate the extent of depravity in
relation to the constituent elements of the man ; it pervades
his whole being or the totality of his constitution. There
Lect. xiii.] original sin. 309
is still a third sense in which its employment might be
legitimate, as conveying the notion of a positive habitude of
soul in which every form of evil might be grounded — a
tendency to the totality of sin. But the
What it does not mean.
word Mas never used to express the de-
grees of positive wickedness attaching to human nature. It
never was employed to convey the idea that men were as
wicked as they could be, or that there were no differences
of individual character among them. On the contrary, the
most strenuous advocates of total depravity have acknow-
ledged the difference between men and fiends, and betwixt
one man and another in reference to moral conduct. While
they contend that all are equally dead, they are far from
affirming that all are in the same state of putrefaction.
There ts every gradation, from the man of unblemished
honour and integrity to the low and unprincipled knave or
cut-throat. They undertook to explain these varieties in the
moral features of humanity upon principles which would
not conflict with their doctrine of total dej^ravity, show-
ing conclusively that the two things were not, as they could
not have been, with any show of decency, confounded.
4. In the last place, this depravity was represented as
hereditary, as bound up with the law by
It was liereditary. i . , , . . i tvt i
which tlie species is propagated. JNo hu-
man being could escape it who came into the world in the
ordinary way. It was an inheritance which every man
brought with him into the world. The production of his
nature as human and his nature as sinful was inseparable.
There was no conception, in the ordinary way, which was
not a conception in sin — no birth which was not the birth
of a sinner. Hence, there could be no exception to the
universality of sin which was not also an excej)tion to the
usual mode of generation. Whatsoever was born of the
flesh was flesh. Hence, hereditary corruption, native de-
pravity and original sin Avere promiscuously used to convey
one and the same idea.
I have thus briefly stated what is meant by the doctrine
CIO ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
of original sin, and if true it pi'esents a melancholy, an
The doctrine as ti.us appalling picturB of the iiioral condition
stated, If true-, appall- of the racB. It is beyond all controversy the
thorniest question in the whole compass
of theology, but its importance is fully commensurate with
its difficulties. Here lies the disease which redemption was
designed to remedy, and our concejDtions of the i^rovisions"
of grace must be modified by our conceptions of the need
they were arranged to meet. The natural state of man is
the key for unlocking the peculiarities of the state into
which he is introduced by grace. No man can ever know
God in Jesus Christ until he knows himself. If tlie doc-
trine is not true, it would seem to be the
if not true, it ought to • i, i • i J^ • • i ,
beWy to be refuted. Simplest aud casicst thing in nature to re-
fute it. Man is before us ; our own con-
sciousness is a volume whicli we can all to some extent read
and understand ; and the question is concerning the inner-
most ground of that consciousness as it pertains to God and
to all spiritual good. The doctrine professes to give a tran-
script of what is found in the soul of man ; it takes the
jDhenomena of human life, analyzes them, explains them
and reduces them to their principle. If there is an error, it
must be in the facts or in the reasoning. The facts, as mat-
ters of experience, speak for themselves, and the error, if it
lies there, can surely be detected and exposed. The reason-
ing is short and simple, not at all complicated ; there is but
a step betwixt the premises and the conclusion, and the
error, if it lies there, ought also to be easy of exposure.
Under these circumstances, if the doctrine is false, if it is
only a caricature and not a true and faithful portrait, is it not
strange that the most earnest and self-scrutinizing minds,
the most zealous and faithful and devoted saints, have been
precisely the persons who have insisted most tenaciously
that this is a just account of themselves apart from the grace
of God, that this is just what they have found in their own
souls, and what observation and Scripture alike teach them
to look for in the souls of others ? How such a doctrine
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIX. 311
could have originated, obtained currency, been handed
down from generation to generation among such men,
and been defended with the zeal of a warfare for hearths
and altars, is an inexplicable marvel if after all it is a
mere libel upon poor human nature. Tlie presumption
would seem to be in its favour. It could not have lived and
spread and reigned as it has done in the
It must be true, /> /-i n • /> • i i t /> •
Church ot (jod, it it had no liie ni it.
There must be something in it ; there must be a preponder-
ance of truth in it. ]\Ien are too much interested not to
believe it, to render it credible for a moment that it should
have formed a part of the faith of Christendom, if it were
not radically true. Still, it may be exag-
but is it exaggerated ? i-i ii-i
gerated, it may be overwrought, and it be-
comes us -with the utmost candour and solemnity to examine
the grounds upon which it has been supposed to rest.
1. The first thing that claims our notice in investigat-
ing the facts upon which the doctrine is
First fact of expe- i i • ji • i*j £> - tt
rience, siu universal. gi'oundcd, IS the universality of sin. Here
the Scrij)tures and experience completely
coincide. There is not a human being who has reached the
period of moral agency of whom it cannot be confidently
affirmed not only that he has sinned, but that he will still
continue to sin. " There is no man," says Solomon, in his
sublime prayer of dedication, " that sinneth not," ^ '' There
is not a just man upon earth that doeth good and sinneth
not."" "How should man be just with God? If he will
contend with Him he cannot answer Him for one of a thou-
sand."^ The doctrines of repentance, pardon, justification
by faith, the promises of daily strength — in fact, all the dis-
tinctive features of the Gospel — take for granted the absolute
universality of human sin. The race is everywhere con-
templated, both in the Old and New Testaments, as a race of
sinners. When we encounter a human being, there is noth-
incf in regard to him of which we are more certain than
that he has often done what was wrong. And we should
1 1 Kings viii. 4G. ^ Eccles. vii. 20. ^ Jq}, [^ o, 3,
312 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
look upon the man who dealt with his fellows upon the sup-
position that any of them were free from sin and not liable
to be seduced into it, as much more to be pitied for his weak-
ness than commended for his charity. If now all have
sinned, if every mouth must be stopped and the whole
world become guilty before God, there must be some cause
which is com^jetent to explain this universal efTect. The
cause cannot be partial and accidental ; as sin is not the
peculiarity of a few individuals nor the preposterous fash-
ion of single tribes or peoples, it can be explained by no
cause M'hich is not coextensive in its influence with the
entire human race. An universal fact implies an univer-
sal cause. Phenomena which always accompany humanity
are in some way grounded in its nature. From the univer-
sality of reason, conscience, intelligence and will we infer
that they belong to the constitution of the species. Opera-
tions which can only be ascribed to these faculties, as causes,
justify the inference that they exist as universally as the
effects, and are inseparable from the conception of a human
being. On the same principle there must be something in
man, something which is not local and accidental, but some-
thing which cleaves to the very being of the species, that
determines every individual to sin. It is only by an origi-
nal tendency to evil, or an ajDtitude to sin lying at the root
of the will, that we can solve the phenomenon. Let us sup-
pose that every human being came into the world free from
every irregular bias, that the will was exclusively deter-
mined to good, or, as Pelagians hold, indifferent to either
alternative ; and how does it happen among so many mil-
lions who have lived upon the earth, through so many ages
and generations, in so many nations and empires, and under
so many different forms of social and political life, that not
one has ever yet been found of whom Behold, he is clean !
could be said with justice ?
2. Sin is not only universal, but the tendency to it, accord-
ing to the confession of the race, is stronger than the tendency
to good. Men have to be carefully educated to virtue;
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN. 313
vice requires no preparatory training. The solicitude of
Second fact the P^rcnts for tlicir children, the precautions
stronger tendency is of cvcry commuuity agaiust crime, the
checks which every constitution has to
frame against the abuse of power ; our bars, bolts and dun-
geons, our racks, gibbets and all the paraphernalia of penal
justice, are conclusive proofs that we look upon each other
as beings not to be trusted, that the motives of virtue re-
quire to be propped by external supports, and tliat even
when thus propped they are counteracted by the superior
energy of evil. Every government is framed upon the sup-
position that men are disposed to crime, and even where the
disposition has not been elicited, it is yet very likely to be
acquired. Here, then, is a prevailing tendency to sin — a tend-
ency which all laws acknowledge, and a tendency which, if
it should be overlooked and not guarded against in any com-
monwealth, would soon bring that commonwealth to ruin.
3. To this may be added the experience of the most earn-
„, . , f . ., . est and devoted men in the culture of moral
Thira fact, its in-
dwelling power in the excellence. They complain of the pres-
best men. p . . i • i it
ence ol sm ni tliem as an nidwelling power,
manifesting its evil in sudden temptation or sly and surrep-
titious suggestions, or in crippling and unnerving the prin-
ciple of good. They cannot concentrate their energies upon
the holy and divine. Their souls are rendered sluggish,
their moral forces are dissipated and scattered, and languor
seizes upon their spiritual life. This mode of operation
clearly reveals the habitual character of sin ; it is evinced
not to lie in single, isolated acts, but in a permanent, abid-
ing disposition, a fixed habit of the soul.
4. This conclusion is further confirmed by the early age
Fourth fact, it be- ^^ ^hich siu makcs its appcaraucc in chil-
gins to appear in ear- drcu. As soou as tlicy bcgiu to act, tlicy
bcffin to show that self-will and self-affir-
mation are as natural as thought and reflection — they begin
to unfctld in their narrow sphere those same tempers and
dispositions which, carried over to mature life and transferred
314 ORIGINAL SIX. [Lect. XIII.
to the relations of business and social intercourse, are branded
as odious and disgusting vices. Particularly in children does
the spirit of self-seeking very early develop itself in the
form of self-justification, and make them impatient under
rebukes, surly to their superiors, and prone to falsehood as
an expedient for maintaining their reputation free from re-
proach. Augustin has signalized these perversities of his
childhood ; and those who can recall their own childish ex-
perience, or who have watched the development of character
in other children, can be at no loss for arguments to dispel
the common illusion concerning the innocence of childhood.
It is true that there is a class of sins, the offspring of expe-
rience and of a larger knowledge of the world, from which
it is free ; it is also free from the corresponding virtues. It
has not yet learned distrust and caution — it is marked by
simplicity of faith and freedom from suspicion ; but it is
equally marked by the principle of self-affirmation, whether
the character be gentle and mild or bold and impetuous.
The type of sin, which the after-life will unfold, begins from
the dawn of consciousness to unfold itself.
Xow these facts are certainly extraordinary if there is no
such thing as a law of sin in human nature.
These facts to be ex- -y^ , i • i i p • t
piaiued only by tiie J^vcry hypotliesis Dut that ot uativc de-
doctnne of original p^avity Utterly breaks down in attempting
to explain them. Sin is universal as a fact.
It is found, without exception, in every human being who
reaches the period of awakened consciousness. It is found
in those who are striving to obey the law of virtue ; it per-
vades their faculties and enfeebles their energies and relaxes
their efforts. It is stronger in the race than the tendency to
virtue ; and society can only protect itself against it by the
powerful support of penal laws. It begins to unfold its po-
tency at the very dawn of consciousness, and is as truly
present in the child as in the full-grown man. These are
not hypotheses, but facts ; they are matters of daily observa-
tion, and matters upon which the institutions of the world
turn. Admit an original aptitude for sin, an original bias
Lect. XIIL] ORIGINAL SIN. 315
to evil, and the phenomena are at once explained. Deny it,
and, as Hume says of the Gospel, all is mystery, enigma,
inexplicable mystery. It is beyond controversy that every
man looks upon his neighbour as having that within him
which has to be watched. Whatever he may think of his
own virtue, he is not willing to venture very far upon the
mere integrity of other men, apart from securities extraneous
to the innate love of right.
But a tendency to sin, as a fixed and abiding disposition.
Is there any nudd.e Hiay bc admitted tO Cxist without ascribiug
ground of truth be- ^q q^^y uaturc that complctc and hopeless
ri'the't^lS moral desolation which the Reformers in-
doctrine? cludcd in the notion of the privation of
original righteousness and the corruption of the whole
nature. The Pelagian doctrine^ that sin is accidental to
every individual, and that the uniformity of the effect does
not involve the steady operation of a permanent cause, may
be discarded without adopting the views concerning the de-
gree and extent of depravity which characterize the Augus-
tinian school. Sin may be recognized as a habit co-ordinate
with other and opposite habits ; it may be represented as a
diseased condition, which weakens without suppressing,
hinders without extinguishing, spiritual life. Though it
' [Apart from the Pelagian scheme, which really denies any fall at all,
there are four hypotheses as to the extent of the injury that human nature
has received. The first is that of some Papists, who represent original sin
as merely the deprivation of supernatural endowments, leaving man in
full and entire possession of all his natural gifts. Original righteousness
was a supernatural furniture for a supernatural end. It constituted no
part of man's nature, considered simply as human, and considered as des-
tined to an earthly existence. All that is necessary to his temporal being
he still possesses, and possesses without injury. With reference to a
higher and nobler end, transcending the pure idea of his nature, he is
wholly unfurnished. The second is that of the Sensationalists, who con-
fine the mischief of sin to the insubordination of the lower appetites— the
undue preponderance of sense over reason and conscience, of flesh over
spirit. The third is that of the Semi-Pelagians, who admit the pervading
influence of sin as extending to the whole soul. The fourth is that of the
Reformers, which we have already signalized as maintaining the total
corruption of the whole nature.]
316 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
cleaves to the nature, it only enfeebles, but does not disable
it ; makes it languid and sluggish in its desires after good,
but does not destroy the truth and reality of holy aspirations.
Something good still clings to the soul. There are still
traces of its pristine beauty, impressions of its original glory.
The spiritual and divine have not been wholly lost by the
fall. One party has represented sin as
The Sensationalists. i • i • i
seated m the sensational nature, and con-
sisting in the undue strength of corporeal appetites and pas-
sions. The higher principles of action, the principles of
reason and conscience, exist in their integrity, but they are
unable to subdue and regulate the inordinate motions of
sense. The flesh is stronger than the spirit. It is in this
want of proportion between the lower and the higher, the
want of proper adjustment, that sin essentially consists.
Others admit that the disorder of sin ex-
The Semi-Pelagians.
tends to tlie whole soul, that the entire
nature is brought under its influence ; but that there still re-
mains in man a point of attachment for Divine grace — an
ability by which he can concur with or decline the influences
of the Holy Ghost. He has points of sympathy with the
good by virtue of which he is differenced from devils and
made capable of redemption. They admit his bondage, but
contend that there is that still left in man which causes him
to abhor it, to sigh for deliverance from it, and to accept
cheerfully the friendly hand that proffers to him assistance.
This natural ability is a very different
fereiicid "^^^ '^'^'^ " tiling froiii that Avliich Arminians attribute
to the race through grace. It belongs to
man independently of the work of the Spirit, and is precisely
that which conditions the result of that work. Tlic Armi-
niaii admits that man since the fall has no
from Arniiiiiaiis. i i -i
natural ability to good, and ascribes to re-
deeming mercy that attitude of the will by virtue of which
it is enabled to accept the offer of salvation. The ability is
the same in kind, but different in its origin, from that main-
tained by those who contend for something still good amid
Lect. XIIL] ORIGINAL SIN. 317
the ruins of the a2)ostasy. The question, therefore, which
we have to discuss is, Whether the sinner,
Is there anv good • i i j.i /? 1
naturally i.. man? independently of grace, possesses any ele-
ment that can be truly and properly called
good ? Whether any seeds of holiness are still deposited in
his nature ? Whether he is able in any sphere of cognition
or of practice to compass the holy and divine? There are
but two sources of proof: Scrijjture and experience — the
word of God and the consciousness of those who have been
renewed by the Holy Ghost.
If there be any spiritual good in man, it must manifest
If there be any good i^Sclf iu the doublc foHU of Spiritual pcr-
in man, he must l)Oth CCptioU and of holy loVC, aS an act of cog-
know and love God. . . , (1 Ml T • i1 1
nition and an act ol will, it is the charac-
teristic of holiness that it holds in unity all the elements of
our rational and moral being. We can separate logically
betwixt thought and volition, betwixt the understanding
and the heart, but in every holy exercise there is the indis-
soluble union of both. The perception of beauty and ex-
cellence cannot be disjoined from love. The peculiarity of
the cognition is just the discernment of that element to
which the soul immediately cleaves as the divine and good.
Now if man independently of grace possesses any germ of
holiness, he is able to some extent to perceive and appre-
ciate the infinite excellence of God ; he must in some de-
gree love Him as the perfect good, and desire conformity
with Him as the true perfection of the soul. Wherever
there is no element of love to God as the good there is no
real holiness. Wherever there is no sense of the glory of
God as the supreme end of life there is nothing divine.
Tried by this test — and it is the only test which is at all
applicable to the case — every mouth must surely be stopped
and the whole world become guilty before God. The testi-
mony of Scripture is explicit, both as to
Scripture denies ? • i -Tj, x • xl 1 i*
both respecting him. "lau s inability to pcrccivc the glory of
God, and the total absence from his heart
of anything answering to a genuine love. Every Scripture
318 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
which teaches that liis understanding is blinded by sin, that
his mind is darkness, that he needs a special illumination
of the Spirit of God in order to be able to cognize Divine
things, teaches most explicitly that in his natural condition he
is destitute of the lowest germ of holiness. If he cannot see
he surely cannot relish beauty. If he is incapable of apjire-
hending the qualities which excite holy aftections, he is
surely incapable of possessing the emotions themselves.
There is nothing in the unrenewed sinner corresponding to
that union of all the higher faculties in one operation which
is implied in every exercise of holiness. He neither knows
God nor loves Him. Hence, all who have been renewed
The experience of , ^^^^ COUScioUS that thcy liaVC bcCU iutrO-
aii renewed men con- duccd iuto a ucw type of life. There is
firms the Scripture. i i i n i • i
not the development oi something that
was in them before, dormant or suppressed, but all things
have become in a most important sense new. Their facul-
ties are moved by a principle of which they had previously
experienced no trace, and a harmony and unity are imparted
to them which make them like really new powers. It is
useless to recount the numerous passages of Scripture which
teach the natural blindness of men, the hardness of their
hearts, the perverseness of their wills and their obstinate
aversion to the Author of their being — useless to cite the
manifold texts which describe man in his natural state as
an enemy to God and a slave to his lusts, to Satan and the
world. Their plain and obvious meaning would be ad-
mitted at once if there were not certain appearances of
human nature which seem to be contradictory to the natural
explanation, and which therefore demand a sense in harmony
with themselves. If these appearances can be reconciled
with the scheme of total depravity, then that scheme must
be accepted as the one taught in Scripture.
Among these appearances, the one on which most stress
„, f ,, is laid is the exhibition of a character dis-
The case of the un-
renewed man of high tinguislicd by high probity and scrupulous
moral character. . . , _,,
inteffritv amono- unrenewed men. ihere
Lect. XIII]. ORIGINAL SIX. 319
are those who make conscience of duty, who recognize the
supreme authority of right, and who endeavour to regu-
late their lives by the principles of reason. These men
are not to be put in the same category with abandoned
knaves or heartless voluptuaries. They have something
about them spiritual and divine ; they are good men. Such
was the young man who presented himself to the Saviour
as an inquirer after life, and whom even Jesus is said to
have loved. Here the real question is as to the root of this
morality. If it can exist apart from the love of God, and
apart from any spiritual perception of the beauty and ex-
cellence of holiness, it is no more a proof of Divine life
than the loveliness of a corpse is a proof that the soul still
lingers in it. It must be borne in mind that the fall has
destroyed no one faculty of man. It has not touched the
substance of the soul. That remains entire with all its en-
dowments of intelligence, conscience and will. These facul-
ties have all, too, their laws, which determine the mode and
measure of their operation — principles which lie at their
root and which condition the possibility of their exercise.
Intelligence has its laws, which constitute the criteria of
truth and falsehood, and without the silent influence of which
no mental activity could be construed into knowledge.
Conscience has its laws, which constitute the criteria of right
and wrong, and without which the sense of duty or of good
and ill desert would be wholly unintelligible. Taste has its
laws, which constitute the criteria of beauty and deformity,
without which aesthetic sentiments would be nothing but
arbitrary and capricious emotions. These are all co-ordi-
nate faculties, and each has a sphere that is peculiar to itself.
Collectively, they constitute the rational, moral, accountable
being. They point to three distinct spheres of thought and
life — truth, virtue, beauty. Intelligence is the faculty of
truth, conscience is the faculty of virtue, and taste is the
fticulty of beauty. They all have an essential unity in
the unity of the human person. They are grounded in
one and the same spiritual substance. It is obvious that
320 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
the mere possession of these faculties does not make a
being holy, otherwise holiness could not be lost without
the destruction of the characteristic elements of human-
ity. They exist in the fiend as really as in the saint.
Neither, again, does every mode of exercising them deter-
mine anything as to the holiness of the agent. There may
be a spontaneous exercise in which the ground of satisfac-
tion is the congruity between the faculty and its object.
Truth may be loved simply as that which is suited to
evoke the peculiar activity which we term knowledge.
Duty may be practiced, in obedience to the authority of con-
science, to prevent schism and a sense of disharmony in the
soul; each faculty may seek its object and delight in its
object only from the natural correspondence betwixt them.
When this is the spring of action and the ground of pleas-
ure, there is nothing but a manifestation of the essential ele-
ments of humanity. There may be in this way much truth
acquired, and duty as a demand of the nature may be stead-
ily and consistently practiced, and in all this the man never
rise above himself. He is acting out his own constitution,
and the law of his agency is that it is his constitution. His
cognitions of duty are really in this aspect upon a level with
his cognitions of truth, and he himself is the centre of both.
Given his present constitution, he might act and think as
he docs if there were no God to whom he is responsible.
In order that the exercise of these faculties may be holy,
there must be something more than the substantial unity
of the person ; they must be grounded in a common princi-
ple of love to God. As truth, beauty and goodness are one
in Him, so they must be one in us by an unity of life.
Truth must not only be apprehended as something suited
to my faculties of cognition, but as something Avhich reflects
the glory of God, and be loved as a ray of His excellence ;
beauty must not only be admired as something suited to
my taste, but as the radiance of Divine excellence, the
harmony of the Divine perfections; and the good must
not only be a2)prehended as a thing that ought to be, the
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN. 321
right and obligatory, but as the secret of the Divine life,
the soul of the Divine blessedness. Where the heart is per-
vaded by holy love all these faculties move in unison and
all derive their inspiration from God. Hence, in these
various spheres, the cognitions of a holy and an unholy
being are radically different ; they look at the same objects,
but they see them in a different light. One perceives only
the relations to himself; the other perceives the marks and
traces of God. One sees only the things ; the other sees
God in the things. To one the objective reality is all ;
to the other, the objective reality is only the dress in
which Deity makes Himself visible. In one, each faculty
has its own separate life grounded in its own laws ; in the
other, they all have a common life grounded in love to Him
who is at once the true, the beautiful and the good. Hence,
as there may be knowledge and taste without holiness, so
„ . ^ . there may also be virtue. Eminent con-
Eminent conscien- J
tiousness with emi- scicntiousness may be joined with eminent
nent ungodliness. ,,. i • i c -\ , ii
ungodliness — a nigh sense ot duty as the re-
quirement of our own nature with an utter absence of any real
sense of dependence upon God. The most splendid achieve-
ments, therefore, of unrenewed men are dead works — ob-
jectively good, but subjectively deficient in that which alone
can entitle them to be considered as the expressions of a
Divine life. That this reduction is true may be inferred
from the fact that there is a tendency in all integrity which
exists apart from the grace of God to generate a spirit of
pride. The motives to right-doing are apt to crystallize
aronnd this principle as their central law. The great argu-
ment for virtue is the dignity of human nature ; the life of
virtue is self-respect, and the beauty and charm of virtue is
the superiority which it impresses upon its votaries. This
tendency is strikingly illu.strated in the
The virtue of the i i l> xl. Oi. • rr\\. • i:> 1 i ^
gjj,jj.j, school ot the otoics. iheir fundamental
maxim was. Be true to yourselves; and the
difference betwixt the genius of their philosophy and the
philosophy of Christianity is, that in the one, man is com-
VoL. I.— 21
322 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
pared to a palace in which the personal individual reigns as
a king, and in the other, to a temple in which God mani-
fests His presence and His glory. The virtue of one exalts
the creature ; the virtue of the other glorifies the Creator.
The one burns incense to his own drag and sacrifices to his
own net ; the other lays all its tribute at the feet of Divine
grace. The one, in short, is the virtue of pride, and the
other is the virtue of humility. The difference betwixt
holiness and morality is like the diiference between the
Ptolemaic and Copernican systems of the universe. One
puts the earth in the centre and makes the heavenly bodies
revolve around it ; the other, the sun. One makes man
supreme ; the other, God. Without denying the reality of
human virtue, or reducing to the same level of moral worth-
lessness all the gradations of human character, it is possible
to maintain that independently of grace there is none that
doeth good in a spiritual and divine sense, no not one.
There is none that understandeth, there is none that seek-
eth after God. They are all gone out of the way, they are
together become unprofitable ; there is none that doeth good,
no, not one. There is no fear of God before their eyes.
There is a passage in Miiller's profound work upon the
Muiier on Sin, criti- Christian Doctrine of Sin, in which, through
cised as concerning inattcntiou to tlic radical distinction betwixt
holiness and morality. i i. -i t i i • • i
holiness and morality, he has maintained a
view of human nature apart from grace which cannot be
reconciled with the teachings of Scripture or the fixcts of
Christian experience. And as the whole strength of the ar-
gument against total depravity is condensed in his remarks,
it may be well to expose their error.
" We have already," he says,^ " directed our attention to
the fact, that in general there are, even for the determined
villain, still deeds of crime at which, if only for a passing
moment, he shudderingly turns away when the temptation
to the same presents itself to him. This is an unambiguous
testimony that even such an one is still capable of aggrava-
' Vol. ii., p. 269, 271.
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN.
323
tino; his state of moral villainousness. But where aggrava-
tion is still possible, there must also exist a remnant of some
power of good to be overcome, however deeply buried under
the ashes of an unbridled life of crime the sparks of the same
may be smouldering. Neither shall we be able altogether
to deny the deeply debased man, in general, the ability of
delaying or of hastening the progress of his debasedness.
The will, as the governing middle point of the inner life,
does not, even in abandoned, obdurate debasedness of life,
become entirely lost in its own complicate entanglement
with sin, but there ever remains, so far as we are acquainted
with human conditions, and in so far as the human has not
yet passed over into diabolical evil, down in the very deep
of the soul an unvanquished remnant of moral, self-deter-
mining power — an ability, if ever so limited, of self-decision
between the moral requirement and the impulses of wicked
lust. And if this must be admitted in the most degenerate
phenomena of the natural condition, how much more shall
we be required to do so with respect to its better forms !
Human nature has been created by God so noble that it is
not easily possible, even in its aggravated and deeply fallen
state, entirely to destroy the traces of its origin which exhibit
themselves in the power of the good." Further on man's
natural condition is represented, in the words of Neander, as
consisting of " two mutually conflicting principles — the prin-
ciple of the Divine offspring, the God-alliance in the endow-
ment of the God, and the therein grounded moral self-con-
sciousness, the reaction of the religio-moral original nature
of man ; and the principle of sin, spirit and flesh — so,
however, that the former principle is impeded in its devel-
opment and efficiency, and therefore held captive. Man, in
his natural condition, without the peace of reconciliation, is,
just because this peace is the truth of his very life, not an
essence which is compact, restful in itself, but one which is
in itself disunited, disquiet and full of contradictions."
" The highest activity, therefore, of the still existent power
of the good in the human natural condition, is not to deter-
324 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
mine to produce from itself an activity corresponding to the
Divine requirement — for that it is by no means able to do —
but to drive man to the humble and self-surrendering at-
tachment to the salvation of Jesus ; and that which in itself
is excellent becomes in the reality the very worst perversion
when it self-sufficiently and perversely sets itself up over
against the offered salvation."
This passage exhibits the whole of the philosophy in which
the doctrine of the bondage of the will is sought to be recon-
ciled with the active concurrence of man in the application
of redemption. It endeavours to maintain, on the one hand,
the hopeless ruin of the race apart from the grace of God,
and to ground, on the other, the different reception of the
Gospel on the part of men in the state of their own wills ;
it is an effort to teach depravity without efficacious grace —
inability without predestination. It wishes to make man
the immediate arbiter of his own destiny. The passage,
therefore, deserves to be carefully considered.
1. In the first place, because there are degrees of wicked-
Four distinctions be- ness, it is a singular confusion of ideas to
twixt hoiintss anil infer that any can be good. One state may
be worse than another Avithout being less
virtuous. One stage of degradation is certainly lower than
another, but it does not follow that there is anything lofty in
either. The development of wickedness is one thing, the
presence of holiness is another ; and the mere absence of
certain measures or forms of wickedness is not the affirma-
tion of any positive element of goodness. Miiller has here
evidently confounded that relative goodness %vhich is only a
less degree of badness with the really good — the non -presence
of types of sin with the actual presence of a principle — of a
germ — of holiness. We might as well say that because the
recent corpse was less loathsome, it was therefore less dead
than that which is rapidly sinking in decay and putrefaction.
2. In the next place, to represent the resistance which a
man makes to his own conscience in every successive stage
of sin as a struggle against the good which still exerts itself
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN. 825
within him, is to overlook the distinction betwixt the au-
thority of conscience and the love of God. The conscience
certainly remonstrates and enforces the right in the form of
an absolute, unconditioned imperative — it threatens him with
the destruction of his peace if he perseveres in his career ;
but the right comes to him as restraint, as force — as some-
thing against which the current of his soul is set. There is
neither love to it, nor respect to the will of God as declared
by it. There is no struggle of inclinations, of opposite
loves, but there is a struggle of love and inclination against
positive j)rohibition. To know duty and to be reluctant to
perform it is no proof of goodness in the heart. On the con-
trary, as we have already seen, there may be a real satisfac-
tion of duty as the demand of our own moral nature, without
the slightest tincture of complacency in God or the slightest
reference to the supreme end of our existence.
3. In the third place, the conflicts which take place in the
breast of the natural man are not conflicts between the love
of God and the inordinate desires and passions of a fallen
nature. They are conflicts between conscience and his lusts ;
and the deepest mortification which he experiences under the
sense of his degradation is the injury done to his pride.
There is no penitence before God, and there is no shame for
having brought reproach upon Him or fdr having come
short of His glory.
4. In the last place, the disjointed, miserable condition to
which the sinner finds himself reduced has no tendency to
dispose his mind to a favourable reception of the Gospel.
The rejiresentations, in which a class of writers is prone to
indulge, of the heart of fallen man as conscious of its bondage
and sighing for deliverance, looking out eagerly for some
method of escape from the degradation and ruin of sin, are
mere figures of the fancy unsustained by a solitary fact of
experience. Man has struggles and conflicts, but they are
struggles, not to escape from sin, but to escape from his own
conscience and the law. His misery is that he cannot sin
with impunity. His great eifort, in the development of sin,
326 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
is to extinguish the sense of obligation ; and the peace which
he seeks is a peace which shall reconcile God to him and not
him to God. There is nothing in the subjective condition
of the sinner which renders redemption welcome to him ;
there is neither a longing for it before it comes, nor a joyful
acceptance after it has been revealed. The Scriptures every-
where attribute to the grace of God those spiritual percep-
tions which present the Saviour to us as an object of faith
and love, and enable us to appreciate the fullness and freeness
of pardoning mercy. It is only the Divine Spirit who pro-
duces the hatred of sin as sin, and the desire to be liberated
from it on account of its inherent vileness. There is nothing;
in man to which redemption attaches itself as sympathizing
with its own distinctive provisions and predisposing the
heart for its message ; and it is proverbial that the very last
to submit to its overtures are precisely those who have the
greatest degree of that moral good which consists in con-
scientiousness and integrity. If mere morality is of a piece
with holiness, it would seem that the more moral a man
was, the readier he would be to accept the offers of salvation ;
but the language of our Saviour in relation to the Pharisees
of His own generation holds in relation to the same class in
all ages. Publicans and harlots go into the kingdom of
heaven before them.
But it may be asked. Is there not a capability of redemp-
tion? Is there nothing upon which the
In what sense, man r^ -i 'xixiii i- i
capable of redemption. Gospcl cau scizc that shall cvokc au ccho
of the unrenewed heart to its doctrines and
promises ? The answer is, that there is no natural sympathy
between them ; but there is a deep and profound sympathy
produced by the Divine Spirit when He awakens the con-
sciousness of need. The consciousness of need is awakened
through the impulse which He gives to the operations of
conscience. He employs our natural faculties ; through them
He convinces of sin, of righteousness and of judgment, and
by His secret touch they are brought into the attitude in
which they are prepared to listen to the joyful tidings of
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN. 327
salvation. We have the elements out of which a sympathy
can be established, but that sympathy results entirely from
the direction which the Holy Ghost impresses upon these
elements. Left to themselves, they would everlastingly
struggle in their blindness against God, holiness and heaven.
The real tendencies of human nature left to itself are found
„ „ . ^ in heathenism. If there is in man a sense
Heathenism snows
the real temiencies of of the lioly, of tlic Spiritual and divine,
liuman nature. . /. i . i i , ^ • i'
if there is a real and earnest longing lor
emancipation from the bondage of sin, we should expect to
see it embodied in some of the forms of religious worship in
which man has given utterance to the deepest and profound-
est instincts of his soul. Do we find any such yearning in
the ritual of heathenism ? Is it the effort of a sinful crea-
ture to restore itself to God in the fellowship of holy love ?
Does it hold fast, while it confesses its own weakness and
aberrations, to the infinite goodness and the adorable excel-
lence of God? Is its language that He is glorious and
deserves to be praised and loved, while we are vile and
ungrateful in withholding the tribute that is due ? So far
from it, that no explanation can be given of its absurdities
and monstrosities, its contradictions to reason and con-
science, its violent perversions even of taste and decency,
but that it is the determined effort of a moral being, cut
loose from its Maker, to extinguish all right apprehensions
of His name. It has utterly exploded the notion of holi-
ness as 'an attribute either of God or man ; it has outraged
reason by creations that contradict the first principles of
common sense; it has outraged conscience by putting the
stamp of religion upon crimes and atrocities which one, it
would seem, could never have dreamed of, if he had not
been resolutely set on becoming as unnatural as it was pos-
sible ; it has outraged taste by transferring to the sphere of
worship all the forms of deformity, ugliness, hatefulness
which it is possible for the human imagination to picture.
If the problem had been to devise a scheme in which not a
single element that belongs to the hio-lier nature of man
328 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect, XIIL
slioukl enter, in which all truth, all goodness and all beauty
should be entirely and completely banished — ^a scheme in
which it was proposed to reach the climax of contradiction
to the noblest features of humanity — nothing more conso-
nant to such a purpose could have been excogitated than the
system of heathenism. It shows us what the human soul
longs for, and while it reveals man's need of redemption
it reveals at the same time the malignant opposition which
it must expect to encounter.
In every view of the case, therefore, whether we look at
man in his wdckedness or in his virtues.
The case summed up. ii i i i ■
we are compelled to say that he is totally
destitute of any holy love to his God. His is dead in tres-
passes and sins. He has an understanding which is able to
distinguioh betwixt truth and falsehood, which can explore
the mysteries of nature and reduce the manifold in her com-
plicated phenomena to the unity of law ; but in all the mul-
titude of his discernments he cannot find the Father of his
own soul, and the real source of all the truth that he appro-
priates in fragments. His knowledge misses the very life
and soul of truth, and his science is but a dead form. He
has a conscience which reveals to him the eternal distinc-
tions of right and wrong and unveils the awful majesty of
virtue. He recognizes the deep significance of law and
duty, but he fails to ascend to the primal fountain of all
rectitude, and is destitute of that Divine life in which the
right is realized as the good, and law divested of all" appear-
ance of constraint in the sweet inspiration of loving obe-
dience. He has a fancy which delights in forms of beauty,
and he contemplates with intense rapture the starry heav-
ens, the rolling earth, and all the types of loveliness and
grandeur which are impressed upon the visible things of
God ; but that beauty which is above all, from which all
have sprung, and to which all point as to their centre, his
heart has never caught and his soul has never adored.
Nay, without the most strenuous efforts his life in all these
spheres is prone to ceaseless degradation. Having lost the
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN. 329
principle which gives them consistency, he is constantly prone
to lose the things themselves. In everything that bears
upon the true, the beautiful and the good, he evinces that
there is a something within him which cripples and retards
and perverts his efforts. Holiness is spiritual health and
strength, and where that is gone the whole action of the
soul is morbid. Hence, the liability to error, the influence
of prejudice, the misapprehension of the true method and
scope of philosophy, are confessions that man has fallen
from his pristine purity. Depravity impedes all the nat-
ural exercises of our faculties ; it is as much the secret of
false philosophy as of false religion. It is the disease, the
paralyzing touch of sin, that makes the memory treacherous,
the imagination unchaste, the attention inconstant, the
power of thought unsteady, reflection painful and arduous,
association arbitrary, and the fancy the storehouse of fleet-
ing and deceitful images of good. With a holy faith utterly
gone — the true light of the spiritual firmament — man gropes
his way in darkness, relieved by the glimmering of the few
stars that stud his natural sky. Without God he cannot
but be without health and peace. The creature mocks him ;
he mocks himself; he walks in a vain show, mistakes dreams
for realities, and embraces a cloud for a divinity.
II. Having considered original sin, both in its nature as
a habit and in its characteristics as the total destitution of
all holiness and as a tendency or disposition to universal
evil, I come now to treat of the mode of its transmission,
in consequence of which it is stvded heredi-
Hereditary guilt. _ *'
tary sin or hereditary guilt. It is handed
down from j)arent to child in the line of ordinary gene-
ration. Adam after his fall begat a son in his own moral
likeness, and all his posterity have perpetuated to their
descendants the character which began with him. That
the notion of transmitted or hereditary sin is beset with
difficulties which human speculation is unable to sur-
mount, it were folly to deny. But these difficulties, it
should be remembered, are not property of any j^eculiar
330 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
theory. All schemes are beset with them, and there is no
method of escaping them but by plunging into the greater
difficulties of denying facts "which form a part and parcel
of every human consciousness. We may deny that human
nature is perverted from its normal development ; that man
is failing to realize the idea of his nature; or that there
exists any special hindrance to the formation of a perfect
character ; but the conscience of every human being not
totally dead to the truth and import of moral distinctions
will remonstrate against such an abuse of speculation. Our
Avisdom is to look at the flicts precisely as they are, to fol-
low the explanations of the Scriptures as far as God has
thought proper to resolve our perplexities, and what still
lies unresolved to leave where we found it until we reach
an elevation of greater light.
There are two questions with which we have to deal in
treating of the hereditary character of origi-
nal sin. The first question is how sin is
propagated — how the child in the first moment of its ex-
istence becomes a participant of natural corruption, with-
out making God the author of its impurity. The second
question is, how that which is inherited, which comes to us
from without as a conditioning cause and not a conditioned
effect, can be strictly and properly regarded as sin — how, as
it exists in us independently of any agency of ours, it can
be contemplated with moral disapprobation or render us
personally ill-deserving. The detailed examination of these
two questions will lead us to a view of all tlie theories which
have ever been proposed on this vexed subject; and if it
should not answer all objections to the doctrine of the Re-
formed churches, it will at least show that this doctrine is
less liable to exception than any other scheme.
1. In relation to the first question, one class of writers
seem to regard it as a complete and satis-
Stapfer's tlioory. '^ . i i . •
factory solution to say that like begets like.
" The state of the parents," says Stapfer,* " is morally im-
1 Vol. i., p. 234, chap, iii., U 851, 853.
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN. 331
perfect ; of a state morally imperfect a perfect state Can by
no means be the consequence, for it is absolutely impossible
that more should be in the effect than in the cause. It fol-
lows, therefore, that if the state of the parents is morally im-
perfect, that of the children must be so also, otherwise infants
would be possessed of a perfection of which there is no nat-
ural cause." " As, therefore, the connection between the
moral state of children ah.d their parents is that of cause
and effect, moral imperfection is propagated in the way of
natural effect." According to this theory, the child is really
the product of the parent — the parent the efficient cause of
its existence. The parent expresses himself in the child,
because the child is potentially included in him as a part of
his own being. But in what sense is the parent the cause,
of the child ? Does he produce by a conscious exercise of
power and with a predetermined reference to the nature of
the effect to be achieved ? Can he fix the sex, bodily con-
stitution or personal features of his offspring? Can he
determine the bias or extent of the intellectual capacities ?
Has his Will anything to do with the actual shaping and
moulding of the peculiarities which attach to the foetus ? He
is in no other sense a cause than as an act of his constitutes
the occasion upon which processes of nature begin entirely
independently of his will, and these forces or laws of na-
ture are the immediate causes of the origin, growth and de-
velopment of the child in the womb. He simply touches a
spring which sets powers at work that he can neither con-
trol nor modify. He is only a link in a chain of instru-
ments through which God calls into being; and the efficient
power which gives rise to the effect is not in him, but in
that great Being who holds all the forces of nature in His
hands. It is, therefore, idle to say that the father makes
the child, and can make him no better than he is himself —
that he puts forth all his causal power, but as that is limited
the results must bear the marks of the limitation. The
relation of parents to children is not that of cause and effect ;
they are the instruments or conditions of the existence of
332 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
the offspring, but God may use an instrument to achieve
results that very far transcend its OAvn nature or capacities.
The other theories which we shall notice admit that the
causal relation of the parent extends only to the body — that
the soul is immediately created by God ; and contend that
as created by Him it is uncontaminated, and account for
its subsequent defilement in one or the other of the follow-
ing ways :
Pictet^ supposes that the mind of the mother during her
pregnancy operates upon the mind of the
Pictet's theory. , ., i i • i n^
child, and impresses the type oi lier own
sinful thoughts ; as the imagination of the mother very fre-
quently marks the body of her offspring with representations
of the objects that had strongly affected herself. From this
account women still have a grievous burden to bear — they
are not only the authors of the first sin that was ever com-
mitted, but they are the active instruments in the production
of all the sin that still continues to afilict the world ! They
make every other human being corrupt as they seduced
Adam from his innocence ! But seriously, this theory is only
a desperate resort. It was invented to save the consistency
of speculative thought. And it cannot maintain itself with-
out admitting that the soul is not created in its primitive
condition ; it admits weakness independently of the mother,
and a weakness which renders corruption absolutely certain.
How God is vindicated in this aspect of the case it is hard
to understand.
The other explanation is that of Turrettin and Edwards,
who contend that the soul is created spot-
Jtnl andEdwlIr" less, yet it is destitute of original righteous-
ness as a punishment of Adam's first sin ;
and accordingly they distinguish between a soul's being
pure, so as the soul of Adam was when it was first created —
that is to say, not only sinless, but having habits or inclina-
tions in its nature which inclined it to what was good — and
its being created with a propensity or inclination to evil . . .
* Pictel, vol. i., p. 446, seq.
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN. 333
and as a medium between both those extremes in which the
truth lies, they observe that tlie soul is created by God des-
titute of original righteousness, unable to do what is truly
good, and yet having no positive inclination or propensity
in nature to what is evil.^
Upon this theory the notion of original guilt is su]5posed
to involve no difficulty, but only the notion of original cor-
ruption. It is taken for granted that there is no contradic-
tion to God's holiness in treating a being as a sinner who
has never sinned, but there is a contradiction to His holiness
in making him a sinner. But where is the difference ? Sup-
pose the being as coming from the hands of God is in fact
spotless, how can he be treated as a sinner ? If not treated
as a sinner, then there is no guilt ; and if no guilt, then no
need of withholding original righteousness.
In the next place, to be destitute of original righteousness
is sin. That a moral, rational and accountable beina; should
exist without a disposition to' love God and to reverence
His holy law is itself to be in a positively unholy state.
Want of conformity with the moral law is as truly sin as
open and flagrant transgression. When these very men are
arguing against i\\Q doctrine of the Papists, they insist upon
the impossibility of an intermediate condition betwixt sin
and holiness ; and yet when they wish to explain the mode
of propagation of sin, they distinguish between simple nature
and the moral qualities which perfect and adorn it, I do
not see, therefore, that this theory obviates any difficulty at
all.
Suppose we should say that the principle of representation
conditions the creation of the child in sin, that God gives
him a being according to the determinations which the Cove-
nant of Works requires, does that make God any more the
author of sin than His daily and hourly conservation of sin-
ners ? If they are to be at all, they must be sinners, because
they are guilty in their federal head — they exist in the Di-
1 See Edwards on Original Sin, p. 330, seq. ; also Turrettin, Loc. ix.,
Qu. 12, \ 8, 9, as quoted in Eidgley, vol. ii., p. 131, upon Question xxvi.
334 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
vine mind as sinners. What contradiction, therefore, is there
in realizing this decree of justice ? I confess that to me the
whole difficulty lies in what to these di-
liefwir'niputauol!^ viucs prescuts no difficulty at all— in the
imputation of guilt. Grant that, and justice
then demands, first, that men should exist, and secondly,
that they should exist as sinners — that they should exist in
an abnormal and perverted condition. Why should not God
fulfil this requirement of justice? But it may be safest to
treat the whole matter as an insoluble mystery. We know
the fact that ^ye are born into the world in a state of sin
and misery ; that we inherit from our parents a nature which
is wholly destitute of original righteousness, and contains the
ground of the most grievous departures from God — a nature
which is absolutely unable to compass a single holy exercise.
Whether our being is wholly derived from our parents,
whether our souls are immediately created by God, whether
defilement is consequent upon the union with the body, or
the result of the generating act, or of the imagination of the
mother, or of any other cause, it may be bootless to inquire.
And on this subject the Reformed Church has settled nothing
as the definite revelation of God.
2. The question which we have now to discuss is, how
that moral condition in which we are born, and which has
been propagated to us independently of our own wills, can be
truly and properly regarded as sin ; how that can be im-
inited to us as guilt which we have inher-
The flifficulty stated. T , , . . „
ited as the constitution of our nature, and
not determined by the free decision of our own personality.
Guilt presupposes causation by the agent — that he is the
author of the actions or of the dispositions for which he is
held responsible. " In the notion of sin," as Miiller^ very
justly observes, " lies only the objective, namely the exist-
ence of a fact, whether it be an act or condition contradic-
tory to the Divine M'ill ; with the idea of guilt arises the sub-
jective side, an author to whom it can be imputed." Hence,
' Vol. i., p. 208.
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN. 335
as he had previously stated, " the first element in the notion
of guilt is this, that the given sin must be ascribed to the
man in whom it is, as to its author." The notion of cau-
sality as lying at the root of the notion of guilt he does not
fail to notice as signalized by the Greek term for guilt, which
has also the general signification of cause. It would seem,
therefore, that where a given condition cannot be traced to
him in Avhom it is found as its cause, where he receives it as
a datum, and has neither directly nor indirectly procured it
by his own agency, he cannot possibly be subject to the im-
putation of guilt. Objectively considered, the state in ques-
tion may have all the qualitative features of sin, it may be
materially the stain and the blot, but, subjectively consid-
ered, the man is rather a patient than an agent, rather suf-
fers than does evil, and his condition accordingly is one of
calamity and affliction, and not of sin. The difficulty is
very pointedly put byMiiller:^ "Only a personal essence,
and not a mere creature of nature, can render itself a sub-
ject of guilt. This arises from the fact that only a personal
essence is able to be the real author of its actions and states,
so that they may be imputed to it. Where there is no per-
sonality, consequently no freedom of the will whatever, there
the power of an original self-determination is wanting ; that
which here appears as a self-determining, if traced into its
true causes, resolves itself into a being determined. Accord-
ingly, actions and states can only in so far be considered as
criminal as they have their ultimate, deciding ground in
the self-determination of the subject. If, on the contrary,
the subject is in them merely the transition point for deter-
minations which it receives from another power, whether it
be a power of nature or a personal one, then these his states
and activities are not his fault, unless that by some preced-
ing self-determination he had rendered himself open to the
power of such determining influence upon him. Now, the
dogma of original sin teaches that the iurooted sinfulness,
which according to the canon. Semper cum raalo origlnall simul
1 Vol. ii., p. 340.
336 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
sunt peceata actuaUa, necessarily produces all kinds of sin,
is in us according to its universal, everywhere equal nature,
solely as the consequence of the first sin of the parents of
our race. But if this sinfulness is in us solely by the action
of other individuals without our own aid, then it cannot be
imputed to us as its authors, but only to those individuals ;
it is then in us not as guilt, but solely as evil and calamity.
Moreover, in all the actual sins which arise out of this sin-
fulness, it is not strictly speaking w'e wdio act, but the first
of mankind by us ; but how" then should our apparent
action still be real sin on account of which we may become
reprobated ?"
Such is the difficulty. Perhaps the most satisfactory
method of aj)proaching the solution, will
Is hereditary de- i n j. j. ' • 'xi-l j.* I»
pravity really sin? ^C, first, tO lUqUirC DltO the qUCStlOU of
fact whether hereditary depravity is or is
not really sin — that is, is or is not damnable in the sight of
God. Does it make a man guilty of death ?
The Papists are reluctant to condemn it as- chargeable
with guilt, especially as it manifests itself in the involuntary
excitations of the regenerate. Its first motions in them they
do not represent as sin, but only the encouragement which is
given by the will to these irregular impulses. Bellarmin^
indeed admits that concupiscence is non-
Bellarmin's views. , .iii n.-i^i
conformity with the law, and sin, if these
words be taken largely and improperly, as every vice and
departure from rule and order, not only in manners, but also
in nature and art, may be called sin. But in a strict and
proper sense the determinations of sin cannot be applied to
the yet unsanctified nature of those who have been renewed
by baptism. " We assert," says he, " that corruption of na-
ture or concupiscence, such as remains in the regenerate after
baptism, is not original sin, not only because it is not im-
puted, but because it cannot be imputed, since it is not in its
own nature sin." And the Council of Trent declares that it
^ De Amiss. Grat., lib. v., cap. xiv. Controv., torn, iv., cap. vii. De
Moor, cap. xv., § xxiii.
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIX. 337
is, in the Scripture, called sin, not because it is sin, but be-
cause it springs from sin and leads to sin : Ex peccato est et
ad peccatum indinat. The Remonstrants in their Apology
articulately maintain " that original sin is
The Eenioiistrants. "^ _ °
not to be considered sin in the sense that it
renders the race unworthy of the Divine favour, or exposes
them to punishment in the strict and proper sense, as con-
tradistinguished from calamity ; but it is to be viewed only
as evil, infirmity, misfortune — it brings with it no guilt."
^ . ^ , Limborch,^ one of the most learned of the
Limborch.
Remonstant divines, repeatedly enounces
the doctrine that what is natural cannot be sinful, and that
the imbecility under which the posterity of Adam labours, and
which, he thinks, has been grievously exaggerated by the
Reformed theologians, cannot be properly associated with
the notion of guilt. He admits that human nature has been
injured by the fell; that we are born with appetites less
pure than those of our first parents ; that there is a stronger
inclination to evil, in consequence of which Ave are seduced
into sin with less provocation ; but still he maintains that
this concupiscence, in as far as it is natural, and not a habi-
tude contracted by our own voluntary acts, cannot be pro-
perly denominated sin. The fundamental position of the
Arminian school, that ability is the measure of duty, neces-
sitates this conclusion. Whatever has not freely originated
from ourselves cannot be imputed to ourselves; it is not
ours, but must be attributed to the cause which really deter-
^ . , mined it. The language of Zwino-le,^ too,
Zwingle. ^ o o & ? )
however it has been attempted to explain
away its obvious import, conveys the same idea. He styles
original sin as a disease, and not as strictly and properly sin.
™, „ , , ,. . On the other hand, the Reformed divines
Tlie Reformed divines. _ '
have uniformly maintained that the de-
praved condition in which all the descendants of Adam are
born is not only the fruitful parent of sin, but is in its own
nature sin, and makes the man truly guilty before God. It
1 Limborch, lib. iii., c. 3, H- ^ De Moor, cap. sv., | xxiii.
Vol. I.— 22
338 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XTIT.
is itself damnable iu its being, motions and ret^ults, and
without any actual transgression is a just ground of exclusion
from the favour of God. This conclusion
Testimony of the • n .•ni,i ,,• p
Scriptures. ^^ equally sustained by the testnnony oi
Scripture and the authority of conscience.
It is admitted by Bellarmin and the Council of Trent that
the word of God pronounces it to be sin. The whole argu-
ment in the seventh chapter of Romans proceeds upon the
supposition not only that it is evil, calamity, misfortune, but
that it is guilt ; that it makes a man damnable — the subject
of the righteous retribution of death. The declaration of
Paul in his Epistle to the Ephesians, that we are by nature
the children of wrath, can by no possibility be evaded. We
are there expressly said to be under the condemnation of
God, on account of the condition in which we are born.
David, too, aggravates the guilt of his actual sin, in the fifty-
first Psalm, by tracing it back to the sinful principles which
he inherited from his mother's womb. The whole treatment
of our natural condition in the New Testament is grounded
in the notion that it is a state of guilt ; that our imbecility
is blameworthy ; and that it has to be dealt with not as
disease, but as moral perversion and disorder. All the pro-
visions of grace imply this, or are utterly unintelligible.
Then, again, if the Scripture definitions of sin are to be
Argument from maintained, they cannot but include our
Scripture definitious native corruptiou. It surely is want of
conformity with the law. It is the very
defect which the law stigmatizes as the form of sin. Wher-
ever there is not conformity, there is and must be sin in a
subject capable of obedience. The man who is not what he
ought to be, or who is what he ought not to be, the Bible
uniformly treats as a sinner, and takes for granted that in
some way or other the blame must be ultimately visited upon
himself. It knows nothing of a non-conformity which is
innocent. It assumes that the fact must always be grounded
in guilt.
In the third place, if original corruption were not sin, it
Lect. XIII.] OEIGINAL SIN. 339
would be difficult to explain how the acts to which it excites,
and which are only the outward expressions
from Scripture^"'"''" ^'^ itself, could bc Considered sinful. If the
original imjjulse is innocent, how can its
gratification be sin ? How can its motions and excitations
undergo a change in their own nature in consequence of their
being humoured or encouraged ? There is surely no harm
in yielding to the suggestions of innocent impulses. The
Saviour teaches us to judge of the tree by its fruits. When
the fruits are good, the tree is good. The Arminian tells us
that all trees are in themselves good, but that some are un-
fortunately afflicted Avith evil fruits ; yet that the evil is
only in the fruit.
In the last place, original sin is certainly visited with
death, and if death be the exponent of
A fourth argument 'ixj.! ••!• . i •, ^
from Scripture gui^*^ ^lien Original sm must make its sub-
ject guilty.
Our own consciences are equally explicit with the Scrip-
tures. They condemn the dis230sitions and
habitudes which are grounded in our na-
ture as the very core of the sinfulness
which appears in our life. It is the malice, the hardness
of heart, the insensibility, the unbelief, which cleave to us
as the legacy of birth, which constitute the very life of our
wickedness. The disposition or principle determines the
moral significancy of the act ; the state of mind which lies
at the root of the will conditions the degree of guilt which
attaches to the act. The awakened sinner is particularly
struck with the appalling wickedness involved in the fixed,
abiding condition of his soul. His attention may first be
arrested by his transient acts, but under the guidance of the
Spirit he is soon led to inspect the moral attitude of his
heart, and to pronounce the sentence of the prophet, " the
heart is deceitful above all things and desperately wicked."
Conscience condemns us, then, for what we are no less un-
equivocally than for what we do. We cannot, therefore,
evade the conclusion that native corruption is sin ; that it
Testimony of our
own conscience.
340 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
carries with it exposure to the Divine condemnation ; that
it ends in death. Scripture and conscience cannot tolerate
the palliatives of a deceitful philosophy ; they know noth-
ing of a heart destitute of love to God as only unfortunate
and not criminal, and they never deal with unbelief as in-
firmity, but not guilt. Both, in directing us to look at our
nature, stop our mouths and compel us to acknowledge that
we deserve to die.
It is an important point to have clearly settled in the
These testimonies J^i"^^ ^^^^^ Original siu is accompauied with
prove that original il] dcscrt. It establishes beyond the possi-
sin involves guilt. m-i- /»iii • i
sibility ot doubt that m some way or other
we must be the responsible authors of it. Conscience in
condemning us as guilty on account of it, and the Word of
God in ratifying that sentence, pronounce us at the same
time to be the voluntary cause of its existence. Other-
wise there would be a palpable contradiction. Even if it
were granted that we are utterly unable to detect the causal
relation, if it eludes our closest scrutiny, if the result of all
philosophical inquiry gives only the appearance of our being
absolutely conditioned by a foreign agency, — still, we should
not be authorized to contradict a fundamental deliverance
of conscience on account of our inability to apprehend the
grounds of its truth. It must be assumed as unquestion-
able, whether we can explain it or not. Its voice is final,
whether we can understand the reason of its verdict or not.
If conscience says that we are guilty on account of our
native turpitude, that is a declaration that we stand in a
personal relation to it which makes it justly imputable to
us as our fault. We have in some way or other procured
it. Now the question arises, How and
procured? ^^^ ^'^^ ' when ? It is perfectly clear that if it must
be ascribed to us, it must either be in con-
sequence of some voluntary act of ours or in consequence of
the voluntary act of another that can be justly construed as
ours. A sinful state can only spring from a sinful act. It
is always the penal visitation of transgression. Original
Lect. xiil] original sin. 341
sill, therefore, as a permanent, abiding condition mnst be
penal, as Augustin and the Reformers persistently assert, or
it cannot be sin at all. The sinful act which produced it
must have been the personal decision of each human will —
that is, each man must have fallen by his own personal
transgression — or it must be the act of another so related to
us as that we may be held accountable for
Only two supposi- •, npi • xi • i
tions possible. ^^- J-^^ere IS no third supposition possi-
ble— no medium betwixt our own act and
the act of another.
Shall we say, then, that each man fell for himself? That
would necessitate the notion of a state of existence prior to
our birth in this world ; of an ante-mun-
Ante-mundane pro- i ij- • i-i n •■! -i -i
batiou. dane probation m which we failed, and
the consequence of w^hich is the disordered
condition in which we find ourselves beginnino; our earthlv
life. There have been intrepid logicians who have reso-
lutely followed up the datum of conscience in relation to
the guilt of original sin, and have found in it the unquali-
fied assertion that we lived, moved and willed before we
were born. The reasoning is short and apparently decisive.
Our nature is sinful ; it could not have been made so with-
out our act ; that act which corrupted the nature could not
have taken place in time, for the corruption begins with our
life in time ; there must, therefore, have been a transcendent
existence in which this indispensable prerequisite of original
sin was realized.
There are many phenomena connected with our present
mundane life Avhicli the deepest thinkers have felt them-
selves unable to comprehend without the supposition of a
pre-existent state. Pythagoras, it is well
Pythagoras. | i i i ^ O 7
known, looked upon the present as a penal
condition to which we were degraded for our abuse of a
higher and nobler state. Plato felt him-
self equally at a loss to explain the pheno-
mena of knowledge or of sin Avithout the same presuppo-
342 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
sition. Origen could find satisfaction in dealing with the
delivei'ances of the human conscience, and
Origen. , ... . . r- o • i
the explicit testimonies oi fecripture, only
by adopting the same hypothesis. " Kant, despairing of
finding liberty anywhere in the iron chain
of motive and action as stretching from the
beginning to the end of our empirical existence, sought it in
the higher world of the unconditioned ; and
Schelling, as early as 1809, in his cele-
brated essay on Freedom, in which he traced sin to a prin-
ciple of darkness existing in God, and uniting itself with
the free-will of man, expressly declared that original sin
was committed by every man before his temporal being, and
drew all the sins of life after it with rigorous necessity.
Life was ]:)0und, but it was bound by an antecedent act of
liberty, and thus the intuitions of conscience were defended
by a bulwark too high for the reach of skepticism, and free-
will stood invincible with its back to the wall of eternity,"^
Miiller, in his great work on Sin, finds
himself driven by the exigencies of con-
sistent speculation to a timeless state in which each man by
his own free act conditioned his moral development in time.
But there are insuperable objections to such a scheme.
In the first place, the notion of a timeless
,:::J::^:^1 existence is Itself utterly unintelligible.
Every finite being is conditioned, and con-
ditioned both by time and space, and an intelligible world
of real substantive existences without temporal relations is
altogether contradictory.
In the next place, it is wholly unaccountable how such a
state, signalized by so momentous an act as that which pro-
duced original depravity, has so entirely passed from the
memory as to leave no trace behind. Surely, if anything
had impressed itself upon our minds, such a condition, so
different from the present and so fruitful in its consequences,
could not have failed to be remembered. If there had been
1 North British Kev., 1850.
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN. 343
such a state, the Scriptures woukl not only have recognized
it, but pressed it upon us as a full vindication of the justice
of God in His dealings with the race. The recollection of
this primitive act of freedom would have silenced all cavils,
stopped every mouth, and explained to every human soul
how and when it became the author of its own ruin.
But the doctrine is palpably inconsistent with the Scrip-
ture account concerning the origin of the
Totally inconsistent i • i , i i t , . .
with Scripture. numau species, and the moral condition m
which the first of the race began his mun-
dane being. We must look for that act which entails our
depravity in the sphere of time and in the sphere of temporal
conditions. We cannot carry human existence beyond
Adam, nor Adam's existence beyond that creative fiat
which gave him his being on the sixth day. Then and
there the species began and began holy. The Scriptures
further inform us when and where and how he lost his in-
tegrity. From the time of his disobedience in the garden
in eating the forbidden fruit he and all the race have borne
the type of sin. There has been no holiness in the species
from that hour to this unless as supernaturally produced by
the grace of God. It would seem, therefore, that the all-
conditioning act which has shaped the moral impress of the
race was no other than the act which lost to Adam the image
of his God. And such seems to be the explicit testimony
of Scripture : " By one man's disobedience many were made
sinners." Either we are guilty of that act, tlierefore, or
original corruption in us is simply misfortune and not sin.
In some way or other it is ours, justly imputable to us, or
we are not and cannot be born the children of wrath. We
must contradict every Scripture text and every Scripture
doctrine which makes hereditary impurity hateful to God
and punishable in His sight, or we must maintain that we
sinned in Adam in his first transgression. There human
sin historically began. Before that time the sijecies was
holy ; since that time there has been none that doeth good,
no, not one. That, therefore, is the decisive act — that was
344 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
tlic point on which the destinies of the race turned. Btit
the question arises, How could that act have been ours in
such a sense as to justify the imputation of guilt? What
causal agency could we possibly have had in bringing it
about ? Was Adam ourselves, or were ourselves Adam, or
Our relation to Adam could wc and hc bc personally ouc ? Let
as a ground for impu- ^g look at our relation to him, and see if
we can find anything in which to ground
the notion of our participating in the guilt of his trans-
gression.
In the first place, he was the natural head of his posterity
— the father of all mankind. But the act
Adam our natural t} j. • j. l j.1 x l"
,jp,^j, 01 a parent is not by any means the act oi
the child. If the parental relation, such as
it now obtains in the species, exhausted Adam's relations to
the race, it would be impossible to explain how they could
be guilty on account of his sin, or why they should be guilty
on account of the first sin xather than any other. Even if it
were granted that as a father he must propagate his own
moral features, his children would receive them simply as a
nature, without being blamable on account of them, as a
child might innocently inherit a distorted body which the
parent had brought upon himself by guilt. The natural re-
lation is, therefore, wholly incompetent to bear the load of
hereditary sin. There must be something more than parent
and child in the case. It is vain to appeal to those analogies
in which the offspring share in the sufferings incurred by the
wickedness of their fathers. The offspring indeed suffer,
but they do not charge themselves with blame — they have
no sense of ill desert. They look upon their sufferings dis-
tinctly as calamities, and not as punishments to them, though
they may be punishments of their fathers through them.
In the next place, Adam was the federal liead or repre-
sentative of his race. He was on probation
head'''" ""■" '''""'' for them, as well as for himself, in the
Covenant of Works. He was not a private
individual — he was the type of universal humanity. In
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIX. 345
him God was dealing witli all who should afterward spring
from his loins. Now, that he sustained this relation is clear
from the explicit testimony of the Scriptures ; and that it,
if justly founded, is adequate to solve the problem of hered-
itary guilt, is beyond dispute. If Adam were the agent of
us all, his act was legally and morally ours. Qui factt per
alium, fac'd jjer se.
The only question is. Whether this federal relation is
founded in justice? We have already
Is this founded in j.i x j.1 • • ^ • i? 1
• jgjj^gj seen that the principle is one ot benevo-
lence, and furnishes the only hope for the
absolute safety of any portion of mankind. Without this
principle, the whole race might have perished without the
possibility of redemption. But its benevolent tendencies
are no proof of its essential justice. Can we vindicate it
upon principles of reason? Is there any such union in the
nature of things betwixt Adam and his descendants as to
justify a constitution in which he and they are judicially
treated as one ? An affirmative answer has
Two grounds. .
been given on two grounds: 1. I hat oi
generic unity ; and 2. That of a Divine constitution.
If a fundamental unity subsisted betwixt Adam and his
species, it is clear that he could be justly
fuIdamel'tTunUy. "" ^Icalt with as the federal head or represent-
ative of the race. He was the race, and
therefore could fairly be treated as the race. What he did,
it did ; his act was the act of Mankind, and his fall was the
fall of ]Man. There was no fiction of law ; there was no ar-
bitrary arrangement when he was made the representative
of all who were to descend from him by ordinary generation.
There was a real and an adequate foundation in nature for
that covenant under which he was put upon trial, not only
for himself, but for all his posterity.
Relation of the fed- HcrC, toO, WC SCC thc prCcisC rclatioU of
era! to the natural tlic federal aud natural union betwixt Adam
and the race. The federal presupposes the
natural. The federal is the public recognition of the fact
346 ORIGINAL SIX. [Lect. XIII.
implied in the natural, and is a scheme or dispensation of
religion founded upon it. If there were not a real unity
betwixt Adam and the race, the covenant of works could not,
by an arbitrary constitution, treat them as one. In the no-
tion of a generic identity of human nature, both ideas blend
into one. Adam's sin becomes imj)utable, and as guilt in
him becomes the parent of depravity in them. Hence, in
the order of thought, his sin must always be conceived as
imputed before they can be conceived as depraved. They
must be regarded as guilty before they can reap the penal
consequence of guilt.
By this doctrine of imputation the testimony of conscience
is completely harmonized. It makes us
The testimony of con- . t ., ,i i^ i^
science harmonized. recogmze our dcpravity as the result of our
own voluntary act; it was our voluntary
act in the sense in which Adam and we were one. It makes
us pronounce ourselves guilty on account of the corrujition
of our nature, and to the extent of our participation in the
generic character of the race we are blameworthy. We
are responsible for this as we are responsible for every habit
contracted by our own voluntary acts.
The only point in which this explanation fails to give
satisfaction is in relation to the question whether the notion
of generic unity is an adequate basis for grounding a per-
sonal participation in the sin of Adam. In consequence of
this difficulty, one class of theologians has
diSfbuf hnn"edire^ rccoilcd from tlic doctriuc of the immediate
imputation of Adam's first sin, and resolved
the guilt of native depravity into our subsequent concurrence
in it. That is, it becomes sin in us only by our free consent
to its impulses — we make it sin by endorsing it. But if it
be given to us as a part of our constitution without any fault
justly chargeable upon us, it is hard to understand how a
life s]3ontaneously manifesting itself in conformity Avith ex-
isting conditions can be criminal in man any more than in
the brute, unless the whole of his moral probation be sum-
med up in the duty of resisting his nature. If sin only then
according to the Scrip-
tures.
Lect. xiil] original sin. 347
begins wheu his will has adoptedlhe suggestions of corrupt
lust, then it is implied that not only up to that point he is
innocent, but that he is fully competent to mortify the flesh
and extirpate his depravity. If he has not the power to re-
sist and subdue, if his will is mastered by his nature, it is
clear that the same reasoning which exempted native cor-
ruption from the imputation of guilt, must also exempt all
the acts necessitated by it. To maintain a will stronger
than depravity is contrary to the whole teaching of Scripture
concerning the extent and degree of that depravity, and is
also inconsistent with the doctrine of the necessity of redemp-
tion. Unless therefore we begin with guilt, we can never
end with guilt. Either Adam's sin must be imputed, or all
his race must be pronounced free from aught that is blame-
worthy or deadly. Hence, the Scriptures
teach exjjlicitly that we are first charged
with the guilt of Adam's sin, and then, as
the legal consequence, are born with natures totally corru])t.
The matter may be put in another light. The disobedi-
ence of Adam was, unquestionably, the be-
Another statement • • r • ' j.1 rri. j. T 1 T
of the case giuning 01 SHi u\ the race. Ihat disobedi-
ence determined the moral habitude or
condition of his own soul, and determined it by a judicial
sentence. He lost the image of God because he was guilty.
The whole human race are born destitute of that image.
Now, their destitution is beyond doubt the consequence of
his sin. In what way or on what principle the consequence ?
There are but two possible suppositions : a consequence
either implying or not implying blameworthiness in them
— a mere process of nature or a decree of justice. If a mere
process of nature, then their existence absolutely begins with
their birth, and the state in which they find themselves is
an appointment of God analogous to that which determines
the qualities of a tree or the propensities of a beast. They
are just what God made them. But it can be no sin to re-
ceive a nature which you cannot determine. If now the
nature conditions the life, there can be no sin in that life in
348 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIIL
as far as it answers to the nature. If, on the other hand,
our depravity is the judicial consequence of the first trans-
gression, then it supposes not only that we existed, but that
we acted, in Adam ; and then we have a point for all the
subsequent determinations of guilt. The nature is wicked
in me on the same principle that it was wicked in Adam —
it was contracted by a wicked act.
Others are content with the general statement of Adam's
natural and federal relations to the race,
ment!' """"'^'^ ^*^*''" witliout attempting to explain how the one
is grounded in and justified by the other.
They are willing to admit that the existence of every indi-
vidual begins at the moment of his personal manifestation
in time. But they contend that the judicial sentence of the
covenant conditions the type of that manifestation, and ne-
cessitates the appearance of every descendant of Adam as a
sinner. If asked, Whether representation can be arbitrary?
they answer. No ; there must be a bond between the head and
the members. If asked. What is the tie between Adam and
his race ? they answer. That of blood. His natural headship
fits and qualifies him for federal headship. This theory, in
avoiding the metaphysics of personal unity, and resolving
the whole connection into a moral and political community
founded in blood, has some advantages. It is justified by
many analogies — by the present constitution of families,
commonwealths and states — and avoids the difficulty growing
out of the limitation of Adam's influence upon us as to his
first sin. But it has also serious drawbacks. It does not
explain the sense of guilt as connected with depravity of
nature — how the feeling of ill desert can arise in relation to
a state of mind of which the subjects have been only passive
recipients. The child does not reproach himself for the
afflictions which his father's follies have brought upon him ;
and the subject does not feel that he is punished in the ca-
lamities which a wicked ruler brings upon a nation. He
makes a marked distinction between those ills which he ex-
periences in consequence of his social and political connec-
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN. 349
tions with others, and those which he experiences in conse-
quence of his own fault. Our inborn corruption we do feel
to be our fault — it is our crime as well as our shame. Be-
sides, this theory fails to explain the necessity of spiritual
death. It does not show why God, in justice, must renounce
the communion of those who are still personally innocent
while putatively guilty. He might visit them with evil as
a magistrate, and still treat them with sympathy and love
in their personal characters. They might suffer without be-
coming depraved. If they are not in themselves the proper
objects of odium, why should they be hated ? These are
difficulties connected with the account which recognizes no
deeper unity than the natural and political. This theory,
however, is the one commonly accepted in this country. Its
simplicity recommends it. But I confess the leaning of my
own mind to some theory which shall carry back our exist-
ence to the period of Adam's probation.
On these grounds I am free to confess that I cannot escape
from the doctrine, however mysterious, of
Generic unity the ... , ^ . n
true basis. ^ geucric uuity m man as the true basis of
the representative economy in the covenant
of works. The human race is not an aggregate of separate
and independent atoms, but constitutes an organic whole,
with a common life springing from a common ground.
There is an unity in the whole species ; there is a point in
which all the individuals meet, and through which they are
all modified and conditioned. Society exerts even a more
powerful influence upon the individual than the individual
upon society, and every community impresses its own pecu-
liar type upon the individuals who are born into it. This
is the secret of the peculiarities of national character.
There was one type among the Greeks, another among the
Asiatics, and still another among the Romans. The Eno--
lishman is easily distinguished from the Frenchman, the
Chinese from the European, and the Negro from all. In
the same way there is a type of life common to the entire
race in which a deeper ground of uuity is recognized than
350 ORIGINAL SIN. [Lect. XIII.
that which attaches to national associations or the narrower
ties of kindred and blood. There is in man what we may
call a common nature. That common nature is not a mere
generalization of logic, but a substantive reality. It is the
ground of all individual existence, and conditions the type
of its development. The parental relation expresses, but
does not constitute it — propagates, but does not create it. In
birth there is the manifestation of the individual from a na-
ture-basis which existed before. Birth consequently does not
absolutely begin, but only individualizes humanity. As,
then, descent from Adam is the exponent of a potential exist-
ence in him, as it is the revelation of a fact in relation to the
nature which is individualized in a given case, it constitutes
lawful and just ground for federal representation. God can
deal with the natural as a covenant head, because the natural
relation proceeds upon an union which justifies the moral.
The second explanation is that of Edwards, who endea-
vours to reduce all identity to an arbitrary
arbUraJconsutuUoT. coustitutiou of God, and finds the same
ultimate ground of the personal unity of
Adam and the race as for the personal identity of the same
individual in diiFerent periods of his existence, or the con-
tinued identity of the same substance in the successive
changes of its being. This doctrine is unquestionably a
paradox, and, however ingeniously put, sets at defiance the
plainest intuitions of intelligence.
But it may be asked. Do you mean to say that each indi-
vidual will actually expressed itself in the prevarication of
Adam — that each man actually ate of the forbidden fruit ?
As individuals certainly not ; as individuals none of us then
existed. In our separate and distinct capacity his sin was
no more ours than our sins are his. But as the race, which
was then realized in him as it is now realized in all its in-
dividuals, his act was ours. How the individual is related
to the genus, how the genus contains it, and how the indi-
vidual is evolved from it, are questions which I am utterly
unable to solve. But their mystery is no prejudice to their
Lect. XIII.] ORIGINAL SIN. 351
truth. Our moral convictions demand that we should pre-
dicate such an unity of mankind; and
Mystery, no preju- xU U •in.
dice to truth. tJiougli a great mystery itself, it serves to
clear up other mysteries which are pitch
darkness without it.
If this account of the representative principle should be
rejected, we can only fall back upon the testimony of Scrip-
ture, and treat it as an ultimate fact in the moral govern-
ment of God until a satisfactory explanation can be given.
We must accept it as we accept other first principles, and
patiently wait until the difficulties connected with it are dis-
sipated by further light. It does explain hereditary sin and
hereditary guilt ; it does unlock the mystery of God's deal-
ing with the race ; it does meet all the requirements of con-
science in reference to our own moral state and condition.
^^ ,^ , ^11 that it leaves unsolved is the ground
The theory of rep- ^ . . ° v^^ii^i
reseutation alone con- 01 its owii righteousucss. Every othcr
InironSrcr t^^^^y ^^ obliged to deny native depravity,
and to contradict at once the explicit teach-
ings of Scripture and the articulate enunciations of con-
science.
LECTURE XIV.
THE STATE AND NATURE OF SIN.
WE liavc now traced the history of man, and of God's
dealings with him, from Creation to the Fall. We
have seen him in his primitive innocence when he walked
in the light of his Creator's countenance, was regaled wuth
the beauties of nature, received the homage of the creatures,
and exulted in the prospect of a blessed immortality. He
was at once a king and a priest — a king to whom the garden
was a palace, and who exercised undisputed dominion over
every lower rank of sublunary being — a priest in the great
temple of nature, Avho gathered first from the fullness of
his own heart, and then from the various perfections of the
creatures, the manifold praises of God and poured them forth
in doxology and adoration into the ears of the Eternal. He
occujiied a noble elevation. He had a grand destiny before
him. But how
" Little knows
Any, but God alone, to value right
The good before him, but perverts best things
To worst abuse or to their meanest use !" ^
The scene becomes woefully changed, and instead of truth,
justice, innocence and sanctitude severe, we are presented
with the brood of ills that have sprung from the pregnant
womb of sin. We must now survey the race amid the ruins
of the fall, and we must never lose sight of the consideration
that the condition in which we now find ourselves is one of
condemnation and of guilt. The frowning aspect of Provi-
1 Par. Lost, iv., 1. 201-204.
352
Lect. XIV.] THE STATE AND NATURE OF SIN. 353
dence which so often darkens our world and appals our
minds, receives its only adequate solution in the fact that
the fall has fearfully changed the relations of God and the
creature. We are manifestly treated as
state of sin. ... , ,
criminals under guard. We are dealt
with as guilty, faithless, suspected beings that cannot be
trusted for a moment. Our earth has been turned into a
jjrison, and sentinels are posted around us to awe, rebuke
and check us. Still, there are traces of our ancient gran-
deur ; there is so much consideration shown to us as to jus-
tify the impression that these prisoners were once kings,
and that this dungeon was once a palace. To one unac-
quainted with the history of our race the dealings of Provi-
dence in regard to us must appear inexplicably mysterious.
The whole subject is covered with light when the doctrine
Theological import- 0^ ^hc Fall is uudcrstood. The gravest
auce of the doctrine of thcological crroi's witli rcspcct alike to the
character of God and the character of man
have arisen from the monstrous hypothesis that our present
is our primitive condition, that Ave are now what God origi-
nally made us, and that the exactions of his law have always
been addressed to the circumstances of disadvantage and im-
becility which now unquestionably attach to us. This were
surely to cast a grave imputation upon the Judge of all the
earth ; and so strongly has the injustice of such an adminis-
tration been felt that others have not scrupled to modify
the principles of the Divine government so as to make them
square with the imperfect condition of the species. It can-
not be denied that if the present be assumed as our natural
state, it is impossible to vindicate God's justice if he con-
demn us for that which He Himself of His own sovereign
will implanted in us, and equally impossible to vindicate
His holiness in implanting sin within us, or in not punish-
ing it when He finds it there. Most of the errors touchinsr
human ability have arisen from inattention to the relations
in which the fall has placed us to God. The whole doctrine
of redemption is conditioned upon these relations, and we
Vol. I.— 23
354 THE STATE AND NATURE OF SIN. [LiXT. XIV.
can therefore neither know ourselves, nor God, nor the Re-
deemer, without the knowledge of the moral features of our
present state. It is represented in the Scriptures as a state
of sin aud misery, and our own experience abundantly jus-
tifies the melancholy record. But if we would compass in
any just measure the magnitude of our ruin, we must in-
quire into the nature of sin, and see whence it derives its
malignity and bitterness ; we must then survey the extent
to which we are involved in sin, and trace the steps by
which we have sunk to this degree of degradation ; we
must finally vindicate the justice and goodness of God in
His dispensations toward us, and when we have taken this
wide survey, we may return prepared to appreciate the bless-
ings of the Gospel.
I. The first point to be considered is the nature of sin, or
the answer to the question, What is sin?
What is sin? rr^^ r' i i • i • •
The first and most obvious determuiation
of it, and that to which the mind instantly reverts, is its re-
lation to the moral law. Where there is
First: Objective tie- i xi a j.i j.1 i
terminations. "^ ^^^^f ^lic Apostlc assurcs US there can be
no transgression. The moral law is the
standard, or measure, by which the man must l^e tried. It
prescribes alike what he is required to be and what he is re-
quired to do. It extends to the whole sphere of his volun-
tary being. It is the mould into which his w*hole life must
be run. Whatever, therefore, in him is not in accordance
with the law is sin. Hence, sin is described by John as
being essentially dvojAa — a state of non-conformity wdth the
law. It is a matter of no consequence how
JnolT^uZluZ. the law is made known, whether through
the operations of conscience or an express
revelation from God ; its authority does not depend upon
the mode of announcing it, but upon its inherent nature as
the standard and measure of moral rectitude. No matter
how proclaimed, the soul of man instantly resj)onds to it as
holy and just and good. He feels that it speaks Avith au-
thority, aud that perfection neither in being nor condition
Lect. XIV.] THE STATE AND NATURE OF SIN. 355
can be attained to apart from its requisitions. "Wlien the
question is asked, What does the law demand ? some have
sought to restrict it to external actions, others have con-
fined it to chosen and deliberate purposes, but it is generally
maintained that its domain is coextensive with the domain
of the will. That it is not to be limited to external acts is
evident from all those testimonies of Scripture which affirm
it to be spiritual, and from the universal conscience of the
race, which condemns the motive even more severely than
the act, and conditions the morality of the agent more by his
purposes than his actual doings. When, however, the obli-
gation of the law is said to be measured bv the extent of the
will, the statement is not to be accepted without an explana-
tion. If by will is meant only the conscious volitions, or the
conscious preferences of the man, the statement is quite too
narrow. Those states or habitual dispositions from which
these conscious preferences proceed, those permanent condi-
tions of the mind which determine and shape every motive
and every act of choice, are as truly within the jurisdiction
of the law as the volitions themselves. There is a something
which we ought to be as well as a something which we
ought to do. The law is as much the rule of our being as
of our life. If it should be asked how we can become re-
sponsible for original habits and dispositions which exist
prior to any exercise of will, and condition and determine
all its choices, we must either resolve the thing into a primi-
tive and inexplicable deliverance of our moral nature, or
presuppose that, in our primitive state, these constitutional
peculiarities are the result of an act of will. Man was made
without any tendencies to evil ; these he has superinduced
upon himself by voluntary transaction, and they are, there-
fore, related to the will as its prosier product. This is evi-
dently the case in relation to acquired habits ; they spring,
in the first instance, from the will, and afterwards master it.
So the whole inheritance of native depravity which we bring
with us into the world, with all those tendencies to evil
which hold the will in bondage, arc the fruits of a free act
356 THE STATE AND NATURE OF SIN. [Lect. XIV.
of choice. But whatever may be the exjjlanation, Scripture
and experience concur in attributing a moral significancy to
the dispositions which, in our present state, lie back of the
will. The malice which prompts to murder is as hateful as
the murderous deed ; the propensity which kindles at temp-
tation is something more than a weakness — it is a positive
evil.
If now the law regulates the being and the life of man, it
is clear that our first determination of sin, taken from its
relation to the law, extends its sphere to the inward condi-
tion as well as the outward expression of the soul — to the
state of the heart as Avell as to the actions of the life. What-
ever is not in exact accordance with the spirit and temper
of the law, whatever is out of harmony with it, either in the
way of defect, omission or overt transgression, is of the
formal nature of sin.
But sin is not distinguished from a crime, or an immoral-
ity, or a vice, by this determination. We
It is disobedience to j.ii ±t i j_i/*
(Jq^ must add anotner element beiore non-con-
formity with the law is entitled to be called
sin. That term indicates a special relation to God — nothing
is sin which does not directly or indirectly terminate in Him.
Hence, the law must be considered as the expression of His
will, and then our determination by the external standard
or measure is complete, and sin, as transgression of the law,
becomes disobedience to God. It is the want of correspond-
ence betwixt His will and ours. But when we have reached
this point, do we feel that our inquiries are satisfied ? Is it
enough to say that such is the will of God, or such is the
law, to satisfy the demands of our moral nature ? Must we
not go further, and inquire into the grounds of that will ?
Is it arbitrary, capricious, and can moral distinctions be
created by a simple act of the Divine will considered with-
out reference to any ulterior ground or motive ? As moral
character in man depends upon dispositions and principles
back of his volitions, must there not be something analo-
gous in God, something in the very nature and grounds of
Lect. XIV.] THE STATE AND NATURE OF SIN. 357
His being wliich determines His will to command and for-
bid what it does ? Unquestionably there is ; it is the holi-
ness of the Divine nature, that essential rectitude of His
being, which constitutes His glory and without which we
could not conceive Him to be an object of worship or reve-
rential trust. Holiness is represented in the Scriptures as
the very life of God. In all other beings it is an accident
separable from the essence ; in God it is His very self It
pervades all His other attributes and perfections, and makes
them to be pre-eminently divine. His infinite knowledge,
tempered by his holiness, becomes wisdom. His infinite
power, wielded by this same holiness, becomes the guardian
of justice, truth and innocence. His infinite will, impreg-
nated with holiness, becomes the perfect standard of right-
eousness and duty. This perfection is God's crown and
glory, and hence sin appears as the contrast to God's holiness
and the coming short of God's glory. It
It is the contradic- . j. ' ^ ' ± • t t -,.
tion of God's holiness. ^^ uot Simply trausgrcssion, disobedience;
it is the want of holiness. These are all
Scripture determinations. They are derived from the com-
parison of man's character and life with an external stand-
ard ; they are objective representations of sin, and it is these
alone through which the conscience is first awakened and
man convinced of the evil that is in him.
But although these objective determinations are enough
for duty, they are not enough for speculation. They do not
satisfy the wants of science. We are impelled to go far-
ther and inquire whether there is any specific quality which
distinguishes sin, and by virtue of which all its forms and
manifestations can be reduced to unity. Let us, therefore
now notice its subjective determinations.
ive dTterJinationr ^^ fixiug thcsc, the first thing to be borne
in mind is the ethical ground of God's rio-ht
to the service of man. This ethical ground is the complete
dependence of man upon God. The creature lives only in
the will of the Creator, Its life, faculties and powers are
only continued expressions of the will that underlies them.
358 THE STATE AND NATURE OF SIN. [Lect. XIV.
The obvious relation implied in the term creature is that of
absolute dependence on the will of the Creator. In him-
self, man is nothing. He is something only in his relations
to the will of God. This gives to God an absolute right of
property in him. The true ethical ground, therefore, is
The true ethical i^^'^^^'s rcktion to God as the expression of
ground of right a